ebook img

The Religious and Philosophical Foundations and Apologetic Implications of George MacDonald's ... PDF

35 Pages·2016·0.27 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Religious and Philosophical Foundations and Apologetic Implications of George MacDonald's ...

Dissertation in Progress In this section of North Wind the editor highlights new scholars who are working on MacDonald at the Masters and Doctoral levels. “The Religious and Philosophical Foundation and Apologetic Implications of George MacDonald’s Mysticism” is a doctoral dissertation in the subject of Christian Spirituality at the University of South Africa. The Religious and Philosophical Foundations and Apologetic Implications of George MacDonald’s Mysticism Dean Hardy Table of Contents Introduction PART ONE: An Examination of George MacDonald’s Humble Beginnings and External Influences Chapter 1 George MacDonald: A Brief Biography 1.1 19th Century Scotland and Huntly’s Cultural and Religious Milieu 1.2 The MacDonald Family 1.3 Other Influences on MacDonald’s Thought 1.3.1 Religious: F.D. Maurice, Alexander John Scott, Dante, Origen 1.3.2 Philosophical: Plato, Plotinus, Schleiermacher, Kant, Schelling, Fichte, William Paley 1.3.3 Mystical: Jacob Boehme, Emanuel Swedenborg, William Law 1.3.4 Literary: Coleridge, Wordsworth, Shelley, Hoffman, and Novalis North Wind 34 (2015): 114-148 Religious and Philosophical Foundations 115 PART TWO: George MacDonald’s Philosophy and its Affect on His Mysticism Chapter 2 MacDonald’s Metaphysical Foundations 2.1 Living in a Shadow World, examining MacDonald’s ‘Temperamental Platonism’ 2.2 Ex Deo: Origen, Plotinus and MacDonald’s doctrine of Creation 2.3 “Participation” in the Divine Nature Chapter 3 Alethiology & Language 3.1 A Contrast of Propositional Truth with the Embodiment of Truth in Christ 3.2 MacDonald, Augustine, and Swedenborg: Symbols as the Conduit of Divine Truth Chapter 4 Epistemology and the Attainment of Knowledge 4.1 The Rejection of Plato’s Rationalism 4.2 Is there a Place for Empirical Science in MacDonald’s thought? 4.3 F.D. Maurice and A.J. Scott: the primacy of Revelation 4.4 MacDonald’s View of the Status and Role of the Holy Scriptures Chapter 5 An Outworking of MacDonald’s Philosophy on his Theology and Mysticism 5.1 Defining MacDonald as a ‘True Mystic’ 5.2 MacDonald’s utilization of Swedenborg’s Theory of Correspondences and Boehme’s Four Spiritual Dimensions PART THREE: The Apologetics of George MacDonald Chapter 6 Modern Implications for George MacDonald’s 19th 116 Hardy Century Apologetic 6.1 An Overview of 19th Century Apologetic Strategies 6.2 An Overview of Current, 21st Century Apologetic Strategies 6.3 Was George MacDonald an Apologist? 6.3.1 Rationalism, Romanticism, and ‘Spiritual Logic’ 6.4 An Analysis of MacDonald’s Intention, Purpose, and Overall Apologetic Goals 6.4.1 Symbols and Imagination as Apologetic Methodology 6.4.2 Spiritual Duty and Intellectual Assent 6.4.3 The Problem of Suffering: Plato, Schleiermacher, and MacDonald’s Theodicy. 6.5 The Application of MacDonald’s Apologetic to the Spiritual Climate of this Age Bibliography Religious and Philosophical Foundations 117 N ineteenth-century author George MacDonald has influenced some of the greatest writers of the past century. G.K. Chesterton (1905) stated, “George Macdonald was one of the three or four great men of 19th century Britain.” He even went so far to explain, “I for one can really testify to a book that has made a difference to my whole existence, which helped me to see things in a certain way from the start; a vision of things which even so real a revolution as a change of religious allegiance has substantially only crowned and confirmed. Of all the stories I ever read . . . it remains the most real, the most realistic, in the exact sense of the phrase the most like life. It is called The Princess and the Goblin, and is by George MacDonald.” The Oxford Companion to Children’s Literature mentions that MacDonald’s Princess and Goblin books were some of J.R.R. Tolkien’s childhood favorites, and even suggests, “The goblin mines beneath the Misty Mountains in The Hobbit owe much to it” (Carpenter and Prichard 1999:427). C.S. Lewis, on many occasions, identified MacDonald as his literary master and admitted, “I fancy I have never written a book in which I did not quote from him” (Lewis 1947:xxxvii). Oswald Chambers went so far as to write “it is a striking indication of the trend and shallowness of the modern reading public that George MacDonald’s books have been so neglected” (Chambers 1995:35). While George MacDonald maintained some national and even international success during the later parts of his career, this changed after his death in 1905. Likely due to the peculiarity and complexities of his work, his notoriety wandered off of the edge of the literary map. Chesterton predicted, “Dr. George MacDonald will be discovered some day . . . until then he will . . . be neglected, contemned, and quarried industriously by people who wish to borrow his ideas” (Chesterton 1905). G.K. Chesterton was a prophet. In the last thirty years there has been resurgence in the reading and subsequent scholarly research in the work of George MacDonald. While there seems to be an overwhelming amount of research from critics of the literary as well as the theological persuasion, there is a striking lack of exploration