ebook img

Notes on Measure, Probability and Stochastic Processes Jo˜ao Lopes Dias PDF

115 Pages·2017·0.55 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Notes on Measure, Probability and Stochastic Processes Jo˜ao Lopes Dias

Notes on Measure, Probability and Stochastic Processes Joa˜o Lopes Dias Departamento de Matema´tica, ISEG, Universidade de Lisboa, Rua do Quelhas 6, 1200-781 Lisboa, Portugal E-mail address: [email protected] December 22, 2017. Contents Chapter 1. Introduction 1 1. Classical definitions of probability 1 Chapter 2. Measure and probability 3 1. Algebras 3 2. Monotone classes 7 3. Product algebras 8 4. Measures 9 5. Examples 16 Chapter 3. Measurable functions 19 1. Definition 19 2. Simple functions 21 3. Convergence of sequences of measurable functions 22 4. Induced measure 24 5. Generation of σ-algebras 25 Chapter 4. Lebesgue integral 27 1. Definition 27 2. Properties 30 3. Examples 32 4. Convergence theorems 33 5. Fubini theorem 40 6. Weak convergence of sequences of probability measures 41 Chapter 5. Distributions 43 1. Definition 43 2. Simple examples 44 3. Distribution functions 46 4. Classification of distributions 48 5. Characteristic functions 49 6. Convergence in distribution 54 Chapter 6. Limit theorems 55 1. Independent random variables 55 2. Sums of random variables 58 3. Law of large numbers 60 4. Central limit theorem 61 iii iv CONTENTS Chapter 7. Conditional expectation 63 1. Radon-Nikodym theorem 63 2. Conditional expectation 67 3. Conditional probability 70 Chapter 8. Markov chains 73 1. The Markov property 73 2. Homogeneous Markov chains 77 3. Classification of states 79 4. Decomposition of chains 84 5. Stationary distributions 87 6. Limit distributions 88 Chapter 9. Martingales 91 1. The martingale strategy 91 2. General definition of a martingale 93 3. Examples 94 4. Stopping times 95 5. Stochastic processes with stopping times 96 Appendix A. Things that you should know before starting 99 1. Notions of mathematical logic 99 2. Set theory notions 101 3. Function theory notions 105 4. Greek alphabet 109 Bibliography 111 CHAPTER 1 Introduction These are the lecture notes for the course “Probability Theory and StochasticProcesses”oftheMasterinMathematicalFinance2016/2017 atISEG–UniversityofLisbon. Itisrequiredgoodknowledgeofcalculus and basic probability. 1. Classical definitions of probability Scienceisaboutobservinggivenphenomena,recordingdata,analysing it and explaining particular features and behaviours using theoretical models. This may be a rough description of what really means to make science, but highlights the fact that experimentation is a crucial part of obtaining knowledge. Many experiments are of random nature. That is, their results are not possible to predict, often due to the huge number of variables that underlie the processes under scrutiny. One needs to repeat the exper- iment and observe its different outcomes and events (sets of possible outcomes). Our main goal is to quantify the likelihood of each event. Thesegeneralideascanbeillustratedbytheexperimentofthrowing a dice. We can get six possible outcomes depending on too many different factors, so that it becomes impossible to predict the result. Consider the event corresponding to an even number of dots, i.e. 2, 4 or 6 dots. How can we measure the probability of this event to occur when we throw the dice once? The way one usually thinks of probability is summarised in the following relation: number of favourable cases Probability(“event”) = number of possible cases assuming that all cases are equally possible. This is the classical defi- nition of probability (called the Laplace law). Example 1.1. Tossing of a perfect coin in order to get either heads or tails. The number of possible cases is 2. So, Prob(“heads”) = 1/2 Prob(“heads at least once in two experiments”) = 3/4. 