Quirky Sides of Scientists True Tales of Ingenuity and Error From Physics and Astronomy David R. Topper David R. Topper Department of History University of Winnipeg Winnipeg, Manitoba Canada R3B 2E9 [email protected] Library of Congress Control Number: 2007925263 ISBN-13: 978-0-387-71018-1 e-ISBN-13: 978-0-387-71019-8 Printed on acid-free paper. ©2007 Springer Science(cid:2)Business Media, LLC. All rights reserved. This work may not be translated or copied in whole or in part without the written permission of the publisher (Springer Science(cid:2)Business Media, LLC., 233 Spring Street, New York, NY 10013, USA), except for brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis. Use in connection with any form of information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now know or hereafter developed is forbidden. The use in this publication of trade names, trademarks, service marks and similar terms, even if they are not identified as such, is not to be taken as an expression of opinion as to whether or not they are subject to proprietary rights. 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 springer.com Acknowledgments For their assistance and support at various stages of this project I kindly thank Wayne Choma, James Hanley, Scott Montgomery, and Dwight Vincent. For his congenial camaraderie spanning more than three decades, I am grateful to my much-missed late friend and colleague in the history of science, David Dyck. Iam also beholden to all my students who asked (and continue to ask) challenging questions, forcing me to concede that I don’t know many things—and compelling me to find them out. And, not the least, I acknowledge the University of Winnipeg, especially for granting me a research leave to complete this task. Whatever singular insights may be found in this book, I will be pleased to accept the accolades for—though fully cognizant that all errors, too, are minealone. vii A Note on the Figures I drew all 57 figures. Figures 3.1, 3.5, 4.1, 6.3, 6.4, 6.6, 8.4, and 11.4 are based on images from I.B. Cohen’s The Birth of a New Physics(New York: W.W. Norton, 1960; revised ed.1985), a teaching text I have used for over three decades. Others are from articles I have published, which are cited at the end of the corresponding chapters. In my sketches of original historical images I have translated any Latin inscriptions into English. The consequential loss entailed in not reproducing the original diagrams and artwork is mitigated by the present-day fact that most images are available on the Internet. ix Contents Acknowledgments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vii A Note on the Figures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ix Prelude . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 1. Tenacity and Stubbornness: Einstein on Theory and Experiment . . . . 3 1.1. Tenacity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 1.2. Stubbornness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7 1.3. Einstein’s Experiment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 2. Convergence or Coincidence: Ancient Measurements of the Sun and Moon—How Far? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 2.1. The Speed of Light . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 2.2. Ancient Astronomy: Ptolemy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 2.3. Aristarchus’s Measurement and Ptolemy’s Model . . . . . . . . . . . 19 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 3. The Rationality of Simplicity: Copernicus on Planetary Motion. . . . . 25 3.1. Planetary Motion: Geocentrism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 3.2. Heliocentrism: The Hierarchy of the Planets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30 3.3. Heliocentrism: Planetary Distances . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 3.4. Copernicus and Simplicity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34 3.5. Copernicus and Complexity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 4. A Silence of Scientists: Venus’s Brightness, Earth’s Precession, and the Nebula in Orion. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43 4.1. Ptolemy on Venus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43 4.2. Copernicus on Venus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46 4.3. Galileo on Venus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48 xi xii Contents 4.4. Galileo, Sunspots, and Precession . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52 4.5. Galileo and Nebulae . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 5. Progress Through Error: Stars and Quasars—How Big, How Far? . . . 67 5.1. Copernicus and the Distance of Stars . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67 5.2. Tycho and Parallax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69 5.3. Galileo on the Stars . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75 5.4. Quasars and Cosmology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 83 6. The Data Fit the Model but the Model Is Wrong: Kepler and the Structure of the Cosmos . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85 6.1. Neutrinos and Sydney’s Opera House . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85 6.2. Kepler and God’s Mind . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 87 6.3. Kepler and the Equant . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96 6.4. Kepler’s Music of the Heavens, and Beyond . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106 7. Art Illustrates Science: Galileo, a Blemished Moon, and a Parabola of Blood . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 7.1. Galileo and Cigoli . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 7.2. Galileo and Artemisia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 115 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 8. Ensnared in Circles: Galileo and the Law of Projectile Motion . . . . . 123 8.1. The Problem with Projectiles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123 8.2. Galileo’s Abstraction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125 8.3. The Relativity of Motion and the Rotating Earth . . . . . . . . . . . . 127 8.4. Galileo’s Inertia in Context . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 130 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137 9. Aesthetics and Holism: Newton on Light, Color, and Music . . . . . . . 139 9.1. Newton Creates the Spectrum . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139 9.2. Newton Counts the Colors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 143 9.3. From Colors to Music . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 146 9.4. Newton’s Holism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 148 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 152 10. Missing One’s Own Discovery: Newton and the First Idea of an Artificial Satellite . