ebook img

Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism PDF

209 Pages·1.606 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism

RUDOLF CARNAP AND THE LEGACY OF LOGICAL EMPIRICISM VIENNA CIRCLE INSTITUTE YEARBOOK 16 VIENNA CIRCLE INSTITUTE YEARBOOK 16 Institut Wiener Kreis Society for the Advancement of the Scientific World Conception Series-Editor: Friedrich Stadler University of Vienna, Austria and Director, Institut Wiener Kreis Advisory Editorial Board: Honorary Consulting Editors: Jacques Bouveresse, Collège de France, Paris, France Robert S. Cohen, Boston University, USA Martin Carrier, University of Bielefeld, Germany Wilhelm K. Essler, University of Frankfurt/M., Nancy Cartwright, London School of Economics, UK Germany Richard Creath, Arizona State University, USA Kurt Rudolf Fischer, University of Vienna, Austria Massimo Ferrari, University of Torino, Italy Adolf Grünbaum, University of Pittsburgh, USA Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Rudolf Haller, University of Graz, Austria Maria Carla Galavotti, University of Bologna, Italy Gerald Holton, Harvard University, USA Peter Galison, Harvard University, USA Jaakko Hintikka, Boston University, USA Malachi Hacohen, Duke University, USA Allan S. Janik, University of Innsbruck, Austria Rainer Hegselmann, University of Bayreuth, Germany Andreas Kamlah, University of Osnabrück, Michael Heidelberger, University of Tübingen, Germany Germany Don Howard, University of Notre Dame, USA Eckehart Köhler, University of Vienna, Austria Paul Hoyningen-Huene, University of Hanover, Germany Brian McGuinness, University of Siena, Italy Clemens Jabloner, Hans-Kelsen-Institut, Vienna, Austria Erhard Oeser, University of Vienna, Austria Anne J. Kox, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands Jan Šebestík, CNRS Paris, France Martin Kusch, University of Vienna, Austria Christian Thiel, University of Erlangen, Germany James G. Lennox, University of Pittsburgh, USA Walter Thirring, University of Vienna, Austria Juha Manninen, Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies, Finland Thomas Mormann, University of Donostia / San Sebastián, Review Editor: Spain Donata Romizi, University of Vienna, Austria Edgar Morscher, University of Salzburg, Austria Kevin Mulligan, Université de Genève, Switzerland Editorial Work/Layout/Production: Elisabeth Nemeth, University of Vienna, Austria Julian Nida-Rümelin, University of Munich, Germany Robert Kaller Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland Camilla Nielsen Otto Pfersmann, Université Paris I Panthéon – Sorbonne, France Editorial Address: Miklós Rédei, London School of Economics, UK Institut Wiener Kreis Alan Richardson, University of British Columbia, CDN Universitätscampus, Hof 1 Gerhard Schurz, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Spitalgasse 2-4, A–1090 Wien, Austria Peter Schuster, University of Vienna, Austria Tel.: +431/4277 46501 (international) Karl Sigmund, University of Vienna, Austria or 01/4277 46501 (national) Hans Sluga, University of California at Berkeley, USA Fax.: +431/4277 41297 (international) Elliott Sober, University of Wisconsin, USA or 01/4277 41297 (national) Antonia Soulez, Université de Paris 8, France Email: [email protected] Wolfgang Spohn, University of Konstanz, Germany Homepage: http://univie.ac.at/ivc/ Thomas E. Uebel, University of Manchester, UK Pierre Wagner, Université de Paris 1, Sorbonne, France C. Kenneth Waters, University of Minnesota, USA Jan Woleński, Jagiellonian University, Cracow, Poland Gereon Wolters, University of Konstanz, Germany Anton Zeilinger, University of Vienna, Austria The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. Richard Creath Editor Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism Editor Richard Creath School of Life Sciences 874501 Arizona State University Tempe, AZ 85287-4501 USA ISSN 0929-6328 ISBN 978-94-007-3928-4 e-ISBN 978-94-007-3929-1 DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-3929-1 Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg New York London Library of Congress Control Number: 2012932633 © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. Exempted from this legal reservation are brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis or material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the Copyright Law of the Publisher’s location, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from Springer. Permissions for use may be obtained through RightsLink at the Copyright Clearance Center. Violations are liable to prosecution under the respective Copyright Law. