Lilia Schürcks, Anastasia Giannakidou, and Urtzi Etxeberria (Eds.) The Nominal Structure in Slavic and Beyond Studies in Generative Grammar Editors Henk can Riemsdijk Harry van der Hulst Jan Koster Volume 116 The Nominal Structure in Slavic and Beyond Edited by Lilia Schürcks Anastasia Giannakidou Urtzi Etxeberria ISBN 978-1-61451-388-9 e-ISBN 978-1-61451-279-0 ISSN 0167-4331 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the internet at http://dnb.dnb.de © 2014 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston Typesetting: PTP-Berlin Protago-TEX-Production GmbH, Berlin Printing: Hubert & Co. GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ♾ Printed on acid free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Table of Contents Lilia Schürcks, Anastasia Giannakidou, Urtzi Etxeberria Nominal Arguments and the role of D: an introduction | 1 Larisa Zlatić Definiteness and Structure of NPs in Slavic | 17 Miloje Despić Intensifiers, Focus, and Clitics: Is Pronoun Position Truly an Argument for D in SC? | 39 Željko Bošković Phases beyond Clauses | 75 Steven Franks The Slovenian Orphan Accusative, Empty Pronouns and Noun Phrase Structure | 129 Franc Marušič & Rok Žaucer A Definite Article in the AP – Evidence from Colloquial Slovenian | 183 Pavel Caha The Jungle of the Czech Local Cases: Where Semantics and Morphology Meet | 209 Iliyana Krapova and Guglielmo Cinque The Case for Genitive Case in Bulgarian | 237 Ilse Zimmermann Reciprocity Expressions | 275 Melita Stavrou About the Vocative | 299 Gilbert C. Rappaport Determiner Phrases and Mixed Agreement in Slavic | 343 VI Table of Contents Lilia Schürcks Syntax Presupposes, Morphology Disposes: Markedness and NP Typology | 391 Urtzi Etxeberria & Anastasia Giannakidou D-heads, domain restriction, and variation: From Greek and Basque to Salish | 413 Peter Kosta and Anton Zimmerling Slavic Clitic Systems in a Typological Perspective | 441 Lilia Schürcks, Anastasia Giannakidou, Urtzi Etxeberria Nominal Arguments and the role of D: an introduction 1 QPs, DPs, and definiteness This book is a study of how nominal arguments are made up. The papers in this collection address, in one way or another, the questions of what the basic ingre- dients of the nominal argument are, and whether there are any crosslinguistic generalizations to be made about potential universals within the constituent tra- ditionally known as the ‘noun phrase’. In type theoretic approaches – which lie at the foundation of the syntax- semantics mapping assumed in linguistic theory today – nominal arguments are quantificational (type et,t) , or referential (type e). Regarding quantificational types, one of the most fruitful ideas in formal semantics has been the idea that quantifier phrases (QPs) denote generalized quantifiers (GQs; Montague 1974, Barwise & Cooper 1981, Zwarts 1986, Westerståhl 1985, Partee 1987, Keenan 1987, 1996, Keenan & Westerståhl 1997, among many others). Generalized Quan- tifier Theory (GQT) offered a solid framework for the study of quantificational structures in English, and initiated a research agenda which soon expanded to study quantificational patterns crosslinguistically (culminating, e.g. in the volume of Bach et al. 1995, and the more recent Matthewson 2008, Giannaki- dou and Rathert 2009, Szabolcsi 2010, and Keenan & Paperno 2011, Gil et. al 2013). The research of the past 20 years revealed a spectacular variation in the patterns of quantification across languages, suggesting that some fine-tuning, or even more radical modifications, of the classical theory are necessary. Most discussions of crosslinguistic variation revolve around identifying what the building blocks of quantificational phrases are, whether there is a “universal” QP structure, and what the mapping is between the morphological pieces in the QP and the semantic or pragmatic functions they may perform. Classical GQT posits that there is a natural class of expressions in language, called quantifica- tional determiners (Qs), which combine with a nominal (NP) constituent of type et, a first order predicate, to form a quantificational argumental nominal (QP). This QP denotes a GQ, a set of sets. In a language like English, the syntax of a QP like every woman is as follows. (1) a. [[every woman]] = λP. ∀x. woman (x) → P(x) b. [[every]] = λP. λQ. ∀x. P(x) → Q(x) 2 Lilia Schürcks, Anastasia Giannakidou, Urtzi Etxeberria c. QP 〈〈e, t〉, t〉 Q NP 〈〈e, t〉, 〈〈e, t〉,t〉〉 〈e, t〉 every woman : λx. woman (x) In the structure in (1), the Q every combines with the NP argument woman and creates an argument that denotes a generalized quantifier. The NP argument pro- vides the domain of the Q, and the Q expresses a relation between this domain and the set denoted by the VP.