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155 10.1. The PrincipiaProject: Origin and Execution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155 10.2. Newton’s Sketch—and the Problem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 160 10.3. The Projectile Path: What Did Newton Know? . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163 10.4. Newton and Hooke: A Debate Over a Spiral . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 169 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 172 Contents xiii 11. A Change of Mind: Newton and the Comet(s?) of 1680 and 1681 . . . 173 11.1. Comets and a Celestial Physics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 174 11.2. Newton’s Struggle with a Celestial Physics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 181 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186 12. A Well-Nigh Discovery: Einstein and the Expanding Universe . . . . . 187 12.1. Nebulae and Galaxies . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 187 12.2. Einstein’s Cosmological Model . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188 12.3. Observational Astronomy in the Early 20th Century . . . . . . . . . 191 12.4. Einstein Defends His Cosmological Constant . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 196 Notes and References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 199 Postlude . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 201 Prelude This is unabashedly an idiosyncratic look at science. Based heavily upon my research and publications—and hence personal interests—it expresses, perhaps, my quirky side. Ever since switching fields in graduate school, from physics to studying its history, I have come to recognize—and especially appreciate—what a thorny matter it is for the apparently simple laws of science to immerge out of the shad- ows of history. This, in turn, made me realize how remarkable and unobvious the expositions in today’s science textbooks are; what is eventually straightforward and transparent today was not so in the past. I did not appreciate the astonishing elegance of many science textbooks; that is, not until I studied the contrasting history of the subject. The subject of this book, however, is not textbook science; the textbook is the foil. A scientific idea, law, discovery, or experiment as expli- cated in a textbook is really a distillation of a multifaceted and often-intricate and convoluted historical narrative, with many missed starts, dead ends, mistakes, even sophistries and deceptions—a labyrinth of ingenuity and error that looks linear only after the fact. The book thusly is directed at the reader who is curious about science but whose exposure has been primarily from science courses and their accompanying textbooks—thus devoid of real history. This book is also intended for those who take pleasure in carefully studying pictures, illustrations, diagrams, of which there are scores in this book, and who are willing to spend the time required to compare and comprehend figure and text, so as to follow the historical narrative and scientific argument. A significant segment of what purports to be writings on science directed beyond the classroom and academy is done so under the stricture that the text should read rather like a novel—as if, God forbid, one might need to stop and ponder a picture or think about an idea. I expect that anyone reading this book “like a novel” is wasting one’s time. The overall structure of the book is plain. Sandwiched between two chapters on the doggedness of Einstein are ten more in approximately chronological order, beginning with an ancient astronomical measurement followed by episodes from the Scientific Revolution (Copernicus through Newton), with accompanying 1 2 Prelude background narratives from ancient science, telling tales revealing some quirky sides of scientists. The format is simple: every chapter constitutes more or less an essay unto itself; furthermore, each is divided into subsections, which are occa- sionally followed by boxed-in essays on specific peripheral topics. To preserve the integrity of the argument of each chapter while concomitantly avoiding too much duplication, I have cross-referenced relevant material from elsewhere in the book by section number, for example, “see section 2.3” means section 3 of Chapter 2. Accordingly, the book may be read in any order. So, begin browsing, perusing, reading—wherever you wish. 1 Tenacity and Stubbornness: Einstein on Theory and Experiment One of the common images of Einstein is this: lost in thought, he scribbles esoteric equations on the back of an envelope and creates a new world. Out of the mathematics on the envelope emerges a theory that he is so convinced is true, no experiment is required for proof. There are many stories of Einstein’s disdain for experiments, especially when the experiments contradicted his theories. But a deeper look into the matter reveals a more complex attitude toward experimenta- tion. Especially interesting is a little-known tale of Einstein himself engaged in an experiment to test one of his own theories—and how he confronted his own data. One of the guiding factors in all this was Einstein’s tenacity for sticking with a scientific problem, following wherever it leads, and stubbornly not straying from the quest. 1.1. Tenacity When once asked how he discovered the laws of physics, Newton said it was straightforward—he just thought about the problem, constantly. Confronted with a problem, Newton became obsessed until he solved it. But most of his life was not spent cracking what today we would consider problems in science; indeed, his interest in science was infrequent. Newton mostly was occupied with theology, church history, and alchemy, although for him they were all of a piece. Einstein, too, once he began, seemingly never stopped thinking about physics. But, in contrast to Newton, science was mostly what he pursued throughout his life. He had little commitment to his family, and except for his involvement with various social concerns (socialism, Zionism, the world-government movement), his life was spent zealously preoccupied with matters of physics. He tells us in his autobiography that at about the age of 16 he thought about a paradox concerning how light would appear if he traveled along with the light beam, and this imagi- nary ride led, about 10 years later, to what we now call the special theory of relativity. The resolution of the paradox entailed two principles: the relativity of motion and the invariant speed of light. In that year, 1905, he not only published two papers on relativity (in the second deducing E(cid:2)mc2) but also laid the 3