ebook img

Porphyry: On Abstinence from Killing Animals PDF

229 Pages·2000·1.49 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Porphyry: On Abstinence from Killing Animals

PORPHYRY On Abstinence from Killing Animals This page intentionally left blank PORPHYRY On Abstinence from Killing Animals Translated by Gillian Clark LONDON • NEW DELHI • NEW YORK • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com First published in 2000 by Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd. Paperback edition first published 2014 © Gillian Clark 2000 Gillian Clark asserts her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the author. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-0-7156-2901-7 PB: 978-1-7809-3889-9 ePDF: 978-1-7809-3888-2 Acknowledgements The present translations have been made possible by generous and imaginative funding from the following sources: the National Endowment for the Humanities, Division of Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the Leverhulme Trust; the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Board of the British Academy; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henri Brown Trust; Mr and Mrs Egon; the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO/GW). The editor wishes to thank Margaret Atkins, Bill Fortenbaugh, Andrew Smith, Dominic Montserrat, Catherine Osborne, and Frank Romer for their comments on the volume, and Sylvia Berryman for preparing the volume for press. Typeset by Ray Davies Printed and bound in Great Britain Contents Introduction 1 Translation 29 Book 1 31 Book 2 55 Book 3 80 Book 4 100 Notes 121 Bibliography 195 English-Greek Glossary 201 Greek-English Index 203 Subject Index 205 Index of Names and Places 215 Index of Animals, Birds, Reptiles and Fishes 219 In memoriam H.J. Blumenthal 30.3.1936 – 23.4.1998 Introduction 1. On Abstinence from Killing Animals On Abstinence from Killing Animals, written in the last third of the third century CE, is a treatise in the form of an open letter from Porphyry of Tyre to his friend Firmus Castricius. Both were philosophers, but Castricius had ‘reverted to consuming flesh’ (1.1.1): that is, he had abandoned the vegetarian diet which he and Porphyry had both thought essential for a committed philosopher. To reconvert him, Porphyry offers an impressive repertory of debate and observation about animals, humans and gods. Biology and theology, ethology and anthropology, are called in to support philosophy; food for the body and food for the soul are equal concerns. Are animals non-rational beings, and thereby excluded from any human com- munity, to be used as humans see fit – exploited as workers, killed for food or medicine or pleasure, or sacrificed to the gods? Do true gods demand the sacrifice of living creatures, or is what passes for religion only a cover for human greed and demonic manipulation? Why do humans acquiesce in the somnolent, desire-driven life of the body, ignoring the evidence that they are immortal souls, and what should they do to break free? Porphyry and Castricius probably met in Rome, when Porphyry joined (in 263 CE) the group which studied with the philosopher Plotinus. Forty years later, Porphyry described the group in the Life of Plotinus which he prefixed to the Enneads, his edition of the philosophical writings of Plotinus.1 This preface gives the most vivid picture we have of a late- antique philosopher among his students. The members of the group varied greatly in their choice of lifestyle. Plotinus, who came from somewhere in Egypt, would not talk about his home or family, had no property (he lodged in the house of a Roman lady, Gemina), was celibate and vegetarian, and ate, drank and slept little. Yet he accepted the social responsibilities of friendship. He acted as arbitrator in legal disputes, and took seriously his financial and educational duties as guardian for children whose father had died.2 Some of his students had heavier domestic, political and business commitments. There were Roman senators, doctors (from Palestine, Ara- bia and Alexandria), and even a professional public speaker who was also a moneylender. Castricius had estates in Campania, the best farming land in Italy, and probably decided on a political career. The senator Roga- tianus, in contrast, abandoned a political career for the study of philoso- phy. He refused to act as praetor (a very senior post with special responsibility for law) even when his official escort came to summon him, and he stayed with friends instead of being accessible in his own great 1 Introduction house. Rogatianus, Porphyry, Castricius, and probably others, were vege- tarian.3 As Porphyry said (Abst. 1.48.1), most philosophers approved of a frugal diet, but vegetarianism meant more than that. The title of this translation, On Abstinence from Killing Animals, tries to convey some of Porphyry’s purpose. His book is conventionally known as On Abstinence, or by the Latin title de Abstinentia, but its full title is On Abstinence from Animates: in Greek, peri apokhês empsukhôn. This is difficult to translate into Latin, or into English.4 apokhê is ‘holding back’, empsukha are not just living creatures (zôia) but creatures with souls. According to Porphyry, animals (unlike plants) have rational souls, less rational than human souls but still recognisably kin to humans. Animals can be seen to recognise and assess their situation, plan for the future, respond to each other and to humans, communicate with each other and (so far as human understanding allows) with humans. It is therefore wrong to kill animals for any reason other than immediate