ebook img

Teaching Psychology and the Socratic Method: Real Knowledge in a Virtual Age PDF

202 Pages·2016·2.65 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Teaching Psychology and the Socratic Method: Real Knowledge in a Virtual Age

Teaching Psychology and the Socratic Method Real Knowledge in a Virtual Age James J. Dillon Teaching Psychology and the Socratic Method James   J.   Dillon Teaching Psychology and the Socratic Method Real Knowledge in a Virtual Age James   J.   Dillon University of West Georgia Carrollton, Georgia, USA ISBN 978-1-349-95049-2 ISBN 978-1-349-95050-8 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/978-1-349-95050-8 Library of Congress Control Number: 2016958141 © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2 016 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifi cally the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfi lms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specifi c statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. Cover image © PRISMA ARCHIVO / Alamy Stock Photo Printed on acid-free paper This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Nature America Inc. The registered company address is: 1 New York Plaza, New York, NY 10004, U.S.A. C ONTENTS 1 Why We Teach 1 2 Who Is Socrates and Why Should We Read Him? 1 3 3 The Socratic Method 1 9 4 Socrates Structures the Course 2 7 5 Teaching Neuroscience with P haedo 3 5 6 Teaching the Psychology of Memory with P haedo 45 7 Teaching the Psychology of Learning with M eno 5 3 8 Teaching Sensation–Perception Psychology with D e Anima 6 5 9 Teaching Cognitive Psychology with D e Anima 7 5 10 First Academic Conference on Psychology and the Body 8 1 v vi CONTENTS 11 Teaching Developmental Psychology with R epublic 93 12 Teaching Moral Development with T heaetetus 105 13 Teaching Abnormal Psychology with N icomachean Ethics 117 14 Teaching Psychotherapy with P haedrus 1 29 15 Conference 2: Good, Better, and Best in Psychology 139 16 Teaching Personality Psychology with A pology 1 47 17 Teaching Social Psychology with C rito 159 18 Teaching Motivation and Emotion Psychology with E uthyphro 1 69 19 Academic Conference 3: What Is the Self? 1 81 20 Omnibus Academic Conference: The Socratic Method 1 91 Appendix A: Interlocutrix Worksheet 201 Appendix B: Conference Feedback Form 203 Index 205 CHAPTER 1 Why We Teach During a class discussion a few years ago, a student struggled out loud with the many demands of college life: classes, work, parents, romance, friends, clubs, sports, and other obligations. “I just can’t make it all work,” she said with exasperation and the beginning of a few tears in her eyes. This was a capstone seminar for senior undergraduate psychology majors. The topic on the fl oor was time management, and this student expressed how hard it was for her to balance getting schoolwork done along with all the other things she wanted and needed to do. Another student piped up to counsel her, “Look, don’t let school interfere with your education.” These words from Mark Twain seemed to elicit near universal agreement from the class. “Of course,” they agreed, “the really important learning in col- lege takes place outside the classroom. Don’t ever forget that.” Lest we think this scenario is an anecdotal blip, 70 % of college students say that “social” learning outside the classroom is more important than academic learning (Grigsby, 2 009 ). It is not only students who think this way. The famous psychologist Carl Rogers said of his career in teaching, “It seems to me that anything that can be taught to another is relatively inconsequential and has little or no signifi cant infl uence on behavior” (1 969 , p. 302). These sentiments remind me of what my uncle used to say over the Thanksgiving table to needle me: “Those who can, do; those who can’t, teach.” In this day of online classes and “distant learning” platforms, is the liv- ing, breathing teacher necessary at all? What can college students learn in © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2016 1 J.J. Dillon, Teaching Psychology and the Socratic Method, DOI 10.1057/978-1-349-95050-8_1 2 J.J. DILLON a classroom, face-to-face with a skilled teacher they cannot learn a nywhere else? Some have argued the answer is “skills and information” (see Craig, 2015 ; Hettich, 1 998 ). Indeed, there has been great pressure from leg- islators, administrators, students, and other stakeholders to have higher education be “relevant,” to show that learning really produces concrete results in the world in terms of obtaining employment, earning higher incomes, and acquiring “real world” job competencies. As a result, the past 25 years have witnessed a wholesale transformation of the teaching profession into an activity focused primarily on the transfer of relevant skills and information to students. What is ironic is that this lurch toward relevance and applicability actu- ally puts the professor on the path of the Dodo Bird. A colleague of mine has a picture on his offi ce door of a professor standing before a classroom. Below it the caption reads, “Dead Man Talking.” The scenario is not that far from being a reality. Once teaching becomes about skills and informa- tion, it can just as easily be “put online.” It strikes many as absurd that we haven’t already put college completely online (e.g., Carey, 2 015 ; Crow & Dabars, 2015 ; Selingo, 2 015 ). I actually agree with these critics: if higher education is really about skills and information, then it s hould all be put online. Students should not be asked to waste their time driving to campus and sitting through face-to-face classes if they can just as easily acquire them by a cheaper and more effi cient means. But what I will try to show in this book is that h igher education is not at all about acquiring skills and information . I return to the Twain quote, “Don’t let school interfere with your edu- cation.” I tend to think that any popular idea like this must have at least a kernel of truth in it. This view of education appreciates that for learning to matter, it needs to be useful to the learner. It needs to pertain to and even be derived from “the real world” rather than be a set of abstract principles that apply to