ON EXISTENCE OF INFINITE PRIMES AND INFINITE TWIN PRIMES 5 Maurice Margenstern andYaroslavD. Sergeyev†‡ ∗ 1 0 2 b e Abstract F Thetwinprimesconjectureisaveryoldproblem. Tacitlyitissupposed 3 thattheprimesitdealswitharefinite. Inthepresentpaperweconsiderthree 2 problemsthatare notrelatedto finiteprimesbutdealwith infiniteintegers. ] Themaintoolofourinvestigationisanumeralsystemproposedrecentlythat M allowsonetoexpressvariousinfinitiesandinfinitesimalseasilyandbyafi- G nitenumberofsymbols.Theproblemsunderconsiderationarethefollowing . andforallofthemwegiveaffirmativeanswers: (i)doinfiniteprimesexist? h (ii)doinfinitetwinprimesexist?(ii)isthesetofinfinitetwinprimesinfinite? t a Examplesofthesethreekindsofobjectsaregiven. m [ KeyWords: Infiniteprimes,infinitetwinprimes,infinitesets. 2 v 1 Introduction 1 5 0 The research on twin primes number has given rise to an important number of 3 works(see, forexample, [6]andreferences giventherein). Inthispaper, westudy 0 . the problem of the existence of infinite primes and infinite twin primes. So, our 1 0 paper brings in no new light on the traditional twin primes conjecture. Let us 5 mention a few works which can be considered as precursors in some sense and 1 might be thought of an exotic character by pure mathematicians. As an example : v of such an exotic issue, we can quote the existence of other natural families of i X numbers whose distribution is alike that of primes. There is an example of such r a family for which an analogue of the twin primes can be formulated and was a indeed proved, see[14]. Now,whatwecanconsider asprecursors forusaremore connected with logical problems. The first paper in this direction is [11], where Maurice Margenstern, Ph.D., is Professor Emeritus at the Universite´ de Lorraine, e-mail: ∗ [email protected] †Yaroslav D. Sergeyev, Ph.D., D.Sc., D.H.C., is Distinguished Professor at the University of Calabria, Rende, Italy. He is also Professor (a part-time contract) at the Lobatchevsky State University, Nizhni Novgorod, Russia and Affiliated Researcher at the Institute of High Performance Computing and Networking of the National Research Council of Italy, e-mail: [email protected] ‡Correspondingauthor. 1 thepossibility ofinfiniteprimenumbersoftheformweconsider inthispaperwas investigated without reaching definite results. The second paper is [19] where the author constructs a model of a theory in which it is possible to prove the twin prime conjecture. There is an important difference in this paper with our result in this sense that the theory considered by this author assumes a weak induction axiomwhilehere, wehavenoinduction atalloninfiniteintegers. Theformofthe twinprimesinthatpaperhassomesimilarity withthatofourinfinitetwinprimes, although thepaperappealstohigherresultsinalgebraandanalysis whichisnotat allthecaseofourwork. Anumeralsystemintroducedrecentlyin[20,21]forperformingcomputations withinfinities andinfinitesimals isusedheretostudytheproblem oftheexistence ofinfiniteprimesandinfinitetwinprimes. Itshouldbementionedthatthiscompu- tationalmethodologyisnotrelatedtonon-standard analysisofRobinsonandhasa strong applied character. In fact, the Infinity Computer working numerically with a variety of infinite and infinitesimal numbers has been introduced (see the patent [23]). In order to see the place of the new approach in the historical panorama of ideasdealing withinfiniteandinfinitesimal, see[10,12,13,15,18,22,24,32]. In particular, connections of the new approach with bijections is studied in [15] and metamathematical investigations on the theory can be found in [13]. Among the applications where the new approach has been successfully used we can mention thefollowing: percolation andbiological processes (see[7,8,34,28]),hyperbolic geometry (see [16, 17]), numerical differentiation and optimization (see [1, 26, 36]),infiniteseries(see[9,22,27,35]),thefirstHilbertproblem,Turingmachines, and lexicographic ordering (see[24, 31, 32,33]), cellular automata (see [2,3,4]), ordinary differential equations (see[30]),etc. The rest of the paper has the following structure. The next Section contains a briefinformal description ofthenumeral system allowing onetoexpress different infinities and infinitesimals in a unique framework (see [21, 25, 29] for a detailed discussion). Section3presentsmainresultsofthepaper. 