1 2 1. INTRODUCTION Example 1.2. 1 Probability(“winning the Euromillions with one bet”) = (cid:39) 7×10−9. C50C12 5 2 The above definition is far from what one could consider as a useful definition of probability. For instance, we would like to examine also “biased”experiments, that is, withinequally possibleoutcomes. Away to deal with this question is defining probability by the frequency that some event occurs when repeating the experiment many times under the same conditions. So, number of favourable cases in n experiments Probability(“event”) = lim . n→+∞ n Example 1.3. In 2015 there was 85500 births in Portugal and 43685 were boys. So, Probability(“it’s a boy!”) (cid:39) 0.51. A limitation of this second definition of probability occurs if one considers infinitely many possible outcomes. The modern probability is based in measure theory, bringing a fun- damental mathematical rigour and an abrangent concept (although very abstract as we will see). This course is an introduction to this subject. CHAPTER 2 Measure and probability 1. Algebras Given an experiment we consider Ω to be the set of all possible outcomes. This is the probabilistic interpretation that we want to associate to Ω, but in the point of view of the more general measure theory, Ω is just any set. The collection of all the subsets of Ω is denoted by P(Ω) = {A: A ⊂ Ω}. It is also called the set of the parts of Ω. When there is no ambiguity, we will simply write P. We say that Ac = Ω\A is the complement of A ∈ P in Ω. As we will see later, a proper definition of the measure of a set re- quires several properties. In some cases, that will restrict the elements of P that are measurable. It turns out that the measurable ones just need to verify the following conditions. A collection A ⊂ P is an algebra of Ω iff (1) ∅ ∈ A, (2) If A ∈ A, then Ac ∈ A, (3) If A ,A ∈ A, then A ∪A ∈ A. 1 2 1 2 An algebra F of Ω is called a σ-algebra of Ω iff given A ,A ,··· ∈ F 1 2 we have +∞ (cid:91) A ∈ F. n n=1 Remark 2.1. We can easily verify by induction that any finite union of elements of an algebra is still in the algebra. What makes a σ-algebra different is that the infinite countable union of elements is still in the σ-algebra. Example 2.2. Consider the set A of all the finite union of intervals in R including R and ∅. Notice that the complementary of an interval is a finite union of intervals. Therefore, A is an algebra. However, the countable union of the sets A =]n,n + 1[∈ A, n ∈ N, is no longer n finite. That is, A is not a σ-algebra. 3 4 2. MEASURE AND PROBABILITY Remark 2.3. Any finite algebra A (i.e. it contains only a finite numberofsubsetsofΩ)isimmediatelyaσ-algebra. Indeed,anyinfinite union of sets is in fact finite. The elements of a σ-algebra F are called measurable sets. In prob- ability theory they are also known as events. The pair (Ω,F) is called a measurable space. Exercise 2.4. Decide if F is a σ-algebra of Ω where: (1) F = {∅,Ω}. (2) F = P(Ω). (3) F = {∅,{1,2},{3,4,5,6},Ω}, Ω = {1,2,3,4,5,6}. (4) F = (cid:8)∅,{0},R−,R−,R+,R+,R\{0},R(cid:9), Ω = R. 0 0 Proposition 2.5. Let F ⊂ P such that it contains the comple- mentary set of all its elements. For A ,A ,··· ∈ F, 1 2 +∞ +∞ (cid:91) (cid:92) A ∈ F iff A ∈ F. n n n=1 n=1 Proof. (⇒) Using Morgan’s laws, +∞ (cid:32)+∞ (cid:33)c (cid:92) (cid:91) A = Ac ∈ F n n n=1 n=1 because the complements are always in F. (⇐) Same idea. (cid:3) Therefore, the definitions of algebra and σ-algebra can be changed to require intersections instead of unions. Exercise 2.6. Let Ω be a finite