ebook img

The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas about Probability, Induction and Statistical Inference Cambridge Series on Statistical & Probabilistic Mathematics PDF

223 Pages·2009·1.47 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas about Probability, Induction and Statistical Inference Cambridge Series on Statistical & Probabilistic Mathematics

THE EMERGENCE OF PROBABILITY Second Edition Historical records show that there was no real concept of probability in Europe before the mid-seventeenth century, although the use of dice and other randomizing objects was commonplace. Ian Hacking here presents a philosophical critique of early ideas about probability, induction, and statistical inference and the growth of this new family of ideas in the fifteenth, sixteenth, and seventeenth centuries. The contemporary debates center around figures such as Pascal, Leibniz, and Jacques Bernoulli. What brought about the change in ideas? Hacking invokes a wider intellectual framework involving the growth of science, economics, and the theology of the period. He argues that the transformations that made it possible for probability concepts to emerge have constrained all subsequent development of probability theory and determine the space within which philosophical debate on the subject is still conducted. This book was first published in 1975, when it opened up a whole new field of historical and philosophical studies of the very idea of probability. This edition includes a new introduction in which Hacking explains how Michel Foucault’s ‘archaeology’ enabled him to do this. It concludes with reflections on the immense body of work done by others after the first publication of this book. Ian Hacking is Professor Emeritus at the Collège de France (Chair of philosophy and history of scientific concepts) and University Professor Emeritus at the University of Toronto. His many books include Representing and Intervening, Probability and Inductive Logic, Rewriting the Soul, Mad Travelers, Historical Ontology, and The Social Construction of What? The Modern Library included Hacking’s The Taming of Chance – a sequel to Emergence – in its list of 100 best non-fiction works published in the twentieth century. THE EMERGENCE OF PROBABILITY A PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY OF EARLY IDEAS ABOUT PROBABILITY, INDUCTION AND STATISTICAL INFERENCE Second Edition IAN HACKING CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo, Mexico City Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521866552 © Ian Hacking 1975, 2006 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1975 Second edition first published 2006 Reprinted 2007 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Hacking, Ian. The emergence of probability: a philosophical study of early ideas about probability, induction, and statistical inference / Ian Hacking. - 2nd ed. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-52186655-2 ISBN-10: 0-521-86655-3 ISBN-13: 978-0-521-68557-3 (pbk.) ISBN-10: 0-521-68557-5 (pbk.) 1. Probabilities - History. 2. Induction (Mathematics) - History. 3. Mathematical statistics - History. I. Title. QA273.H22 2006 519.209 - dc22 2006040643 ISBN 978-0-52186655-2 Hardback ISBN 978-0-521-68557-3 Paperback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. Information regarding prices, travel timetables, and other factual information given in this work is correct at the time of first printing but Cambridge University Press does not guarantee the accuracy of such information thereafter. FOR DANIEL CONTENTS Introduction 2006 1 An absent family of ideas Although dicing is one of the oldest of human pastimes, there is no known mathematics of randomness until the Renaissance. None of the explanations of this fact is compelling. 2 Duality Probability, as we now conceive it, came into being about 1660. It was essentially dual, on the one hand having to do with degrees of belief, on the other, with devices tending to produce stable long-run frequencies. 3 Opinion In the Renaissance, what was then called ‘probability’ was an attribute of opinion, in contrast to knowledge, which could only be obtained by demonstration. A probable opinion was not one supported by evidence, but one which was approved by some authority, or by the testimony of respected judges. 