2 Infinitiesandinfinitesimalsexpressedingrossone-based numerals Letus consider a study published in Science (see [5])where there isa description of a primitive tribe living in Amazonia - Piraha˜ - that uses a very simple numeral system1 forcounting: one,two,many. ForPiraha˜,allquantitieslargerthantwoarejust‘many’andsuchoperationsas 1 We remind that numeral is a symbol or a group of symbols that represents a number. The differencebetweennumeralsandnumbersisthesameasthedifferencebetweenwordsandthethings theyreferto.Anumberisaconceptthatanumeralexpresses. Thesamenumbercanberepresented bydifferent numerals. Forexample, thesymbols ‘3’, ‘three’, and‘III’aredifferent numerals, but theyallrepresentthesamenumber. 2 2+2 and 2+1 give the same result, i.e., ‘many’. Using their weak numeral system Piraha˜ are not able to see numbers 3, 4, etc., to execute arithmetical operations with them, and, in general, to say anything about these numbers because in their language thereareneither wordsnorconcepts forthat. Moreover, theweaknessof theirnumeralsystemleadstosuchresultsas ‘many’+1=‘many’, ‘many’+2=‘many’, which are very familiar to us in the context of views on infinity used in the tradi- tionalcalculus ¥ +1=¥ , ¥ +2=¥ . This analogy advices that our difficulty in working with infinity is not connected to the nature of infinity but is just a result of inadequate numeral systems used to express numbers. In fact, numeral systems strongly influence our capabilities to describe physical andmathematical objects. Forinstance, Romannumeral system has no numeral to express 0. As a consequence, the expression III-X in this nu- meralsystemisanindeterminateform. Moreover,anyassertionregardingnegative numbers and zero cannot be formulated using Roman numerals because there are nosymbolscorresponding totheseconcepts inthisconcretenumeralsystem. The numeral system proposed in [21, 25, 29] is based on an infinite unit of measureexpressedbythenumeral① calledgrossoneandintroducedasthenumber of elements of the set N of natural numbers (a clear difference with non-standard analysiscanbeseenimmediatelysincenon-standard infinitenumbersarenotcon- nected to concrete infinite sets and do not belong to N). Other symbols dealing with infinities and infinitesimals (¥ , Cantor’s w , (cid:192) ,(cid:192) ,..., etc.) are not used to- 0 1 gether with ① . Similarly, when the positional numeral system and the numeral 0 expressing zero had been introduced, symbols V, X, and other symbols from the Romannumeralsystemhadnotbeeninvolved. Notice that people very often do not pay a great attention to the distinction betweennumbers andnumerals (inthisoccasion itisnecessary torecallconstruc- tivistswhostudiedthisissue),manytheoriesdealingwithinfiniteandinfinitesimal quantities have asymbolic (notnumerical) character. Forinstance, manyversions of non-standard analysis are symbolic, since they have no numeral systems to ex- presstheirnumbers byafinitenumberofsymbols(thefinitenessofthenumberof symbols isnecessary fororganizing numerical computations). Namely,ifwecon- siderafinitenthanitcanbetaken n=7,orn=108oranyothernumeral usedto express finite quantities and consisting of afinite number of symbols. Incontrast, ifweconsider anon-standard infinitemthen itisnotclear whichnumerals canbe usedtoassignaconcretevaluetom. Oneoftheimportantdifferences betweenthe new approach and non-standard analysis consists of the fact that the new numeral system allows us to assign concrete values to infinities (and infinitesimals) as it happens with finite values. In fact, we can assign m=① , m=3① 2 or to use − any other infinite numeral involving grossone to give a numerical value to m (see [21,25,29]foradetaileddiscussion). 