ebook img

The Philosophical and Theological Foundations of Ethics: An Introduction to Moral Theory and its Relation to Religious Belief PDF

177 Pages·1992·9.446 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Philosophical and Theological Foundations of Ethics: An Introduction to Moral Theory and its Relation to Religious Belief

THE PHILOSOPHICAL AND THEOLOGICAL FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS Also by Peter Byrne ETHICS AND LAW IN HEALTH CARE AND RESEARCH (editor) HEALTH, RIGHTS AND RESOURCES (editor) MEDICINE IN CONTEMPORARY SOCIETY (editor) MEDICINE, MEDICAL ETHICS AND THE VALUES OF LIFE (editor) NATURAL RELIGION AND THE NATURE OF RELIGION RELIGION DEFINED AND EXPLAINED (with Peter Clarke) RIGHTS AND WRONGS IN MEDICINE (editor) The Philosophical and Theological Foundations of Ethics An Introduction to Moral Theory and its Relation to Religious Belief PETER BYRNE Lecturer in the Philosophy of Religion King's College, London M St. Martin's Press © Peter Byrne 1992 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1992 997788--00--333333--5555449944--44 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Tottenham Court Road, London W1P 9HE. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. First published in Great Britain 1992 by THE MACMILLAN PRESS LTD Hound mills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 2XS and London Companies and representatives throughout the world A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN 978-1-349-39029-8 ISBN 978-0-230-37646-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/9780230376465 First published in the United States of America 1992 by Scholarly and Reference Division, ST. MARTIN'S PRESS, INC., 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 ISBN 978-0-312-07937-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Byrne, Peter, 1950- The philosophical and theoloigical foundations of ethics: an introduction to moral theory and its relation to religious belief I Peter Byrne. p. em. Includes bibliographical references and index. IISSBBNN 997788--00--331122--0077993377--66 1. Ethics. 2. Religion and ethics. I. Title. BJ1012.B97 1992 170-dc20 91-44846 CIP Contents Preface vi 1 The Nature and Objectivity of Morality 1 2 Conscience, Moral Experience and Moral Theory 21 3 The Moral Structure of Action 40 4 Consequentialist Moral Theory 63 5 Deontological Moral Theory 86 6 Aretaic Moral Theory 108 7 Morality without Religion 129 8 Morality with Religion 145 Works Cited 163 Index 166 v Preface This book is intended as an introductory survey of moral philosophy with a particular emphasis on the relationship between morality and religious belief. The aim is to explain and discuss some of the major issues in moral philosophy, tracing, as the account proceeds, their implications for an understanding of how religion might bear on ethics. The book is meant therefore to be of particular help to students of moral theology and religious studies who need an introduction to moral theory. One way in which such students meet moral philosophy nowadays is in the context of practical ethics. It has come to be assumed that in fields such as medical ethics it is essential to know moral philosophy and moral theory in order to discuss practical moral problems. Hence, we have the coinage 'philosophical medical ethics' -used to characterise critical thinking about the ethics of medical practice. I have written with one eye on the notion that moral philosophy is the foundational discipline in practical ethics. During the course of my argument I shall suggest that there are grave limitations in this idea, arising out of the nature of moral knowledge. But there are some lessons to be learnt from moral philosophy for practical ethics, and I have drawn them when appropriate. Readers should be warned that this study is biased in certain directions. Its interest in morality's relation to religion inclines it to objectivism in ethics and to giving, from the start, an account of moral knowledge and moral experience which will make dialogue between secular and religious moral thinkers intelligible. Its lack of neutrality is I hope compensated by the fact that it offers an argument for a positive, distinctive view of the nature of moral thought, so that at least those who disagree with this view will see what has to be defended and attacked if it is to work at all. In the interests of getting on with an uncluttered argument and exposition I have kept references and textual notes to a minimum. Before the rise of interest in practical ethics in philosophy depart ments it was common to find moral philosophy characterised as a purely formal, 'second-order' discipline. Some argue that it has no concern with the content of moral judgement but merely with the formal structure of moral argument and experience. It does not seek vi Preface vii to know what is good but rather what the meaning of 'good' and related words might be. Such a characterisation of the subject is sat isfactory only in so far as there is an intelligible distinction between form and content in morals. Moral philosophy has traditionally had other tasks, notably the discovery and examination of the most basic goods, virtues and moral principles. In the course of this 'first-order' task moral philosophers past and present perforce offer comment on the nature and distinguishing features of moral judgement but they go beyond comment on the 'form' of ethics. There is every reason to persevere with this second, older