4 Evidence Until the end of the Renaissance, one of our concepts of evidence was lacking: that by which one thing can indicate, contingently, the state of something else. Demonstration, versimilitude and testimony were all familiar concepts, but not this further idea of the inductive evidence of things, 5 Signs Probability is a child of the low sciences, such as alchemy or medicine, which had to deal in opinion, whereas the high sciences, such as astronomy or mechanics, aimed at demonstrable knowledge. A chief concept of the low sciences was, that of the sign, here described in some detail. Observation of signs was conceived of as reading testimony. Signs were more or less reliable. Thus on the one hand a sign made an opinion probable (in the old sense of Chapter 3) because it was furnished by the best testimony of all. On the other hand, signs could be assessed by the frequency with which they spoke truly. At the end of the Renaissance, the sign was transformed into the concept of evidence described in Chapter 4. This new kind of evidence conferred probability on propositions, namely made them worthy of approval. But it did so in virtue of the frequency with which it made correct predictions. This transformation from sign into evidence is the key to the emergence of a concept of probability that is dual in the sense of Chapter 2. 6 The first calculations Some isolated calculations on chances, made before 1660, are briefly described. 7 The Roannez circle (1654) Some problems solved by Pascal set probability rolling. From here until Chapter 17 Leibniz is used as a witness to the early days of probability theory. 8 The great decision (1658?) ‘Pascal’s wager’ for acting as if one believed in God is the first well-understood contribution to decision theory. 9 The art of thinking (1662) Something actually called ‘probability’ is first measured in the Port Royal Logic, which is also one of the first works to distinguish evidence, in the sense of Chapter 4, from testimony. The new awareness of probability, evidence and conventional (as opposed to natural) sign, is illustrated by work of Wilkins, first in 1640, before the emergence of probability, and then in 1668, after the emergence. 10 Probability and the law (1665) While young and ignorant of the Paris developments Leibniz proposed to measure degrees of proof and right in law on a scale between 0 and 1, subject to a crude calculation of what he called ‘probability’. 11 Expectation (1657) Huygens wrote the first printed textbook of probability using expectation as the central concept. His justification of this concept is still of interest. 12 Political arithmetic (1662) Graunt drew the first detailed statistical inferences from the bills of mortality for the city of London, and Petty urged the need for a central statistical office. 13 Annuities (1671) Hudde and de Witt used Dutch annuity records to infer a mortality curve on which to work out the fair price for an annuity. 14 Equipossibility (1678) The definition of probability as a ratio among ‘equally possible cases’ originates with Leibniz. The definition, unintelligible to us, was natural at the time, for possibility was either de re (about things) or de dicto (about propositions). Probability was likewise either about things, in the frequency sense, or about propositions, in the epistemic sense. Thus the duality of probability was preserved by the duality of possibility. 15 Inductive logic Leibniz anticipated Carnap’s notion of inductive logic. He could do so because of the central place occupied by the concept of possibility in his scheme of metaphysics. Within that scheme, a global system of inductive logic makes more sense than Carnap’s does in our modern metaphysics. 16 The art of conjecturing (1692[?] published 1713) The emergence of probability is completed with Jacques Bernoulli’s book, which both undertakes a self-conscious analysis of the concept of probability, and proves the first limit theorem. 17 The first limit theorem The possible interpretations of Bernoulli’s theorem are described. 18 Design The English conception of probability in the early eighteenth century, guided by the Newtonian philosophy espoused by members of the Royal Society, interprets the stability of stochastic processes proven by the limit theorems as evidence of divine design. 19 Induction (1737) Hume’s sceptical problem of induction could not have arisen much before 1660, for there was no concept of inductive evidence in terms of which to raise it. Why did it have to wait until 1737? So long as it was still believed that demonstrative knowledge was possible, a knowledge in which causes were proved from first principles, then Hume’s argument could always be stopped. It was necessary that the distinction between opinion and knowledge should become a matter of degree. That means that high distinction between opinion and knowledge should become a matter of degree. That means that high and low science had to collapse into one another. This had been an ongoing process throughout the seventeenth century. It was formalized by Berkeley who said that all causes were merely signs. Causes had been the prerogative of high science, and signs the tool of the low. Berkeley identified them and Hume thereby became possible. Bibliography Index INTRODUCTION 2006: THE ARCHAEOLOGY OF PROBABLE REASONING After 1975: histories of probability and statistics This book happened to be the first in a wave of new studies of probability and its past. Such work was soon to be cultivated by a research group at the Zentrum für interdisziplinäre