3 The numeral ① allows one to construct different numerals expressing differ- ent infinities and infinitesimals and to execute numerical computations with all of them. Asaresult,inoccasionsrequiringinfinitiesandinfinitesimalsindeterminate formsandvariouskindofdivergencearenotpresentwhenoneworkswithany(fi- nite,infinite, orinfinitesimal) numbersexpressible inthenewnumeralsystemand it becomes possible to execute arithmetical operations with a variety of different infinities and infinitesimals. For example, for ① and ① 3.1 (that are examples of infinities)and① 1 and① 3.1 (thatareexamplesofinfinitesimals) itfollows − − ① 0 ① =① 0=0, ① ① =0, =1, ① 0=1, 1① =1, 0① =0, (1) · · − ① 0 ① 1=① 1 0=0, ① 3.1>① 1>1>① 1>① 3.1>0, − − − − · · ① 1 5+① 3.1 ① 1 ① 1=0, − =1, − =5① 3.1+1, (① 1)0=1, − − − ① 1 ① 3.1 − − − ① 3.1+4① ① ① 1=1, ① ① 3.1=① 2.1, =① 2.1+4, − − − ① · · ① 3.1 =① 6.2, (① 3.1)0=1, ① 3.1 ① 1=① 2.1, ① 3.1 ① 3.1=1. ① 3.1 · − · − − Itfollowsfrom(1)that① 0=1,therefore,afinitenumberacanberepresented in the new numeral system simply as a① 0 =a, where the numeral a itself can be written down by any convenient numeral system used to express finite numbers. The simplest infinitesimal numbers are represented by numerals having only neg- ativefinitepowersof① (e.g.,50.1① 10.2+16.38① 20.3,seealsoexamplesabove). − − Notice that all infinitesimals are not equal to zero. In particular, ①1 >0 because it is a result of division of two positive numbers. We shall not speak more about infinitesimals heresincetheyarenotusedinthepresentpaper. It should be mentioned that in certain cases ① -based numerals allow us to ex- ecute a finer analysis of infinite objects than traditional tools allow us to do. For instance, it becomes possible to measure certain infinite sets and to see, e.g., that the sets of even and odd numbers have ① /2 elements each. The set Z of integers has2① +1elements(① positiveelements,① negativeelements,andzero). Within thecountablesetsandsetshavingcardinality ofthecontinuum (see[12,24,25])it becomes possible to distinguish infinite sets having different number of elements expressible inthenumeralsystemusinggrossone andtoseethat,forinstance, ① <① 1<① <① +1<2① +1<2① 2 1<2① 2<2① 2+1< 2 − − ① ① ① ① ① ① ① 2① 2+2<2 1<2 <2 +1<10 <① 1<① <① +1. − − Itisimportanttostress thatthenewapproach doesnotcontradict Cantor’s results. The situation is similar to what happens when one uses a microscope with two different lenses: the first of them is weak and allows one to see the object of the 4 observation as two dots and another lens is stronger and allows the observer to see instead of the first dot 10 dots and instead of the second dot 32 dots. Both lenses give two correct answers having different accuracies. Analogously, both approaches, Cantor’s and the new one, give correct answers but the accuracy of the answers is different. Cantor’s tools say that the sets of even, odd, natural, and integer numbers have the same cardinality (cid:192) . This answer is correct with the 0 precisionthatcardinalnumbershave. However,thefactthattheyallhavethesame cardinality canbeviewedalsoastheaccuracy oftheusedinstrument istoolowto see that these sets have different numbers of elements. The new numeral system allowsustoseethesedifferencesamongsetshavingcardinality(cid:192) andamongsets 0 havingcardinality ofthecontinuum, aswell(see[12,15,24,25,29]foradetailed discussion including alsotheone-to-one correspondence issues). We conclude this brief informal introduction by mentioning that properties of grossonearedescribedbytheInfiniteUnitAxiom(see[24,25,29])thatisaddedto axiomsforrealnumbers. Inthecontext ofthepresent paper twoissues postulated bytheAxiomareimportantforus: grossone isaninfinitenumber;(ii)grossone is divisiblebyanyfiniteinteger. Noticethatgrossoneisnottheonlynumberenjoying thelatterproperty. Infact,zeroisalsodivisible byanyfiniteinteger. 