from the mystical, philosophical, and apologetic angle. These aspects of George MacDonald’s interior life are usually disregarded. While many scholars examine MacDonald through the lens of literature or theology, it has yet to be found where a scholar has researched his mysticism in any overt detail. G.K. Chesterton wrote of MacDonald, 118 Hardy “When he comes to be more carefully studied as a mystic, as I think he will be when people discover the possibility of collecting jewels scattered in a rather irregular setting, it will be found, I fancy, that he stands for a rather important turning-point in the history of Christendom” (2005:13). It is my contention that Chesterton’s suggestion has yet to be fully realized. Whether due to the anti-intellectualism that sometimes is associated with the study of “spirituality,” or due to the complex nature of MacDonald’s views, the well of his spiritual walk has been seldom tapped. Even more interestingly, the lack of scholarship on MacDonald’s mysticism can only be outdone by the absence of research on his underlying philosophical ideas. This lack of scholarship caused researcher and biographer Robert Trexler to write: “Not enough has been written of the theological and political debates of the nineteenth century, especially an exploration of the influence of MacDonald’s good friend and mentor, F.D. Maurice, who, after John Henry Newman is probably the most influential and prophetic theologian of the nineteenth century. However, the theological issues of the nineteenth century, as important and under-studied as they have been, still receive more attention than the philosophical debates upon which they rest” (Trexler 2003, italics mine). It is this missing scholarship from the philosophical, apologetic, and mystical angle that this study seeks to fulfill. PART II George MacDonald’s Philosophy and its Affect on his Mysticism “Novalis has said: ‘Philosophy is really homesickness, an impulse to be at home everywhere.’ The life of a man here, if life it be, and not the vain image of what might be a life, is a continual attempt to find his place, his center of recipiency, and active agency . . . [But] he is not at home; his soul is astray amid people of a strange speech and a stammering tongue. But the faithful man is led onward; in the stillness that his confidence produces arise the bright images of truth; and visions of God, which are only beheld in solitary places, and granted to his soul.” —George MacDonald (1895:211-12) Chapter Two MacDonald’s Metaphysical Foundations Section I: Living in a Shadow World: examining MacDonald’s “Temperamental Platonism” Religious and Philosophical Foundations 119 Section II: Ex Deo: Origen, Plotinus and MacDonald’s view of Creation. Section III: “Participation” in the Divine Nature Introduction The fact that the philosophy of MacDonald has rarely been researched is not due to a lack of willing hearts or uneducated researchers. It is likely due to the fact that even a tertiary student of MacDonald recognizes that he had a negative attitude toward the discipline. Bruce Hindmarsh stated that the “One thing he [MacDonald] never claimed to be . . . was a theologian” (Hindmarsh 1991:55). Hindmarsh is correct, but in addition, MacDonald also ignored the title of “philosopher” for the same reasons. This researcher contends that the motives for which MacDonald disliked both labels was not due to the disciplines in-and-of themselves, but rather the outworking of these fields of study on the religious culture and the personal spiritual lives of those who lived in the Victorian era. Thus, MacDonald’s reasons for dismissing these disciplines will be elucidated, as well as his belief that there is, in fact, a correct theology and philosophy. MacDonald never publically placed himself into any theological or philosophical system, and his reasons were primarily preventative and reactionary. MacDonald himself said in a letter to his father, “I am neither Arminian or Calvinist. To no system could I subscribe” (Beinecke: April 15, 1851) as well as saying “Jesus Christ is my theology, and nothing else” (Anonymous 2012:31). One of the reasons why he never sought to proclaim his systematized theology was that he was worried about being pigeonholed into one system of belief. He writes in his sermon entitled “Light,” “But if one happens to utter some individual truth which another man has made into one of the cogs of his system, he is in danger of being supposed to accept all the toothed wheels and their relations in that system” (MacDonald 2012a:250). MacDonald was concerned about being misconstrued and misinterpreted, and encouraged others to also eschew choosing a system of belief, “Therefore, if only to avoid his worst foes, his admirers, a man should avoid system. The more correct a system the worse will it be misunderstood; its professed admirers will take both its errors and their misconceptions of its truths, and hold them forth as its essence” (MacDonald 1882:332). Philosophy and theology did much during the Victorian period to divide and dis-unify the church until the body of Christ was barely recognizable. MacDonald (2012b:69) contends: 120 Hardy All those evil doctrines about God that work misery and madness, have their origin in the brains of the wise and prudent, not in the hearts of the children. These wise and prudent, careful to make the words of his