self-defence. It is especially wrong if the purpose is only to provide people with meat, a kind of food which for most people is both unnecessary and unhealthy. Porphyry of course approves of frugality and of kindness to animals, but these are not his only reasons for abstinence from killing and eating animals. Most philosophers agreed that commitment to philosophy requires a disciplined and moderate lifestyle. Porphyry and Castricius were Platon- ist philosophers, and for Platonists it was especially important to mini- mise the distraction caused to the soul by the desires of the body. They believed that the true self is the intellectual soul, which has temporarily fallen away from contemplating God because it is involved with the mortal body. Platonists (like Plato himself) had different ideas about the cause of this involvement: it might be inherent weakness, or excessive self-confi- dence, or natural affinity of souls for bodies, or a god-given mission to illuminate the material world.5 Whatever the cause, the soul now inhabits a world which is mortal, corporeal and changeable, at the furthest remove from God, and the mortal body demands the soul’s attention. But the soul is able to turn back towards God, and philosophers must work to purify body and soul from the contaminating effects of existence in the material world. The philosopher aims to ‘become like God’ (Plato, Theaetetus 176b), that is, ‘to be just and holy with wisdom’ so that the true self may rise towards God even in this life and be ready for return to God after death. Porphyry argues that the philosopher should concentrate on feeding the intellect with contemplation and thoughts about God. The body also must be fed, but not on meat. Meat requires expensive and distracting prepara- tion (1.46.2); it obstructs the soul by weighing down the body and stimu- lating desire (1.47.2); and it cannot be acquired without doing harm. Killing animals harms them because it takes away their souls (2.13.1), whereas God, who is wholly good, does no harm to anything (3.26.11). That 2 Introduction is a challenge to traditional Graeco-Roman belief about the relationship of humans, animals and gods. Meat-eating was closely linked to the Graeco-Roman mode of animal sacrifice, in which the inedible parts of the victim were burned for the gods, and the edible parts were eaten by the worshippers or sold off by the priests for others to eat. The everyday Mediterranean diet was based on grain made into bread or porridge and enlivened with whatever was available as a ‘relish’ (opson): oil, olives, herbs and vegetables, cheese, sometimes fish. For most people, only special occasions made it worth killing an animal for food. Such occasions – religious festivals and major life-events – also required the animal to be offered to the gods, in honour or thanksgiving or hope of benefit (2.24.1). This is not to say that meat was unobtainable without sacrifice. In town markets it was always available, and had not always been ritually butchered and offered.6 But Porphyry still had to counter the religious argument that by authorising sacrifice, the gods have authorised meat-eating by humans. The standard definition of ‘human’ (used by Porphyry in his Introduc- tion to Aristotle’s Categories) was ‘mortal rational animal’. We are below the gods because we are mortal like the other animals, but above the other animals because we are rational like the gods. This status is acknowledged when we offer sacrificial animals to gods, who need no food, and eat the meat ourselves. But according to Porphyry, gods, humans and animals are all rational. Animals are less rational than humans, but are still too close kin for us to kill them unless it is in immediate self-defence, as we would kill a dangerous human (2.22.2). Humans are less rational than gods, but are still capable of assimilation to the divine when freed from the body (perhaps even in brief experiences of union in this life), and should try to be as much like the gods as human life allows. We should therefore understand that gods do no harm and have no needs, least of all for dead flesh. They welcome simple bloodless offerings, such as grain or barley- cakes or flowers, which manifest the respect of ordinary unphilosophic people. From the philosophic few, the proper offering is contemplation and pure thought uncontaminated by the concerns of the body (2.34.2-3). When Porphyry heard that Castricius had lapsed from the beliefs they had shared, he knew it could not be from simple greed or from mistaken ideas about health, and he was anxious about the possible motives for this change (1.1.1-2.2). Why should he be anxious? As On Abstinence pro- gresses, some reasons become clear. Castricius might have been convinced by philosophic arguments that it is impossible, or simply mistaken, to treat animals as if they were humans, that is, to regard them as part of our society and kill them only in self-defence (1.4.1-4). But he might instead have been persuaded by Gnostics among the students of Plotinus that his enlighted soul was not affected by the experiences of his body (1 chs 41-2). Their position could seem to be supported by Plotinus’ belief (which was, as he knew, untraditional in Platonism) that there is a part 3

Description:
Porphyry's On Abstinence from Killing Animals is one of the most interesting books from Greek antiquity for both philosophers and historians. In it, Porphyry relates the arguments for eating or sacrificing animals and then goes on to argue that an understanding of humans and gods shows such sacrific
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.