ebook img

The Definition of Arthron in Aristotle's Poetics PDF

101 Pages·2017·1.87 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Definition of Arthron in Aristotle's Poetics

UNIPA Springer Series Patrizia Laspia From Biology to Linguistics: The Definition of Arthron in Aristotle's Poetics UNIPA Springer Series Editor-in-chief Carlo Amenta, Università di Palermo, Palermo, Italy Series editors Sebastiano Bavetta, Università di Palermo, Palermo, Italy Calogero Caruso, Università di Palermo, Palermo, Italy Gioacchino Lavanco, Università di Palermo, Palermo, Italy Bruno Maresca, Università di Salerno, Fisciano, Italy AndreasÖchsner,GriffithSchoolofEngineering,SouthportQueensland,Australia Mariacristina Piva, Università Cattolica Sacro Cuore, Piacenza, Italy Roberto Pozzi Mucelli, Policlinico G.B.Rossi, Verona, Italy Antonio Restivo, Università di Palermo, Palermo, Italy Norbert M. Seel, University of Freiburg, Freiburg im Breisgau, Germany Gaspare Viviani, Università di Palermo, Palermo, Italy More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/13175 Patrizia Laspia From Biology to Linguistics: fi The De nition of Arthron ’ in Aristotle s Poetics 123 Patrizia Laspia Dipartimento di ScienzeUmanistiche University of Palermo Palermo Italy ISSN 2366-7516 ISSN 2366-7524 (electronic) UNIPA SpringerSeries ISBN978-3-319-77325-4 ISBN978-3-319-77326-1 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77326-1 LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2018934441 ©SpringerInternationalPublishingAG,partofSpringerNature2018 Thisworkissubjecttocopyright.AllrightsarereservedbythePublisher,whetherthewholeorpart of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission orinformationstorageandretrieval,electronicadaptation,computersoftware,orbysimilarordissimilar methodologynowknownorhereafterdeveloped. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publicationdoesnotimply,evenintheabsenceofaspecificstatement,thatsuchnamesareexemptfrom therelevantprotectivelawsandregulationsandthereforefreeforgeneraluse. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authorsortheeditorsgiveawarranty,expressorimplied,withrespecttothematerialcontainedhereinor for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictionalclaimsinpublishedmapsandinstitutionalaffiliations. Printedonacid-freepaper ThisSpringerimprintispublishedbytheregisteredcompanySpringerInternationalPublishingAG partofSpringerNature Theregisteredcompanyaddressis:Gewerbestrasse11,6330Cham,Switzerland Ἐpeὶ wάllo1 ἀqihlὸm peqipέuetcem jaὶ jeῖmo1 ὅra vάqlas' ἄk- koi1 ἔhηjem, sί1 ἂm uqάrai dύmaiso… Pindaro, Olimpica II, Ant. 5, vv. 98/101 (178–180 Gentili) A D. P., con gratitudine Contents 1 The Problem. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 1.1 The Definition of ἄqhqom in Aristole’s Poetics: An Unsolvable Dilemma? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 1.2 State of the Text. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 1.3 The Principal Critical Positions Regarding the Definition of ἄqhqom . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20 2 From Biology to Linguistics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 2.1 Biological Patterns in the Twentieth Chapter of the Poetics . . . . . 37 2.2 The Aristotelian Definitions of ἄqhqom . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42 2.3 eἶmai as ἄqhqom: My Conjecture. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45 2.4 Some Possible Objections. Is eἶmai a Verb?. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50 2.5 Nature and Uses of eἶmai: The Contemporary Debate. . . . . . . . . . 53 3 Conclusions. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61 Bibliography .. .... .... .... ..... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... 65 Index Locorum .... .... .... ..... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... 73 Index Verborum ... .... .... ..... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... 79 Index of Ancient Authors.... ..... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... 81 Index of Modern Authors.... ..... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... 83 vii Abstract This volume is not intended as a philological or paleographical specialist contri- bution:itisanewattemptatreadingAristotle’sworkasawhole.Itconsistsoftwo chapters.Thefirstchapterconsistsofthreesections.Firstsectiondiscussesthemain problems posed by the definition of arthron; second section considers the state of the text; third section examines the critical literature on that issue since the end of the nineteenth century. The second chapter is the actual pars construens of the work. It consists of five sections. The first section explores the close relationship thatAristotleholdsbetweenbiologyandlanguage.Aristotleisnotthefatherofthe specialized sciences: He isratherthelast great global thinkerofAntiquity; ineach field of knowledge, he employs the method of his biological inquiries. Second sectionanalyzesthedefinitionofarthroninthetwentiethchapterofthePoeticsand emphasizestheirclosesimilaritytoitsdefinitioninthebiologicalworks.Inthethird section suggest my conjecture about the first example of arthron in the Poetics, accordingtowhichIreadeimiinsteadoff.m.i.Inthefourthandfifthsections,Itake someobjectionstomyconjectureintoaccount;Irejectthateinaimaybeconsidered ‘one verb among the others.’ Last section considers the more recent critical issues about Greek einai. ix Introduction The content of the work whose introduction I am writing today, September 13, 2017,wasalreadyclearinmymindbackin1996whenIgavebirthtothevolume that was published in September 1997 with the title L’articolazione linguistica. Origini biologiche di una metafora (Laspia 1997). As demonstrated by the eighth chapter—almost a fifth of the volume1—the difficulties posed by the definition of ἄqhqom in the Poetics were already well known to me, and, I must say, their solution,too.Butin1996,Iwasonlythirty-fiveyearsold,withlittleexperiencein philologyandpaleography,nostableacademicposition,andalltherecklessnessof youth,butnotenoughtoproposeahypothesisasdaringastheoneInowproposein these pages. Once the book had been published—and the reviews had been read—I thought that the question was closed, and that there was no reason to return to the subject. I had to wait until the year 2009 and the Ph.D. defense of Laura Gianvittorio, my doctoral student at that time and today my colleague, whom I thank for finally exhuming the issue at a symposial dinner. Laura and her boyfriend (now her husband) Alex Ungar, who has been studying Classical Philology in Oxford for a while,thoughttheideaexposedherewasagoodone.Meanwhile,yearshadpassed (somehow, twenty!) and my self-confidence had increased somewhat. So I began the arduous task of acquiring the philological, paleographic, and, not least in importance,thebibliographicskillsnecessarytore-examinetheissuefromthevery beginning. ThedefinitionofἄqhqominthePoeticsisarealpuzzle,intheveryprecisesense explainedbyThomasKuhninhisfamousbookof1962,TheStructureofScientific Revolutions. Generations of scholars have used it as their exercise regime, only to endupproposingwhatisalreadywell known,attimes whatisoutdated,orelseto expressadrasticdistrustofanypossiblesolutiontotheproblem.Withthispaper,I hope I have made a small contribution to the subject. Up to Sect. 2.2, my con- clusions run parallel to the contents of L’articolazione linguistica. Since I do not 1Lalogicadelvivente.Rύmderlo1edἄqhqominAristotle,inLaspia1997,pp.79–126. xi xii Introduction think that there were many more than the proverbial twenty-five readers of that book, there is no need to apologize: repetita iuvant. But the conjecture I propose here is different, and my bibliographic knowledge is different as well—time has movedforward,andsome(thoughnotmany)havespokenoutonthedifficulttopic. Aboveall,themethodologicalawarenesswithwhichIwritetodayisdifferent,even though my method has not changed. I say, moreover, that if one should choose to refuse the conjecture I propose here regarding the first example of ἄqhqom in the twentieth chapter of Aristotle’s Poetics, but appreciate the way I have conducted my reading of Aristotle, we cannot say that we disagree completely. WhatamIalludingtoandwhatisthemethodIusetoreadAristotle?Inmyreading, Ibeginwiththreemainassumptions.(1)Unlikewhatiscommonlysaidtoday,Aristotle is not the father of the specialized sciences, nor is he the one who inaugurated spe- cialized studies in Greece, but the last great global thinker of antiquity2. There is, therefore,aunitaryAristotelianresearchprogram3,whosedimensioncoincideswithhis ownwork.(2)TheheartoftheAristotelianresearchprogramisrepresentedbythelife sciences.Thecurrentreadingparadigm,whichgivesprioritytoAristotle’sethicaland political works, does not do justice to that research program and should not be fol- lowed.(3)WithintheAristotelianresearchprogram,indeedatitsheart—representedby the biological investigation—a highly significant place is occupied by the ‘language/living body’ analogy, which is the basis of Aristotelian linguistic investi- gation, and in particular, of twentieth chapter of the Poetics. Any reading of the so-calledlinguisticchapterofthePoeticsthatdoesnotproceedsimultaneouslyandin parallel with the biological investigation, which is the model of Aristotle’s linguistic investigations, has in my opinion no foundation on principle. Tothisisaddedthefollowingmethodologicalpremise:InreadingAristotle,we are in no way justified in seeking to understand what precedes in function of what follows—that is, in interpreting his words on the basis of later texts by other authors. This means that we are not justified in reading Aristotle in light of our contemporary prejudices, or in considering him as the forerunner of any of our fashions or theories. Instead, it is necessary to read Aristotle iuxta propria prin- cipia:«AristotlethelinguistwithAristotlethebiologistandnaturalist».4Onlythen can Aristotle regain his voice, which still speaks to us after thousands of years. In this way, we can avoid the insurmountable contradictions present, for example,inthe current readings ofthetwentieth chapterof thePoetics.But thisis 2«L’ultimograndepensatoretotaledell’antichità»(Laspia1997,p.79). 3Originally coined by Imre Lakatos (1968), the notion of ‘research program’ was first used in regardtoAristotelianbiologybyJamesLennox(1987).Lennoxisconvinced,however,thatthis notioncanonlybeappliedtothebiologicalworks.Theauthor,therefore,implicitlyadherestothe ideaofAristotleasthefatherofspecializedsciencesandusestheterminanarrowersensethanthe oneIusehere.MyhypothesisisthatAristotle,theheirofIonicnaturalism,andinabroadersense of the Homeric Encyclopedia (see Laspia 1996), is the last global scientist of antiquity. In my view, the notion of ‘program’ would, therefore, be applicable to his entire work, viewed as a whole. 4«L’Aristotlelinguistaconl’Aristotlebiologoenaturalista».Laspia(1997),p.80.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.