messengers rime with their conclusions, interpret the great heart of God, not by their own hearts, but by their miserable intellects; and, postponing the obedience which alone can give power to the understanding, press upon men’s minds their wretched interpretations of the will of the Father, instead of the doing of that will upon their hearts. They call their philosophy the truth of God, and say men must hold it, or stand outside. They are the slaves of the letter in all its weakness and imperfection,—and will be until the spirit of the Word, the spirit of obedience shall set them free (italics mine). MacDonald concluded that to choose and broadcast a specific system or denomination would simply cause more division and detract from the gospel and the mere Christianity in which he advocated. MacDonald argued that, “Division has done more to hide Christ from the view of men, than all the infidelity that has ever been spoken” (MacDonald 2009d:192). He specifically pointed out the issue of divisiveness within the church: “The real schismatic is the man who turns away love and justice from the neighbour who holds theories in religious philosophy, or as to church-constitution, different from his own; who denies or avoids his brother because he follows not with him; who calls him a schismatic because he prefers this or that mode of public worship not his” (MacDonald 2012b:80). This concept struck close to MacDonald’s heart, for in the middle of the 19th century a small schism in his church in Arundel had charged him with heresy that eventually caused him to resign (Raeper 1987:90). Rolland Hein summarizes succinctly, “MacDonald, who would ally himself with no system, scorns the sectarian mentality that so vehemently expends its energies in futile clashes with those of opposing opinions” (Hein 1989:98). MacDonald was simply concerned that by proclaiming a philosophical or theological system, he’d be throwing fuel on a fire that he longed to extinguish. Thirdly, MacDonald truly believed that certain theologies, as well as an obsession for theological deliberation, could actually detract from one’s relationship with the Father and one’s duty to serve him. He argued that men have a habit of spending too much time focusing on their theology, and not enough on loving God and their fellow men, “Zeal for God will never eat them up; why should it? He is not interesting to them: theology may be; to Religious and Philosophical Foundations 121 such men religion means theology” (MacDonald 2012b:68). MacDonald goes so far as to specifically state, “I firmly believe that people have hitherto been a great deal too much taken up about doctrine and far too little about practice . . .” (Greville MacDonald 2005: 155). Not only was MacDonald worried that an infatuation with theology could poorly affect our praxis, but the theology itself could be faulty, and thus one’s view of God could poorly influence our relationship with him. Rolland Hein explains, “In many novels the chief deterrent to a successful journey toward a spiritual maturity is contact with false ideas about God’s character and manner of working in the world, particularly those fostered by mean and popular versions of Calvinist doctrines” (Hein 1989:120). George MacDonald did not pull punches when it came to certain theological beliefs; for instance, he goes so far as calling the doctrines of atonement and eternal torment, “doctrines of devils” (MacDonald 2012a,179). In Robert Falconer, MacDonald took aim at Calvinism, the creed of his youth: “For now arose within him, not without ultimate good, the evil phantasms of a theology which would explain all God’s doings by low conceptions, low I mean for humanity even, of right, and law, and justice, then only taking refuge in the fact of the incapacity of the human understanding when its own inventions are impugned as undivine. In such a system, hell is invariably the deepest truth, and the love of God is not so deep as hell. Hence, as foundations must be laid in the deepest, the system is founded in hell, and the first article in the creed that Robert Falconer learned was, “I believe in hell” (MacDonald 2005:98). There is also no doubt that MacDonald felt a calling to do damage to the prevailing systems of his day. One of his purposes was to “deliver the race from the horrors of such falsehoods, which by no means operate only on the vulgar and brutal, for to how many of the most refined and delicate of human beings are not their lives rendered bitter by the evil suggestions of lying systems--I care not what they are called--philosophy, religion, society, I care not?