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. While the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication, neither the authors nor the editors nor the publisher can accept any legal responsibility for any errors or omissions that may be made. The publisher makes no warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein. Printed on acid-free paper Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com) T C able of onTenTs Editorial ...............................................................................................................vii MiChael friedMan, Scientific Philosophy from Helmholtz to Carnap and Quine ..............................................................................................1 GeorG sChieMer, Carnap’s Untersuchungen: Logicism, Formal Aximatics, and Metatheory ............................................................................................13 MaTThias neuber, Realism as a Problem of Language – From Carnap to Reichenbach and Kaila .............................................................................37 riChard CreaTh, Analyticity in the Theoretical Language: Is a Different Account Really Necessary? ....................................................57 ChrisTian daMböCk, Rudolf Carnap and Wilhelm Dilthey: “German” Empiricism in the Aufbau ...........................................................67 ChrisToph liMbeCk-lilienau, Carnap’s Encounter with Pragmatism .................89 ThoMas MorMann, Toward a Theory of the Pragmatic A Priori: From Carnap to Lewis and Beyond ............................................................113 ThoMas uebel, Carnap, Philosophy, and “Politics in its Broadest Sense” .......133 General parT review essays ThoMas MorMann, A Virtual Debate in Exile: Cassirer and the Vienna Circle after 1933 ............................................................................149 John MiChael, Emergence – still trendy after all these years ...........................169 reviews Anne Siegetsleitner (Ed.), Logischer Empirismus, Werte und Moral, Wien–New York: Springer, 2010 (Massimo Ferrari) ................................181 Matthew Eve and Christopher Burke (Eds.), Otto Neurath: From hieroglyphics to Isotype. A Visual Autobiography. London: Hyphen Press 2011. (Günther Sandner) .....................................................184 v v i Table of Contents Giovanni Vailati. Logic and Pragmatism. Selected Essays by Giovanni Vailati. Edited by Claudia Arrighi, Paola Cantù, Mauro de Zan, and Patrick Suppes. Stanford: CSLI, 2010. (Paolo Palmieri) ..........................................................................................187 The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences. Ed. by Michael Heidelberger and Gregor Schiemann. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2009. (Miles MacLeod) ..........................................................190 Karl von Meyenn (ed.), Eine Entdeckung von ganz außerordentlicher Tragweite. Schrödingers Briefwechsel zur Wellenmechanik und zum Katzenparadox. Springer-Verlag: Berlin Heidelberg 2011. (Wolfgang L. Reiter) ..................................................................................194 Activities of the Institute Vienna Circle ............................................................197 Index of Names .................................................................................................201 e diTorial Rudolf Carnap was one of the most important philosophers of the twentieth cen- tury, and he came to worldwide fame during his time in Vienna, 1926–31, as a core member of the Vienna Circle. So the eight papers in this volume, all on Carnap and all given at a conference in Vienna, represent a homecoming of sorts. But the papers do not confine themselves to Carnap alone or to his time in Vienna. They explore his history and motivation, his interaction with other philosophers in both Europe and America, various aspects of his work on logic and philosophy of sci- ence, and even his political engagement. The conference at which these papers were presented, “Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism”, was held on the 28th and 29th of June, 2010 at the University of Vienna, under the auspices of the Institute Vienna Circle. The meeting was organized jointly by Friedrich Stadler for the Institute and by Richard Zach on behalf of the Collected Works of Rudolf Carnap, forthcoming from the Open Court Publishing Company. Carnap wanted philosophy to be scientific, that is, a progressive, coopera- tive venture. But as Michael Friedman shows the ideal of a scientific philosophy appeared long before Carnap and continues to inspire many philosophers even today. Logic was central to Carnap’s vision of a scientific philosophy, and Georg Schiemer explores one of Carnap’s large-scale logic