characterisation of the moral philosopher's task. It is truer to the history of the subject and reflects even contemporary practice better. Even the strictest formalists in modem moral philosophy have found it hard to refrain from drawing implications from their accounts of the meaning of moral judgement for the nature of the most basic goods, virtues and principles of right. There appears reason to expect that any account of the form of morality will set limits upon, or suggest requirements for, an acceptable content of morality. The above registers the conviction that the distinction between form and content in morality is a hazy one at best. Students should be particularly wary, in my view, of the vision of the subject which ties it to description of the special features of 'the language of morals', as if moral philosophy's task were the tracking down of a special type of meaning and a special type of vocabulary peculiar to morals. While this might lead to a sharp distinction between second and first-order reflections on morals, there is ground to question whether there is any special form of meaning attaching to words in moral contexts. Moreover, though there are terms characteristic of moral judgement (such as the words for the human virtues), many words used in moral discussion are equally at home outside it (see Wertheimer 1972 for well-argued doubts about whether there is a 'language of morals'). Morality as conceived in this book is a body of knowledge about how human beings ought to act. Moral philosophy has the task of setting out the structure of this body of knowledge and outlining its leading principles and ideas. Some might think that this begs straightaway the question of whether an objectivist or subjectivist account of moral thought is correct. The reasoning behind a subjec tivist portrayal of morals will be discussed in Chapter 1. But we can see at once that any thinker who takes the possibility of a religious basis to ethics seriously has strong ground for assuming that such viii Preface reasoning is fallacious and that only the view that morality is a branch genuine knowledge will do. It cannot be denied that there are subjectivist accounts of morals which try to establish an intelligible link between religion and ethics (Braithwaite 1966 is a clear if simple example). Yet there will always be a substantial cost to embracing subjectivism in ethics from within a religious outlook. It will entail a corresponding subjectivism in doctrine and related problems in the conception of the sacred. It is one of humanity's key ideas about the sacred that it is worthy of devotion or worship and is in some manner the source of moral and other values. It is difficult to entertain the thought that value is some form of human invention or projection and not draw the consequence that divinity is likewise a humanly produced fiction. If I take away from my conception of divinity all that contains judgements of value, on the ground that such judgements are in no real sense objectively true or known to be true, then what is left will hardly be intelligible as a portrayal of the independently sacred.ln consistency an account of the sacred as a human projection must follow, and while such accounts can indeed be found they are hard to reconcile with traditional belief or with the task of doctrinal reflection (compare Cupitt 1980). Whether or not morality is dependent on religion we shall discuss in Chapter 7 and 8, but it certainly appears a~ if religion is dependent on morality to the extent that if the idea of moral truth is an illusion, then so is that of religious truth. 1 The Nature and Objectivity of Morality THE FORM OF MORALITY One of the crucial tasks of moral philosophy appears to be that of defining morality. This might be one early way in which reflection on the form of morals suggests limits to its content. The customary understanding of what morality is might indeed rule out various modes of thought and action as options for ethics. Though inviting, this method for quickly narrowing our sights in the search for the fundamentals of ethics is open to objection. It is evidently wrong to settle substantive questions on important topics by definitional fiat or appeal to ordinary usage. Somehow we must balance our proper search for an initial definition of morality with the need not to beg important questions. It is right to look to the definition of morality for hints in structuring enquiry into the nature of moral knowledge, while seeing any principles that definition yields as rebuttable and in need of independent justifica tion should they prove controversial in later passages of argument. For example, I shall indicate below how a certain conception of morality's universality is implicit in its customary definition and how this conception entails prima facie problems for the view that moral knowledge depends on religious knowledge. This will not settle questions about the relationship of religion to morality by itself. But it will draw our attention to a range of human experience which counts against some accounts of that relationship. By 'morality' we do not mean in this study customary, established thought about conduct and our enquiry into the relation between religion and morality does not concern the historical or sociological facts about the influence of religion on behaviour. It is assumed here that within the history of customary moral ideas we can find 1

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.