--to deliver men, I say, from such ghouls of the human brain, were indeed to have lived!” (MacDonald 2002:38). He believed, categorically, that Calvinism was a barricade to one’s relationship with God. The following assessment will be helpful in understanding the spirit of MacDonald’s stance. This review of one of MacDonald’s lectures in London from a direct, albeit anonymous observer (Anonymous 2012:30-1), was originally published in Christian World in 1882: It is the breaking up of old habits of theological thought, or the 122 Hardy exercise of a happy liberty in regard to it, that has prepared the way for a preacher who avows himself, as Dr. MacDonald did on Sunday, to be no theologian, but who feels that the truth of God is to be reached in other ways than by a theological key. There ought, indeed, to be nothing startling in this, for it is evident that souls did somehow find the truth of God before Christianity knew anything of scientific theology. That the formulating of the truth of the New Testament into a system has been helpful to some minds, there can be no doubt. But the transposing of “truth as it is in Jesus” into a system has also hindered some minds from getting at Christ Himself, they having rested in the system, and only comprehend as much of Christ as they could see through the system. Thus, theological systems could cloud the lenses of one’s faith in Christ and MacDonald felt that it was his job to clean the lens. While it is obvious that he spoke negatively about these disciplines, and even claimed not to espouse a particular belief system, to argue that he did not have a philosophy or theology is simply nonsensical. Just because MacDonald did not like the title of “philosopher” or “theologian” does not mean that he was not one. If we are to take the words of Francis Schaeffer seriously, we should argue that all rational beings are philosophers, “No man can live without a worldview; therefore there is no man who is not a philosopher” (Schaeffer 2001:4). The central difficulty with arguing that MacDonald was not a theologian resides in the fact that in order for MacDonald to be able to point out the falsity of any system, which he did on many occasions, he must purport to know the truth. MacDonald argued this point himself in his sermon ‘The Last Farthing,’ “. . . any system which tends to persuade men that there is any salvation but that of becoming righteous even as Jesus is righteous; that a man can be made good, as a good dog is good, without his own willed share in the making; that a man is saved by having his sins hidden under a robe of imputed righteousness—that system, so far as this tendency, is of the devil and not of God. Thank God, not even error shall injure the true of heart; it is not wickedness. They grow in the truth, and as love casts out fear, so truth casts out falsehood” (MacDonald 2012a:125, italics mine). This casting out of falsehood was the first step to replacing the erroneous view of God with the truth. The difference between MacDonald and his counterparts is that he would rather the reader seek the truth on his own, rather than have MacDonald force-feed them his own personal Religious and Philosophical Foundations 123 views. So, it is no surprise when he writes, “I know, however, that there were words in it which found their way to my conscience; and, let men of science or philosophy say what they will, the rousing of a man’s conscience is the greatest event in his existence” (MacDonald 2009e:173). But for MacDonald himself, his conscience had been raised, and he did, in fact, purport to have a proper philosophical and theological underpinnings. The simplest way of reporting this fact is to recognize when he, in fact, agreed with certain scholars’ points of view. He states succinctly in the Tragedie of Hamlet, “Note the unity of religion and philosophy in Hamlet: he takes the one true position” (MacDonald 1885:265). Now he does not argue this fact because he merely believes that Shakespeare’s Hamlet is correct because he aligns with MacDonald, but even more importantly, he believes that Hamlet aligns with God’s own philosophy. MacDonald stated, “Matter, time, space, are all God’s, and whatever may become of our philosophies, whatever he does with or in respect of time, place, and what we call matter, his doing must be true in philosophy as well as fact” (MacDonald 2002:424). Therefore, God has a philosophy, Hamlet aligned with this philosophy, and MacDonald understands and agrees with this alignment. But in order to make this assessment he must have concluded that he had the correct philosophical and religious position in the first place. To give another example of MacDonald’s affirmation of a philosophical position, take this passage in England’s Antiphon, “Dr. Henry More was . . . chiefly known for his mystical philosophy, which he cultivated in retirement at Cambridge, and taught not only in prose, but in an elaborate, occasionally poetic poem . . . Whatever may be thought of his theories, they belong at least to the highest order of philosophy; and it will be seen from the poems I give that they must have borne their part in lifting the soul of the man towards a lofty spiritual condition of faith and fearlessness. The mystical philosophy seems to me safe enough in the hands of a poet: with others it may degenerate into dank and dusty materialism” (MacDonald 1996:223). In the following pages, this researcher will proceed with the same spirit as MacDonald in his elevation of Dr. More’s mystical philosophy. Even while MacDonald occasionally downplayed the role of philosophy, he absolutely asked and discussed questions of a metaphysical nature. Adelheid Kegler goes so far to say that “MacDonald’s oeuvre is conceived in a dynamic and dialectic analysis of the central problems of modern philosophy” (Kegler 2003:19). MacDonald elucidated his philosophical positions on reality, truth, and knowledge; specifically discussed in his Dish

Description:
“Participation” in the Divine Nature. Chapter 3 Alethiology & Language. 3.1 A Contrast of Propositional Truth with the Embodiment of. Truth in Christ.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.