projects, the Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik. This work was set aside in the 1930s and published only well after Carnap’s death. Schiemer is able to show that the work is subtle and gives important clues to Carnap’s thinking in logic. Philosophy of science was also central to Carnap’s vision of philosophy. Matthias Neuber explores the scientific realism defended by Hans Reichenbach and Eino Kaila and Carnap’s resistance to it. Richard Creath examines the related issue of Carnap’s proposal for endow- ing theoretical terms with meaning by tying theories to their Ramsey sentences. Christian Damböck examines another empirical tradition, “German” empiricism, especially as exemplified by Wilhelm Dilthey, and assesses its influence on Car- nap’s view in the Aufbau. Christoph Limbeck-Lilienau and Thomas Mormann, in their separate papers, explore the relations between Carnap and American pragmatism. They approach this topic differently, but each shows that this relation is both complex and illu- minating. Finally, Thomas Uebel examines the political dimension of the Vienna Circle and particularly of Carnap within it. Uebel shows that logic and philosophy of science were from the beginning conceived of as part of a larger project that was indeed political in the broadest sense. Taken together, the papers show the rich variety of Carnap’s concerns and his place within important intellectual traditions that shape our thinking even today. vii v iii Editorial Thanks go to the organizers of the conference, Friedrich Stadler and Richard Zach, to the host institutions, the Institute Vienna Circle and the University of Vienna, to the conference participants, and to the production team at the Institute. Richard Creath Tempe, Arizona, July 7, 2011 Michael FriedMan S P h cientiFic hiloSoPhy FroM elMholtz to c Q arnaP and uine The concept of a “scientific philosophy” (wissenschaftliche Philosophie) first de- veloped in the mid nineteenth century, as a reaction against what was viewed as the excessively speculative and metaphysical character of post-Kantian German ideal- ism. One of the primary intellectual models of this movement was a celebrated address by Hermann von Helmholtz, “Über das Sehen des Menschen,” delivered at the dedication of a monument to Kant at Königsberg in 1855. Helmholtz begins by asking, on behalf of the audience, why a natural scientist like himself is speak- ing in honor of a philosopher. This question only arises, he says, because of the current deplorable climate of enmity and mutual distrust between the two fields – a climate which is due, in Helmholtz’s opinion, to the entirely speculative system of Naturphilosophie that Schelling and Hegel have erected wholly independent of, and even in open hostility towards, the actual positive results of the natural sci- ences. What Helmholtz is now recommending, however, is a return to the close cooperation between the two fields exemplified in the work of Kant, who himself made significant contributions to natural science (in his nebular hypothesis put forward in 1755), and, in general, “stood in relation to the natural sciences together with the natural scientists on precisely the same fundamental principles.”1 And it was this recommendation that was enthusiastically embraced within the emerging “back to Kant!” movement, where it led to the idea that all metaphysics should be replaced by the new discipline of “epistemology” or “theory of knowledge” (Erk- enntnistheorie), so that philosophy itself would now become “scientific.” What is the nature of this new scientific philosophy that is now being ex- plicitly opposed to Naturphilosophie in particular and post-Kantian idealism in general? What relation is philosophy now supposed to bear to the sciences, and what does it mean for philosophy to become scientific in this way? What exactly is being recommended when we are told that philosophy should stand “in relation to the natural sciences together with the natural scientists on precisely the same fundamental principles”? For Helmholtz himself this means that philosophy – that is, epistemology or the theory of knowledge – should work in cooperation with the latest psycho- physiological research in inquiring into the nature of the representations of our senses, and the relationship between these representations and the actual world to which they correspond. And it is for this reason that the body of his 1855 address 1 See Helmholtz (1865/1903, vol. I, p. 88). R. Creath (ed.), Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism, 1 Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 16, DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-3929-1_1, © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.