ebook img

No limit model in inaccessible PDF

0.19 MB·
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview No limit model in inaccessible

NO LIMIT MODEL IN INACCESSIBLE 7 0 Saharon Shelah 0 2 The Hebrew University of Jerusalem y Einstein Institute of Mathematics a M Edmond J. Safra Campus, Givat Ram Jerusalem 91904, Israel 9 2 Department of Mathematics Hill Center-Busch Campus ] O Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey L 110 Frelinghuysen Road . h Piscataway, NJ 08854-8019 USA t a m Abstract. Our aim is to improve the negative results i.e. non-existence of limit [ models, and the failure of the generic pair property from [Sh 877] to inaccessible λ 1 as promised there. The motivation is that in [Sh:F756] the positive results are for λ v measurable hence inaccessible, whereas in [Sh 877] in the negative results obtained 1 only on non-strong limit cardinals. 3 1 4 . 5 0 7 0 : v i X r a The author would like to thank the Israel Science Foundation for partial support of this research (Grant No.242/03). Publication 906. I would like to thank Alice Leonhardt for the beautiful typing. Typeset by AMS-TEX 1 2 SAHARON SHELAH §0 Introduction [Sh:F576] contains results “for T dependent the generic pair property holds”; see introduction there. Here we have complimentary results. Let λ be strongly inaccessible (> |T|) such that λ+ = 2λ. Here in §1 we prove that for strongly independent T (see Definition 0.2), a strong version of the generic pair conjecture (see Definition 0.5(2)) holds. We also prove the non-existence of (λ,κ)-limit models, a related property (for all version of limit). In §2, we also prove this even for independent T. The use of λ+ = 2λ is just to have a more transparent formulation of the conjecture. 0.1 Notation: 1) D is the club filter on λ for λ regular uncountable. λ 2) Sλ = {δ < λ:cf(δ) = κ}. κ 3) For a limit ordinal δ let Pub(δ) = {U : U is an unbounded subset of δ}. [used?] 4) T denotes a complete first order theory. Recall (as in [Sh 877, 2.3]) 0.2 Definition. 1) T has the strong independence property (or is strongly inde- pendent) when: some ϕ(x¯,y) ∈ L(τ ) has it, where: T 2) ϕ(x¯,y¯) ∈ L(τ ) has the strong independence property for T when for every T n < ω, model M of T and pairwise distinct ¯b ,...,¯b ∈ ℓg(y¯)(M) for some 0 2n−1 a¯ ∈ ℓg(y¯)M we have ℓ < 2n ⇒ M |= ϕ[a¯,¯b ]if(ℓ is even). ℓ Remark. 1) Elsewhere we use ϕ(x,y), and the proof are not affected. ¯ 2) Also if we restrict ourselves to a ,a ,...,∈ ψ(M,d) where ψ ∈ L(τ ) such that 0 1 T ¯ ¯ ψ(M,d) is infinite, and we may restrict ourselves to b’s realizing a fix non-algebraic type p ∈ Sm(A,M) with M being (|A|++ℵ )-saturated. The results are not really 0 affected. 0.3 Question: 1) Assume λ = λ<λ1 ≥ λ > |T|,T a complete first order theory. 2 2 1 When is the theory T∗ a dependent theory? where λ ,λ 1 2 (a) T∗ = Th(K+ ) where λ ,λ λ ,λ 1 2 1 2 (b) K+ = {(M,N) : M is a λ -saturated model of T of cardinality λ ,N a λ ,λ 1 2 1 2 λ+-saturated elementary extension of M}. 2 2) Similarly for other properties of T∗ ; note that this theory is complete. λ ,λ 1 2 2A) When can we prove that T∗ does not depend on the cardinals at least for λ ,λ 1 2 NO LIMIT MODEL IN INACCESSIBLE 3 many pairs? 3) Characterize when in Th(M,N) we cannot (with parameters) interpret PA. Remark. 1) It is known that in 0.3(1) if T extends PA or ZFC then in T∗ = Th(M,N) we can interpret the second order theory of λ . 2 2) It seems to me that it is known that there is a Boolean algebra B and four ideals I ,...,I of it such that in Th(B,I ,I ,I ,I ) we can interpret PA hence this says 0 3 0 1 2 3 the Boolean algebra are high in 0.3(3). But may well be that as in Baldwin-Shelah [BlSh 156] 0.4 Question: Assume |T| < κ ≤ λ ≤ λ = λ<λ1,T a complete first order. For 1 2 2 which T’s can we interpret in M ∈ K+ a model of PA of cardinality ≥ λ by λ ,λ 1 1 2 an L (τ )-formulas with parameter, the intention for λ large enough than λ ∞,κ T 2 1 which is large enough than T if 2κ ≥ λ this is trivial. 1 Recall (from ([Sh 877, 0.2]) 0.5 Definition. 0) Let EC (T) be the class of model M of (the first order) T of λ cardinality λ. 1) Assume λ = λ<λ > |T|,2λ = λ+,M ∈ EC (T) is ≺-increasing continuous for α λ α < λ+ with ∪{M : α < λ+} ∈ EC (T) saturated. The generic pair property α λ+ (for T,λ) says that for some club E of λ+ for all pairs α < β of ordinals from E of cofinality λ,(M ,M ) has the same isomorphism type (we denote this property of β α T by Pr2 (T)). λ,λ 2) The generic pair conjecture for λ = λ<λ > ℵ such that 2λ = λ+ says that for 0 any complete first order T of cardinality < λ,T is independent iff it has the generic pair property for λ. 3) Let ncκ(T) be min{|{M / ∼=: δ ∈ E has cofinality κ}| : E a club of λ+} for λ δ M¯ = hM : α < λ+i as above; clearly the choice of M¯ is immaterial. α 0.6 Remark. 1) Note that to say ncκ(T) = 1 is a way to say that T has (some λ variant of) a (λ,κ)-limit model. 2) Recall that we conjecture that for λ = λ<λ > κ = cf(κ) > |T|,2λ = λ+ we have ncκ|T| = 1 ⇔ ncκ(T) < 2λ ⇔ T is dependent. The use of “λ+ = 2λ” is for clarity. λ λ See more in [Sh 877]. 4 SAHARON SHELAH §1 Strongly independent T Context. T is a fixed first order complete theory and C = C a monster for it. T Here for λ strongly inaccessible and (complete first order) T with the strong independence property (of cardinality < λ) we prove the non-existence of (λ,κ)- limit models for κ = cf(κ) < λ (in Theorem 1.8) and the generic pair conjecture for λ and T, in Theorem 1.9 (which shows non-isomorphism). Recall that the generic pair property speaks on the isomorphism type of pairs of models. ∼ Definition 1.1 gives us a more constructive invariant of (M,N)/ =. Unfortu- nately it seemed opaque how to manipulate it so we shall use a different version, the one from Definition 1.3. Naturally it concentrates on types in one formula ϕ(y,x¯) witnesssing the strong independence property. But mainly gives the pair (M,N) an invariant hP : δ < λi/D where P ⊆ P(P(δ)). Now always |P | ≤ 2|δ| and it is δ λ δ δ easily computable from one P ⊆ P(δ), in fact from the invariant inv (M,N) from 4 Definition 1.1, but in our proofs its use is more transparent. It has monotonicity property and we can increase it. We need different but similarversion for the proof of non-existence of (λ,κ)-limit models. 1.1 Definition. 1) Let E∗ be the following relation on {(M,P) : M |= T and T P ⊆ S<ω(M)}; let (M ,P )E∗(M ,P ) iff there is an isormorphism h from M 1 1 T 2 2 1 onto M mapping P onto P . 