3 Infinite primes and twin primes We need some definitions and conventions to continue our study. First, in the further consideration we use the following representation of an infinite number c whereitsinfinitepartisseparatedfromitsfinitepart: c=c +c . Inthisseparation, 1 2 c isinfiniteandisexpressedbynumeralsinvolving① andc isfiniteandisrepre- 1 2 sented bynumerals used towrite downfinitenumbers. Note that such arepresen- tation isnot unique. Forinstance, the number k=1.7① 1.5can bedecomposed as k =1.7① , k = 1.5, or as k˜ =1.7① 1, k˜ = 0−.5, or in some other way. 1 2 1 2 − − − Clearly, thisdecomposition becomes unique ifwerequire thatthepartc doesnot 1 containanypartexpressedbyfinitenumeralsonly. Inourexamplewiththedecom- positionofthenumberkwehaveitsuniquedecomposition k =1.7① , k = 1.5. 1 2 − Then,infinitenumbersthatdonotcontainfinitepartsarecalledpurelyinfinite. In other words, this means that in their unique decomposition they have c = 0. 2 Infinite numbers having their infinite part c including more than one infinite part 1 represented by different powers of ① are called compound. Numbers that are not compound are called simple. For instance, the numbers ① 3① 12 and ① 2+① + − 3.5 are both compound; the former is purely infinite while the latter is not. The ① numbers and① 2+1areexamplesofsimpleinfinitenumbers; againtheformer 2 ispurelyinfinitewhilethelatterisnot. Finally,ifafiniteorinfinitenumbercisthe squareofanintegerd,i.e.,c=d2,wesayhereinafter simplythatcisasquare. Lemma 3.1. There exist purely infinite simple numbers l divisible by all finite integers. 5 Proof. Duetoitsdefinition① issuchanumberl . Then,foranypositivefinite ① numbern, isalsoanexampleofsuchanumberl . Infact,foranyfinitenumber p n ① theproduct pnisfiniteand,therefore,itfollows pn① and,asaconsequence, p . | | n ① 2 Analogously, ① 2 and foranypositivefinitenumbernareexamplesofl . ✷ n Theorem3.1. Forallpurelyinfinite simplepositive integers l suchthatanyfinite positiveinteger dividesl itfollowsthatl +1isaprimenumber. Proof. Let us consider the number l +1, where l is a purely infinite simple positiveintegersuch pdividesl ,whateverthefinitenumber pis. Letusshowthat therearenointegersaandbsuchthata b=l +1. · Suppose that such integers exist. Then two situations are possible: (i) a is finiteandbisinfinite; (ii)both aand bareinfinite. Thefirstsituation cannot hold becausel isdivisiblebyanyfinitenumber p. Thereforeif pl +1,asalso pl then | | p1whichisimpossible. Andso,l +1cannothaveanontrivialfinitedivisor. | Thisfacthasitsimportancealsoforthecase(ii)whereaandbarebothinfinite. Itmeans they they cannot have finite divisors. Suppose the opposite, i.e., a=k c · where k is a finite integer and c is an infinite integer. Then l 1=k cb, i.e., we − · havethatl 1isproductofthefiniteintegerkandtheinfiniteintegercb. Sincekis − finite,duetoassumptions ofthelemmak l and,therefore, k l 1. Theobtained | 6| − contradiction provesthatinfinitenumbersaandbcannothavefinitedivisors. Letuslook atthe case (ii)and consider the unique decomposition of numbers aandbintheform a=a +a , b=b +b , (2) 1 2 1 2 wherethefirstpartsarepurelyinfiniteintegers (simpleorcompound) andthesec- ondpartsarefiniteintegers. Thenitshouldbe a b=(a +a )(b +b )=l +1, 1 2 1 2 · a b +a b +b a +a b =l +1. (3) 1 1 2 1 2 1 2 2 Letusdenotetheleft-hand partof(3)byLandtheright-hand partof(3)byR. Note that a b > a b and that a b > b a as a and b are finite integers. 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 1 2 2 | | | | | | | | Alsonotethata b =0isimpossibleasLwouldcontainnofinitepartwhileRdoes. 