¹ Another item that combines with a domain set of type et to give a nominal argument is the definite determiner – the article the and its equivalents, e.g. a demonstrative pronoun. Hellan (1986), Abney (1987) and Bowers (1987) pro- posed a functional category Determiner (D) as the head of the noun phrase, making the noun phrase a ‘doubly-headed’ construction (cf. example (2)), i.e. D takes NP as its complement. The definite article is usually designated as D (Abney 1987; see Alexiadou, Haegeman, & Stavrou 2008 for an extensive recent over- view), and the demonstrative is generated in English under the same head (thus *this the book) – echoing the semantic view of definiteness as including both the and this (e.g. Roberts 2002, 2003, 2010). The DP has a structure parallel to (1), only that in this case the Q is D, and the constituent is called DP (though some authors call the Q position uniformly D position; cf. Matthewson 1998, Gillon 2009). As indicated below, the DP produces typically a referential expression, a (maximal or unique) individual indicated here with iota: (2) DP, e: ι (λx. woman (x)) D NP 〈〈e, t〉,t〉 〈e, t〉 {the/this} woman : λx. woman (x) 1 Qs like every, most, etc. are known as ‘strong’ (Milsark 1977), as opposed to some, three, many which are called “weak” etc (see e.g. discussions in the paper in Reuland and ter Meulen 1991). Strong quantifiers and definite descriptions (to be discussed next) have been claimed to not occur easily in the so-called existential constructions, but McNally (1992, 2009), and more recently Francez (2007, 2009) have questioned this generalization, so we will not make much of it here. Nominal Arguments and the role of D: an introduction 3 Demonstratives come with additional presuppositions of maximal salience or proximity to the addressee or the speaker, cf. Alexiadou, Haegeman, & Stavrou 2008; cf. also Roberts 2010). The DP produces the most basic argument e –which can be lifted up to the GQ type when necessary (in type shifiting theories such as Partee 1987). Both D and Q are functions that need a domain, and the NP pro- vides that domain. The definite D, in languages that have it, is the most basic syntactic closure devise: it creates an argument of the simplest type (e). So, in languages that have the definite article, the device is necessary for argument- hood, and these languages do not allow bare nominals to function as arguments (*Boy ate a sandwich). The notion of definiteness, then, appears to be closely related to the use of a definite determiner (be it a definite determiner or a demonstrative) in the syn- tactic position D combined with a nominal expression to produce a basic, refer- ential argument. However, having a definite article is not a universal property of languages. Many languages in the Slavic family, the main focus of this book, are articleless. We see this in the example in (3) from Serbo-Croatian. Only Bulgarian and the closely related Macedonian have articles. (3) a. Kamen je razbio prozor. (Serbo-Croatian) stone is broken window ‘The stone broke the window’ b. Kamŭkŭt razbi prozoreca. (Bulgarian) stone-the broke window-the ‘The stone broke the window’ In the articleless languages, the definite or indefinite interpretation of bare nominal expressions depends on the context in which they are used and on the word order of the constituents as well as on the position in which they appear in a sentence, i.e. nominals are more easily interpreted as definites in preverbal position while nominals in postverbal position get usually an indefinite interpre- tation. If this is the case, and if – despite the absence of D – nominals of Slavic lan- guages are able to function as arguments and obtain a referential, definite inter- pretation, the following question becomes pressing: if D is the element respon- sible for definiteness and argumenthood crosslinguistically, but Slavic languages possess no definite determiner, then how come these bare Slavic nominals end up being definite and referential? Some authors answer this question by suggesting that the DP hypothesis applies universally and argue that in Slavic languages, in order for the nominal expression to obtain a definite interpretation it is necessary
Description: