The focus of this book is Artistotle's theory of virtue. Unlike traditional accounts of Aristotelian virtue, Nancy Sherman claims that excellence of character is not a merely habituated, affective state, but a state constituted by the operations of practical reason. In particular, she considers four aspects of practical reason as they relate to character: namely, moral perception, choicemaking, collaboration, and the development of those capacities in moral education. The inclusion of moral perception as a moment of practical reason suggests that an adequate account of practical reason begins not with the question, how should I act given some end, but rather with the acknowledgement that some end is here and now relevant to the particulars. Composing the scene is thus as much a part of the projection of character as deciding how ultimately to act. And this, Sherman argues, has been ignored in traditional accounts of the practical syllogism. In both deciding what to do and how to construe circumstances, our capacities are enlarged by the collaborative efforts of others with whom we share a life. This social dimension has a place in moral education, but more generally, in the planning and living out of a good life. Finally, the account of character has implications for Aristotle's theory of moral education. Contrary to the popular interpretation in which ethical habituation is non-rational, Sherman's claim is that the cognitive skills requisite for mature character are cultivated earlier on as a part of the shaping of emotions and desires. Throughout the arguments of this book, the author is sensitive to contemporary moral debates, and indicates the extent to which Artistotle's account of practical reason provides an alternative to theories of impartial reason. Nancy Sherman is Associate Professor of Philosophy, Yale University. Jacket illustration by Meryl Friedman Blinder THE FABRIC OF CHARACTER The Fabric of Character ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF VIRTUE N aney Sherman CLARENDONPRESS·OXFORD 1989 Oxford University Press, Walton Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford New York Toronto Delhi Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi Petaling Jaya Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo Nairobi Dar es Salaam Cape Town Melbourne Auckland and associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Oxford is a trade mark of Oxford University Press Published in the United States by Oxford University Press, New York © Nancy Sherman 1989 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Sherman, Nancy Thefabric of character: Aristotle's theory of virtue. I. Ethics. Theories of Aristotle, 384-322 B.C. 1. Title 170'.92' 4 ISBN 0-1,)-824451-7 Library of Congress Catliloging in Publication Data Sherman,Nancy,I951- Thefabric of character: Aristotle's theory of virtue I Nancy Sherman. Includes index. I. Aristotle-Ethics. 2. Virtue-History. 3. Character-History. 1. Title. B491. V57S52 1989 171'.3-dc19 88-29109 CIP ISBN 0-19-824451-7 Set by Oxford Text System Printed in Great Britain at the University Printing House, Oxford by David Stanford Printer to the University For M arshall PREFACE ARISTOTLE'S ethical theory has enjoyed a resurgence of interest of late. The ancient idea that ethical theory is about how to lead a good life, and that such a life will express the emotions as well as reason, has found a sympathetic ear in many. I am among these, and the aim of this work is to capture the way in which the sentiments and p.ractical reason together constitute character. The work, in some sense, began life as a thesis submitted for my Ph.D. at Harvard in 1982. At the time, I was struck by the fact that discussions of Aristotle's theory of virtues often side-stepped an account of their acquisition, Two notable exceptions were articles by Burnyeat and Sorabji,l but on the whole the idea of moral habituation as a kind of non-cognitive practice was unquestioningly accepted. The aim of the thesis was to debunk this view, both as an interpretation of Aristotle and as a plausible theory in its own right. Little of the thesis survives in this present book, but the motivating idea, to demonstrate that character is inseparable from the operations of practical reason, remains. In writing a book on Aristotle, I have felt acutely the problem of Aristotle's inherent sexism, and have struggled with the awkward issue of just how to allow women into the ranks of the decent and wise. I have not come to any ready solution, and, perhaps with some anachronism, have in the end allowed myself to use women as well as men as the subjects of my examples, moving freely between the masculine and feminine pronoun. For my own process of writing and interpretation, this seemed to be necessary and crucial for sympathetic appreciation of the theory. If not 1 Myles Burnyeat, 'Aristotle on Learning to be Good', in A. O. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics (University of California Press, 1980), 69-92; Richard Sorabji, 'Aristotle on the Role of Intellect in Virtue', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 74 (1973-4), 107-29, repr. in Rorty, 201-19. Preface VU1 abetted by Aristotle, it seems at least within his own dictum of allowing time to be a co-partner in and co-discoverer of the details of his theory (NE I098a22). Where appropriate, I have examined in some detail Aristotle's position on women, and, especially in the case of their role as moral tutors within the family, have pointed to inconsistencies in his views. MallY people have helped at different stages in the growth of this book, and to all of them I owe my gratitude. My deepest debt is to Martha Nussbaum. As a teacher and thesis supervisor at Harvard she was everything a graduate student could want, and more. Her interest never flagged, and her vigilant supervision at all stages of the thesis was incomparable. At later stages of the book, too, she was a careful critic. Indeed, it would be hard to imagine acknowledging my debt to her in any brief space. For coming to understand Aristotle's place in the larger sweep of moral philosophy, I owe deep appreciation to my second thesis supervisor, John Rawls. His writing, and his remarkable lectures in moral philosophy, have remained the foundation of my own education in that subject. His force ful defence of Kantian ethics compelled me then (and now) to take seriously the challenge Kant poses to Aristotelian theory. Many thanks are also due to Steven Strange, who read the thesis, and who offered helpful criticisms along the way. The book began life again at Yale, and benefited from the various seminars at which its ideas were developed. To the many students whose discussions helped to shape this book, I am most grateful. I also owe thanks to my Yale colleagues for their encouragement and support of my work. John Fischer's careful reading of earlier drafts of two chapters led to substantial improvements, and conversations with Sarah Waterlow Broadie clarified my own thinking about difficult issues in Aristotle's theory. Both R. 1. G. Hughes and Giovanni Ferrari read and commented on several chapters of the book, and I am thankful for their interest. To Ruth Marcus, for her steady encouragement and warmth over the past six years, I owe special thanks.
Description: