ebook img

Tense Logic PDF

95 Pages·1976·2.769 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Tense Logic

TENSE LOGIC SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE, AND ON THE MA THEMA TICAL METHODS OF SOCIAL AND BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES Managing Editor: J AAKKO HINTIKKA, Academy of Finland and Stanford University Editors: ROBER T S. COHEN, Boston University DONALD DAVIDSON, Rockefeller University and Princeton University GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, University of Arizona VOLUME 111 ROBERT P. McARTHUR Colby College, Waterville, Maine, U.S.A. TENSE LOGIC SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. ISBN 978-90-481-8345-6 ISBN 978-94-017-3219-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-3219-2 AlI Rights Reserved Copyright © 1976 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland in 1976 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form by or any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner PREFACE This monograph is designed to provide an introduction to the principal areas of tense logic. Many of the developments in this ever-growing field have been intentionally excluded to fulfill this aim. Length also dictated a choice between the alternative notations of A. N. Prior and Nicholas Rescher - two pioneers of the subject. I choose Prior's because of the syntactical parallels with the language it symbolizes and its close ties with other branches of logi cal theory, especially modal logic. The first chapter presents a wider view of the material than later chapters. Several lines of development are consequently not followed through the remainder of the book, most notably metric systems. Although it is import ant to recognize that the unadorned Prior-symbolism can be enriched in vari ous ways it is an advanced subject as to how to actually carry off these enrichments. Readers desiring more information are referred to the appropri ate literature. Specialists will notice that only the first of several quantifi cational versions of tense logic is proven complete in the final chapter. Again constraints of space are partly to blame. The proof for the 'star' systems is wildly complex and at the time of this writing is not yet ready for publi cation. It is a pleasure to thank Professors Hugues Leblanc, Henry Kyburg, Frank Parker, Mr. Daniel Cohen, and Mr. Russell Wahl for their generous assistance and helpful comments on earlier versions of this work. I should also like to thank Colby College's Humanities Grant Committee for a research grant during the summer of 1974. R.P.M. TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE v CHAPTER l/AN OVERVIEW OF TENSE LOGIC 1 1.1. Introduction 1 1.2. The Formalities of Tensed Statements 2 1.3. Interpreting Tensed Statements. I 7 1.4. Interpreting Tensed Statements. II 12 Notes 15 CHAPTER 2/LINEAR TENSE LOGICS 17 2.1. The Minimal System K 17 t 2.2. Linear Enlargements of K 24 t Notes 36 CHAPTER 3/BRANCHING TENSE LOGIC AND TEMPORAL MODALITY 37 3.1. Branching Tense Logics 37 3.2. Ten1poral Modality 42 Notes 51 CHAPTER 4/QUANTIFICATIONAL TENSE LOGICS 53 4.1. The Q Systems 53 4.2. The Q* and Q** Systems 60 Notes 66 CHAPTER S/SOUNDNESS AND COMPLETENESS THEOREMS FOR TENSE LOGIC 67 Notes 78 APPENDIX 1/ SC TAUTOLOGIES USED IN PROOFS 79 APPENDIX II/SUMMARY OF THE SYSTEMS 80 BIBLIOGRAPHY 83 CHAPTER 1 AN OVERVIEW OF TENSE LOGIC 1.1. INTRODUCTION As P. F. Strawson noted in his Introduction to Logical Theory, 1 standard logic seems ill-adapted to deal with statements containing tensed verbs or explicit temporal references. For example, we say things like 'There were women among the survivors' but the existential quantifier 3 ~ is read 'There is (timelessly) an x such that', and the relation of predicate expressions to their subjects is also presumed to be timeless.2 Hence, trying to symbolize this statement results in the awkward (1) (3 x )(x is a woman & x is a person who was among the survivors) where both occurrences of 'is' are taken to be timeless. One of the conse quences of this deficiency in standard logic is that arguments whose premisses and conclusion contain tensed verbs may be pronounced invalid, even though they are intuitively valid. So, in the following case (2) John is running (therefore) John will have run most would agree that the conclusion follows from the premiss, but this can not be represented by standard logical means. Responses to complaints such as Strawson's have fallen, until recently, into two classes. Some, such as W. V. Quine, argue that all statements con taining tensed verbs can be paraphrased into an atemporal form and repre sented in an extended version of standard logic.3 Others take the situation outlined above as evidence of the inherent limitation of formal logic, showing that it is incapable of representing the statements of ordinary language. This is Strawson's position.4 In the last few years a third response has appeared which takes the form of developing a (formal) logic of tense and temporality. Slipping between the alternatives posed by Quine and Strawson, such logics offer a neat compro mise. On one hand, temporality is preserved against Quine's atemporal 2 CHAPTER 1 paraphrases. And on the other hand, the scope of formal logic is extended so as to meet, at least in this area, Strawson's misgivings about the limits of logic. In addition to the formalization of tensed statements, the systematization of inferences involving such statements has been a primary aim of tense logicians. But here, as in all non-standard areas of logical theory, a difficult question arises as to which assumptions about tense - and, as we shall soon point out, about time - should be taken axiomatically in the development of deductive systems of tense logic. Without an exploration of various possi bilities any proposed answer to this question will inevitably seem arbitrary. Thus many systems of tense logic have been created which incorporate differ ing tense logical principles. Such systems allow the investigation of these prin ciples taken singly and in "groups. And, in this manner, the covert assumptions behind intuitive appraisals of tensed arguments are brought to the surface. 1.2. THE FORMALITIES OF TENSED STATEMENTS As regards temporal reference, two distinct categories of statements can be distinguished. These are: (i) Temporally definite s (ii) Temporally .indefinite. The first category includes all those statements having no temporal reference whatsoever - so-called atemporal statements - such as '5 is a prime number' as well as those with specific temporal references, e.g., (3) It always rains in Boston. The essential feature of temporally definite statements is that their truth values are independent of the time of their utterance. Or, to put the matter in a somewhat different manner, such statements do not convey any positional information concerning the temporal relation of the speaker and the event or state of affairs depicted. Of course, hybrids of the sort (4) It rained in Boston on May 12, 1973 are not unusual. Although some positional information is imparted by (4), i.e., that the time of utterance is later than May 12, 1973, to convey this fact is generally not the primary intent of the speaker. In such cases, statements like (4) can be thought of as if they were expressed with atemporal verbs (e.g., It rains in Boston on May 12, 1973). When the positional information is AN OVERVIEW OF TENSE LOGIC 3 the point of the statement, it can be parsed as a conjunction of a temporally definite statement and a temporally indefinite statement, e.g., (4') It rains in Boston on May 12, 1973 and May 12, 1973 is now past. Since the tense of the verb, as already noted, does not play an important role in temporally definite statements, it is not surprising that tense logic is more concerned with the second category: temporally indefinite statements. Several examples of this sort of statement are: (5) Richmond was the capital of the Confederacy. (6) It is sunny and warm today. (7) Montreal will be the site of the next Olympic Games. Note that the truth-value of all these is very much dependent upon the time of utterance, a property we can take as essential to this category of state ment. English has three basic tenses which may enter into the composition of a temporally indefinite statement. These are the (simple) past, present, and future tenses. Following the analogy of the formal analysis of negation in ordin~ry logic, iOt is convenient to think of statements in these three tenses as compounds consisting of a one-place statement operator - which picks up the tense - and an interior statement. Utilizing the symbol F for the future tense operator, P for the past tense operator, and T for the present tense operator, statements (5)-(7) above can be partially symbolized as follows. (5 ') ~Richmond is the capital of the Confederacy) (6') T(It is sunny and warm today) (7') F(Montreal is the site of the next Olympic Games) Note however that construing the tense operators as statement operators requires the verb in the (temporally indefinite) interior statement to have some tense or other. Hence a certain redundancy is present in (6'); not only does the statement operator T signify present tense but the interior statement in is the present tense as well. Thus the T operator is superfluous and can be dispensed with. This leaves us with only two tense operators - F and P. The function of F and P is to strip all but present tenseness from the main verb in the original statement and pack the tense into the prefix. Conse quently, reading F as 'It will be the case that' and P as 'It has been the case 4 CHAPTER 1 that' seems appropriate. When symbols are translated back into English this results in some artificiality, e.g., 'It will be the case that it rains in Boston', but no more than arises from the formal reading of the negation operator as 'It is not the case that'. Utilizing the two tense operators in combination allows the symbolization of other tenses as well. Below are statements in two common perfect tenses (past and future) with symbolizations. (8) It had rained in Boston = PPp FPP (9) It will have rained in Boston = (Note that p stands for the atomic statement 'It rains in Boston'). With the addition of the truth-functional connectives & (conjunction) and ~ (negation) other constructions are possible, e.g., 'It did rain in Boston but isn't now' beingpp & ~p. Negations in statements containing tense operators must be handled with care, for there is a considerable difference between and (11) ~Fp. The best rendition of (10) (with p still doing duty for 'It rains in Boston') is (10') It won't always rain in Boston whereas (11) would be (11 ') It will never rain in Boston. The reasons for these paraphrases are straightforward. Fp translates 'p at sometime in the future' and, hence F~p translates '~p sometime in the future'. But ~ Fp, being the denial of Fp, translates 'p at no time in the future'. The same considerations apply, mutatis mutandis, to P. The Law of Double Negation operatires as usual, as shown by the equiv~ alences (= is the biconditional symbol) (12) =Fp ~~Fp =pp (13) ~~pp (14) =Fp F~~p

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.