2 2 a b a b 1 1 1 1 Consequently, | | and | | are both infinite numbers. This means that in L, a b b a 2 1 2 1 | | | | thethree termsa b ,a b andb a areinfinite numbers whereoneofthem, a b , 1 1 2 1 2 1 1 1 isofahigherorderthantheothersandtheydonotcontainafinitepartinthesense of the unique decomposition of 2. Consequently, a b = 1 and a b +b a =0 2 2 2 1 2 1 since a b +b a is a smaller infinite than a b and l is a purely infinite simple 2 1 2 1 1 1 number. Asa and b areintegers, wegeta =b =1ora =b = 1. Possibly 2 2 2 2 2 2 − changing the sign of a and b wemay assume that a =b =1. Thisentails that 1 1 2 2 a +b =0whichgivesus a2=l whichisimpossible asl ispositive. ✷ 1 1 − 1 6 ① ① 2 Corollary 3.1. For all finite positive integers n, +1 and +1 are infinite n n primenumbers. Thus, we have proved the existence of infinite prime numbers and have given examples ofsuch numbers expressible in① -based numerals. Letus consider now theproblemoftheexistenceofinfinitetwinprimes. Lemma 3.2. For all purely infinite simple positive integers l such that any finite positive number divides l the infinite integer l 1 is a prime number if and only − ifl isnotthesquareofaninteger. Proof. Let us repeat the argument of Theorem 3.1 and find the factors of the numberl 1. Namely,wehavethatab=l 1,a=a +a ,b=b +b andasin 1 2 1 2 − − the proof of Theorem 3.1 we obtain that a b = 1and, therefore, it follows that 2 2 − a =b anda2=l . Ifl isnotasquare,thisisimpossibleandso,wegetthatl 1 1 1 1 − isaprimenumber. Now,ifl isasquare,weobtainl =(a 1)(a +1)wherethe 1 1 − integera satisfiesa =√l and,therefore, l 1cannotbeaprimenumber. ✷ 1 1 − Let us give an example. The infinite integer ① 2 can be taken as the number l and it can be easily seen that ① 2 1 is not prime since ① 2 1=(① 1)(① +1) − − − where① 1and① +1areinfiniteintegers. − Lemma 3.3. For all purely infinite simple positive integers l such that any finite positivenumberdividesl anditisasquareitfollowsthattheinfinitenumber l p2m+1 cannotbeasquareforfinitemand pwhere pisaprimenumber. Proof. Supposethat l isasquare. Thenitfollows l =r2,where,since p2m+1 p2m+1 p2m+1 isafinitenumber, risaninfiniteinteger. Thus,wecanwrite l = p2m+1 r2=(pmr)2 p. · · Since pis afinite prime number, it cannot be asquare. This result contradicts the fact that l is the square of an infinite integer and, therefore, we have proved that l cannotbeasquare. ✷ p2m+1 l Obviously, theinfinitenumber isanexampleillustrating Lemma3.3. 22m+1 Theorem3.2. Forallpurelyinfinite simplepositive integers l suchthatanyfinite positive number divides l and l is a square it follows that the numbers l 1 p2m+1 − l and +1areinfinitetwinprimesforallpositivefinitenumbersmand pwhere p2m+1 pisaprimenumber. Proof. By repeating the argument of Theorem 3.1 we find that the number l l +1isprime. ItfollowsfromLemma3.3that isnotasquare. Thus,due p2m+1 p2m+1 toLemma3.2itfollowsthat l 1isprime. ✷ p2m+1 − ① 2 ① 2 Numbers 1 and +1 are examples of infinite twin primes for all 22m+1 − 22m+1 positivefinitenumbersm. 7 NoticethatinTheorems3.1and3.2weneedonlytoassumethatl isdivisible byanyfiniteprimenumber. Inthefollowingtheoremtheassumptionthatanyfinite positiveintegerdividesl becomesessential. Theorem3.3. If: (i) l is an infinite simple positive integer such that any finite positive integer di- videsl ; (ii)l isasquare; (iii)misapositive integer; (iv) pisafiniteprimenumber; then: (i)thesetsA(p)haveinfinitely manyelements,where l A(p)= x:x= , p2m+1 l ; (4) { p2m+1 | } (ii)allnumbersx A(p)areinfiniteintegers; ∈ (iii)thenumberofelementsofthesetA(p)is M(p)=max m:y p2m+1=l , (5) { · } where p yand p2∤ y. | Proof. SupposethatthesetA=A(p)hasM=M(p)elements andM isfinite. Since numbers p2m+1 are strictly increasing, p2M+1 is the largest element in the set. Letusconsiderthenumber p2M+2. SinceMisfinite,itfollowsthatif p2M+2 l , | it should belong to A. However, M+1 > M, thus it cannot belong to A. This contradiction concludes theproofofthefirstassertionofthetheorem. Letusprovenowthatalltheelements ofthesetAareinfiniteintegers. Ifmin l (4)is a finite integer then the respective number y= is obviously an infinite p2m+1 integer. Supposenowthatmisinfiniteandyisfinite. Remindthatl isdivisibleby l allfinitenumbers. Thus, should bedivisible byallfinitenumbersexcluding, p2m+1 probably, p. This means that y cannot be finite since in this case it would be divisible onlybyafinitenumberofintegers. Letusprovethe thirdassertion ofthe theorem. Thefact p yfollows from our | supposition thatl isasquare. Supposenowthaty= p2y . Thenweobtainthat 1 y p2 p2M+1=y p2(M+1)+1=l . 