nothing. It needs to be something we achieve through our own efforts rather than be “given” to us by a teacher in a classroom. But this view misses other vitally important facets of learning, what we might think of as the deeper aspects of education. Deep learning aims to develop higher order and critical thinking in the learner, to help the student see the underlying assumptions behind claims to knowledge, to be able to evaluate those assumptions, and consider better ones. Deep learning seeks to enable students to logically reason from premises to valid conclusions or to induce others’ premises from listening and careful observation. Deep learning teaches students to engage in thoughtful, persuasive speech WHY WE TEACH 3 and writing, to go out into the world and be able to really know and understand it to its core. Deep learning seeks to develop the young human being’s mind to be able to live a meaningful life and productively engage the franchise of democratic citizenship. The important point is that for deep learning to happen, i t requires an intimate and interpersonal learn- ing community . These things cannot be taught or learned online. And one does not just pick these things up from one’s family, friends, and social life. One does not acquire them from working in or running a business. One can only learn these things in a classroom from a teacher who already has these abilities himself or herself and who knows how to construct sce- narios for students to learn and rehearse them. My practice in this book is to pose questions about the role of the teacher to the ancient fi gure Socrates. Socrates devoted his entire life to teaching and was even willing to die for what he saw as the noblest of all vocations, one which he thought required more strength and courage than the soldier and more practical intelligence than the businessman. In the dialogue I on , Socrates speaks with the famous rhapsode Ion. A rhap- sode is a minstrel of sorts who gives oral recitals of the great poet Homer. These fi gures were quite esteemed in ancient Greece. Given the adulation he has enjoyed, Ion is quite convinced he is the greatest rhapsode who ever lived. Always taken aback by displays of self-confi dence, Socrates is determined to fi nd out what this young man knows which leads him to his bluster. In conducting this investigation through dialogue with Ion, Socrates introduces a distinction between an art (t echne ) and its purpose (e rgon ). The purpose of the art of medicine, he says, is health. The purpose of the art of farming is food. The purpose of the art of carpentry is furniture. The skilled practitioner of any art, Socrates maintains, has not only techni- cal skill, but also an intimate knowledge of the overall purpose of the art, where the art is supposed to lead. The practitioner uses this knowledge of the end point to guide his or her specifi c actions while practicing the art. Socrates tells Ion, since you are such a good practitioner of the art of rhapsody, I assume you must also be conversant with its ergon . So what, Socrates asks him, is the purpose of the art of rhapsody? Ion mumbles, fumbles, and has an overall great deal of diffi culty articulating what the purpose of his art is. He answers, does it even need to have a purpose? Can’t my art just be for art’s sake? Socrates is perplexed. Practitioners of any art should at least be able to provide an account (l ogos ) of the goal of their craft. Otherwise, they are just 4 J.J. DILLON blindly doing things, uncritically applying skills they have learned from their own teachers. Socrates tries to engage Ion further. He asks Ion to consider his own profession: teaching. He asks Ion, what is the pur- pose of Dialectical teaching, the philosopher’s art? Is it fame? Esteem? Is it accomplished students who have productive careers? No, Socrates answers before Ion even has a chance to reply. It is none of these things. As the carpenter’s art produces furniture, Socrates argues, the teacher’s art produces k nowledge . The good teacher knows he or she is practiced in the art of teaching if their instruction facilitates knowledge in the student. Socrates here introduces two very important concepts for this book: knowledge and Dialectic. My book is based entirely on these two concepts. I believe that if we can understand these two ideas, we can grasp the whole Socratic enterprise and will better understand what teaching is all about. I will try to thoroughly explain both in the pages that follow. I look fi rst at knowledge. LEARNING OUTCOMES: THE MODERN EQUIVALENT OF WISDOM Socrates defi nes “knowledge” as the condition in which a mind appre- hends the truth about a subject. He puts it more poetically in the Republic : knowledge is the condition in which a soul has been “turned toward the light” (518c). Socrates calls this state of knowledge “wisdom” ( Phaedo , 79c). In this book, I refer to wisdom as “real knowledge.” In modern parlance, we often prefer to speak of “learning outcomes” rather than “wisdom” or “knowledge,” but the meaning is basically the same. Today’s schools and academic programs are often required to give an account of the “knowledge” they seek to develop in their students. This is a good thing. Imagine if teachers did not do this. We would be like Ion, practitioners of an art whose purpose we did not really understand. These learning outcomes are posted on school websites and printed in brochures and syllabi. Even in our virtual age of online degrees and Massive Online Open Courses (MOOCs), when you review these posted outcomes, most aca- demic programs still aspire to humane, liberal arts goals: self-knowledge and moral awareness in students, critical thinking, analytical reasoning, creative problem solving, and coherent writing. These are goals Socrates would embrace. Not even at the most rapacious, for-profi t, or vocationally

Description:
This book presents a lively and accessible way to use the ancient figure of Socrates to teach modern psychology that avoids the didactic lecture and sterile textbook. In the online age, is a living teacher even needed? What can college students learn face-to-face from a teacher they cannot learn any
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.