set with #Ω = n. Compute #P(Ω). Hint: Find a bijection between P and {v ∈ Rn: v ∈ {0,1}}. i Exercise 2.7. Let Ω be an infinite set, i.e. #Ω = +∞. Consider the collection of all finite subsets of Ω: C = {A ∈ P(Ω): #A < +∞}. Is C an algebra? Is it a σ-algebra? Exercise 2.8. Let (Ω,F) be a σ-algebra. Consider two disjoint sets A,B ⊂ Ω and assume that A ∈ F. Show that A ∪ B ∈ F is equivalent to B ∈ F? 1. ALGEBRAS 5 1.1. Generation of σ-algebras. In many situations we want to consider some specific collection of subsets to be measurable because of their relevance to the problem we are studying. If the collection is not already a σ-algebra, we need to take a larger one that it is. That is called the σ-algebra generated by the original collection. Take I to be any set (of indices). Theorem 2.9. If F is a σ-algebra, α ∈ I, then F = (cid:84) F is α α∈I α also a σ-algebra. Proof. (1) As for any α we have ∅ ∈ F , then ∅ ∈ F. α (2) Let A ∈ F. So, A ∈ F for any α. Thus, Ac ∈ F and Ac ∈ F. α α (cid:83) (3) If A ∈ F, we have A ∈ F for any α. So, A ∈ F and n n α n n α (cid:83) A ∈ F. n n (cid:3) Consider now the collection of all σ-algebras: Σ = {all σ-algebras of Ω}. So, P ∈ Σ and {∅,Ω} ∈ Σ. In addition, let I ⊂ P be a collection of subsets of Ω, i.e. I ⊂ P, not necessarily a σ-algebra. Define the subset of Σ given by the σ-algebras that contain I, Σ = {F ∈ Σ: I ⊂ F}. I The σ-algebra generated by I is the intersection of all σ-algebras containing I, (cid:92) σ(I) = F. F∈ΣI Hence, σ(I) is the smallest σ-algebra containing I (i.e. it is contained in all σ-algebras that contain I). Example 2.10. (1) Let A ⊂ Ω and I = {A}. Any σ-algebra containing I has to include the sets ∅, Ω, A and Ac. Since these sets form already a σ-algebra, we have σ(I) = {∅,Ω,A,Ac}. (2) Consider two disjoint sets A,B ⊂ Ω and I = {A,B}. The generated σ-algebra is σ(I) = {∅,Ω,A,B,Ac,Bc,A∪B,(A∪B)c}. 6 2. MEASURE AND PROBABILITY (3) Consider now two different sets A,B ⊂ Ω such that A∩B (cid:54)= ∅, and I = {A,B}. Then, σ(I) ={∅,Ω,A,B,Ac,Bc, A∪B,A∪Bc,Ac ∪B,(A∪B)c,(A∪Bc)c,(Ac ∪B)c, Bc ∪(A∪Bc)c,(Bc ∪(A∪Bc)c)c, ((A∪Bc)c)∪((Ac ∪B)c),(((A∪Bc)c)∪((Ac ∪B)c))c} ={∅,Ω,A,B,Ac,Bc, A∪B,A∪Bc,Ac ∪B,Ac ∩Bc,B \A,A\B, (A∩B)c,A∩B, (A∪B)\(A∩B),(Ac ∩Bc)∪(A∩B)}. Exercise 2.11. Show that (1) If I ⊂ I ⊂ P, then σ(I ) ⊂ σ(I ). 1 2 1 2 (2) σ(σ(I)) = σ(I) for any I ⊂ P. Exercise 2.12. Consider a finite set Ω = {ω ,...,ω }. Prove that 1 n I = {{ω },...,{ω }} generates P(Ω). 1 n Exercise 2.13. Determine σ(C), where C = {{x} ∈ P: x ∈ Ω}. What is the smallest algebra that contains C. 1.2. Borel sets. A specially important collection of subsets of R in applications is I = {]−∞,x] ⊂ R: x ∈ R}. It is not an algebra since it does not contain even the emptyset. An- other collection could be obtained by considering complements and intersections of pairs of sets in I. That is, I(cid:48) = {]a,b] ⊂ R: −∞ ≤ a ≤ b ≤ +∞}. Here we are using the following conventions ]a,+∞] =]a,+∞[ and ]a,a] = ∅ so that ∅ and R are also in the collection. The complement of ]a,b] ∈ I(cid:48) is still not in I(cid:48), but is the union of two sets there: ]a,b]c =]−∞,a]∪]b,+∞]. So, the smallest algebra that contains I corresponds to the collection of finite unions of sets in I(cid:48), (cid:40) (cid:41) N (cid:91) A(R) = I ⊂ R: I ,...,I ∈ I(cid:48),N ∈ N . n 1 N n=1 Clearly, I ⊂ I(cid:48) ⊂ A(R).

Description:
Lisboa, Rua do Quelhas 6, 1200-781 Lisboa, Portugal. E-mail address: [email protected] 3. Convergence of sequences of measurable functions. 22. 4. Induced measure. 24. 5. Generation of σ-algebras. 25. Chapter 4. Lebesgue integral. 27. 1. Definition. 27. 2. Properties. 30. 3. Examples. 32. 4.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.