Forshchung in Bielefeld, 1982–3. Lorenz Krüger gathered together twenty-odd scholars, many of them young and working on their first major project. Such groups seldom gel. Krüger’s did – thanks to his planning and leadership, and his own exceptional character. The subject was changed permanently, and not only by the in-house publications emanating from Bielefeld.1 New benchmarks were established, starting with books by members of the group: Ted Porter’s The Rise of Statistical Thinking 1820–1900 (Princeton 1986), Steve Stigler’s The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900 (Chicago 1986), Raine Daston’s Classical Probability in the Enlightenment (Princeton 1988). Add in my own Taming of Chance (Cambridge 1990) and you have the start of an amazing little library. Doubtless the take-off in history would have occurred without this collective activity. Much of the work published directly after 1983 was already in preparation before Lorenz brought us together in Bielefeld. Donald Mackenzie had already written Statistics in Britain 1865–1930: The Social Construction of Scientific Knowledge (Edinburgh 1981). And I should mention an amusing reminder that many more minds were out there. English-speakers at Bielefeld met regularly to try to improve our German. We mostly read lesser works of Robert Musil, under the guidance of Christa Krüger. We never thought about how probability and The Man without Qualities might be connected. It was left to Jacques Bouveresse’s amazing book to show us what had been before our faces.2 Bielefeld was an extraordinary catalyst, and I am enormously grateful for having had the opportunity to work with such colleagues. Since then, histories of probability have become part of the history of science, and of science studies more generally. Cultural studies have become aware. This is hardly surprising, for probability is part of how we think about our chancy world. Literary critics are beginning to acknowledge that fact. The writing has been on the wall for some time. The last chapter of Taming ended by invoking Mallarmé’s poem of 1897, A throw of the die, which begins by swearing that we ‘NEVER will annul chance’. When The Emergence of Probability was published, there was little recent history of probability besides the excellent mathematical histories by Oscar Sheynin. Now there is plenty. But Emergence was not written as history. Archaeology Emergence is about the past, yes, but it is subtitled A Philosophical Study. I never called it history. It was the first long piece of writing, in any language, that captured, adapted and applied the new kind of analysis that Michel Foucault called archaeology. At the time, few readers who came across the book were familiar with his work. Today his achievements are almost too well known, beloved by some, loathed by others. I continue to be a fan, but I have no intention of writing about Foucault. I continue to use him in my own way, with no thought about whether I am faithful to the traditions he began. I shall say just enough about them to frame The Emergence of Probability. Les Mots et les choses came out in 1966. Its translation, The Order of Things, was published in 1970. Foucault began by thinking of this project as ‘his book about signs’.3 That was how I read the first part of his book, as is pretty obvious in my first few chapters. I hardly ever acknowledged debts to Foucault, because I wrongly thought they were obvious and did not need stating. Moreover I did not want to appear merely trendy. His name appears only twice in the index. Soon after the book was published, I happened to read this sentence in some notes on the book written by Anne Fagot-Largeault: ‘An investigation in the style of Michel Foucault, though a great deal more clear.’ I mentioned this pleasing remark in a 1978 report on work in progress, called ‘From the emergence of probability to the erosion of determinism’ which also gives a brief summary of my debt to Foucault as I saw it then.4 ‘The erosion of determinism’ – I was obviously already at work on Taming. The summary of that book begins, ‘Determinism was eroded during the 19th century and a space was cleared for autonomous laws of chance.’5 In May 1974, the year that Emergence went to press, I gave a talk to the Moral Sciences Club in Cambridge called ‘One way to do philosophy’. It was an account of how an analytic philosopher trained at Cambridge University in the shadows of G. E. Moore and the rest could learn a new approach to conceptual analysis of problematic concepts – such as probability.6 The version of

Description:
Historical records show that there was no real concept of probability in Europe before the mid-seventeenth century, although the use of dice and other randomizing objects was commonplace. Ian Hacking presents a philosophical critique of early ideas about probability, induction, and statistical infer
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.