1 1 · · · Thiscontradict thefactthatM isthemaximalnumbersuchthat p2M+1 l . ✷ | Corollary3.2. ResultsofLemma3.3andTheorem3.2holdforinfinitevaluesofm. 8 Corollary 3.3. Thesets ① 2 B(p)= x 1, x+1:x= , p2m+1 ① 2 , (6) { − p2m+1 | } ofinfinite primenumbers have2M(p)elements wheretheinfinite numberM(p)is from(5). Forinstance, itfollowsthattheset ① 2 B(2)= x 1, x+1:x= , 22m+1 ① 2 , { − 22m+1 | } consists ofinfiniteprimenumbersandhasinfinitelymanyelements. Weconclude the paper with the following rather obvious remark: substituting ① 2 in (6) by ① 4,① 16 or by any other infinite simple positive integer l being a squarewecangenerateotherinfinitesetsofinfiniteprimenumbers. References [1] S. De Cosmis and R. De Leone. The use of grossone in mathematical pro- gramming and operations research. Applied Mathematics and Computation, 218(16):8029–8038, 2012. [2] L.D’Alotto. Cellular automata using infinite computations. Applied Mathe- maticsandComputation, 218(16):8077–8082, 2012. [3] L.D’Alotto. Aclassification oftwo-dimensional cellular automata using in- finitecomputations. IndianJournalofMathematics, 55:143–158, 2013. [4] L.D’Alotto. Aclassificationofone-dimensionalcellularautomatausinginfi- nitecomputations. AppliedMathematicsandComputation,255:15–24,2015. [5] P. Gordon. Numerical cognition without words: Evidence from Amazonia. Science, 306(15October):496–499, 2004. [6] R.K. Guy, editor. Unsolved Problems in Number Theory. Springer-Verlag, NewYork,3dedition, 2004. [7] D.I. Iudin, Ya.D. Sergeyev, and M. Hayakawa. Interpretation of percolation in terms of infinity computations. Applied Mathematics and Computation, 218(16):8099–8111, 2012. [8] D.I. Iudin, Ya.D. Sergeyev, and M. Hayakawa. Infinity computations in cel- lularautomatonforest-firemodel. CommunicationsinNonlinearScienceand NumericalSimulation, 20(3):861–870, 2015. [9] V.KanoveiandV.Lyubetsky. Grossone approach toHuttonandEulertrans- forms. AppliedMathematicsandComputation, 255:36–43, 215. 9 [10] L.H.Kauffman. Infinitecomputations andthegenericfinite. AppliedMathe- maticsandComputation, 255:25–35, 2015. [11] J.G. Kemeny. Undecidable problems of elementary number theory. Mathe- matischeAnnalen, 135:160–169, 1958. [12] G. Lolli. Infinitesimals and infinites in the history of mathematics: A brief survey. AppliedMathematicsandComputation, 218(16):7979–7988, 2012. [13] G.Lolli. Metamathematicalinvestigationsonthetheoryofgrossone. Applied MathematicsandComputation, 255:3–14, 2015. [14] M.Margenstern. Lesnombrespratiques:the´orie,observationsetconjectures. JournalofNumberTheory,37:1–36, 1991. [15] M. Margenstern. Using grossone to count the number of elements of infi- nite sets and the connection with bijections. p-Adic Numbers, Ultrametric AnalysisandApplications, 3(3):196–204, 2011. [16] M. Margenstern. An application of grossone to the study of a family of tilings of the hyperbolic plane. Applied Mathematics and Computation, 218(16):8005–8018, 2012. [17] M. Margenstern. Fibonacci words, hyperbolic tilings and grossone. Com- munications in Nonlinear Science and Numerical Simulation, 21(1–3):3–11, 2015. [18] F. Montagna, G. Simi, and A. Sorbi. Taking the Piraha˜ seriously. Commu- nications in Nonlinear Science and Numerical Simulation, 21(1–3):52–69, 2015. [19] Yu.G.Penzin.Twinsprobleminformalarithmetic.Matematicheskiezametki, (transl.Mathematical Notes),26:505–511, 1979. [20] Ya.D. Sergeyev. Arithmetic of Infinity. Edizioni Orizzonti Meridionali, CS, 2003,2delectronic ed.2013. [21] Ya.D. Sergeyev. A new applied approach for executing computations with infiniteandinfinitesimal quantities. Informatica, 19(4):567–596, 2008. [22] Ya.D. Sergeyev. Numerical point of view on Calculus for functions assum- ingfinite, infinite, andinfinitesimal values overfinite, infinite, andinfinitesi- maldomains. NonlinearAnalysisSeriesA:Theory,Methods&Applications, 71(12):e1688–e1707, 2009. [23] Ya.D.Sergeyev. Computer system for storing infinite, infinitesimal, and fini- te quantities and executing arithmetical operations with them. USA patent 7,860,914, 2010. 10