2 1 2 2) For model M ≺ N of T we define (a) inv (M,N) = {p ∈ S<ω(M) : p is realized in N} 1 (b) inv (M,N) = (M,inv (M,N))/E∗. 2 1 T 3) If M ≺ N are models of T such that the universe of N is ⊆ λ, let, recalling D λ is the club filter on λ (a) for any ordinal δ < λ inv (δ,M,N) = (N ↾ δ,{p ∈ S<ω(N ↾ δ) : p is realized by some sequence 3 from M})/E∗ T (b) inv (M,N) = hinv (δ,M,N)) : δ < λi/D . 4 3 λ 4) If M ≺ N aremodels ofT ofcardinality λthen inv (M,N)isinv (f(M′),f(N′)) 4 4 for every one-to-one function f from N into λ (equivalently some f, see below) 1.2 Observation. 1) Concerning Definition 1.1(3), if M ≺ N are models of T of car- dinalityλandf ,f areone-to-onefunctionsfromN intoλtheninv (f (M),f (N)) = 1 2 4 1 1 NO LIMIT MODEL IN INACCESSIBLE 5 inv (f (M),f (N)). 4 2 2 2) Definitions 1.1(3), 1.1(4) are compatible and in 1.1(4), “some f” is equivalent to “every f such that...” 1.3 Definition. Assume ϕ = ϕ(x¯,y¯) ∈ L(τ ) and N ≺ N are models of T of T 1 2 cardinality λ. 1) For one-to-one mapping f from N to λ and δ < λ we define 2 invϕ(δ,f,N ,N ) = {P : there are a¯ ∈ ℓg(y¯)N for γ < δ such that 5 1 2 γ 2 f(a¯ ) ⊆ δ and for every U ⊆ δ the following are equivalent : γ (i) U ∈ P (ii) for some ¯b ∈ ℓg(y¯)N we have γ < δ ⇒ N |= ϕ[a¯ ,¯b]if(γ∈U)}. 1 2 γ 2) We let invϕ(N ,N ) be hinvϕ(δ,f,N ,N ) : δ < λi/D for some (equivalently 6 1 2 5 1 2 λ every) f as above. ϕ 1.4 Claim. 1) In Definition 1.3 we have inv (N ,N ) is well defined. 6 1 2 2) In Definition 1.3, for δ,λ,N ,N ,ϕ(x¯,y¯) as there 1 2 (a) the set invϕ(δ,f,N ,N ) has cardinality at most 2|δ| 5 1 2 (b) if π is a one-to-one function from f(N ) into λ mapping f(N ) ∩ δ onto 2 2 ϕ ϕ π(f(N )∩δ then inv (δ,π ◦f,N ,N ) = inv (δ,f,N ,δ ). 2 5 1 2 5 1 2 (cid:3) 1.4 Proof. Easy. 1.5 Definition. 1) For ϕ = ϕ(y¯,x¯) ∈ L(τ ), a model N of T with universe λ,δ an T ordinal < λ and κ < λ let invϕ (ϕ,N) = {P ⊆ P(δ) : we can find a¯i ∈ ℓg(x¯)δ for γ < δ,i < κ such that 7,κ γ the following conditions on U ⊆ δ unbounded in δ are equivalent : (i) U ∈ P ¯ (ii) for some b ∈ N we have : for every i < κ large enough for every γ < δ we have N |= ϕ[a¯i,¯b]if(γ∈U)}. γ 6 SAHARON SHELAH ϕ 2) For ϕ = ϕ(y¯,x¯) ∈ L(τ ) and a model N of T of cardinality λ let inv (N) = T 8,κ hinvϕ(δ,N) : δ < λi/D for every, equivalently some model N′ isomorphic to N 7 λ with universe λ. ϕ 1.6 Observation. 1) inv (N) is well defined for N ∈ EC (T) when |T|+κ < λ. 8,κ λ 2) In Definition 1.5(1) we have |invϕ (δ,N)| ≤ 2|δ|. 7,ϕ Proof. Easy. 1.7 Claim. Assume λ > |T| is regular, ϕ = ϕ(x¯,y¯) and (a) hN : i < κi is a ≺-increasing sequence i (b) N ∈ EC (T) i λ (c) N = ∪{N : i < κ} i (d) P¯ = hP : α < λi where P ⊆ P(α) α α (e) f is a one-to-one function from N onto λ (f) there are a¯ ∈ N for α < λ such that for every i < κ for a club of δ < λ α 0 there are ¯b ∈ N ∩f−1(δ) for γ < δ satisfying γ i+1 (α) for every c¯ ∈ ℓg(x¯)N there is U ∈ P such that γ < δ ⇒ N |= 0 δ ϕ[c¯,¯b ]if(γ∈U) γ (β) foreveryU ∈ P there isα < λ such that γ < δ ⇒ N |= ϕ[a¯ ,¯b ]if(γ∈A). δ α γ Then {δ < λ : P ∈ invϕ (δ,f(N))} ∈ D . δ 7,κ λ Proof. Straight. Now we come to the main two results of this section. 1.8 Theorem. For some club E of λ, if δ 6= δ belongs to E∩Sλ+ then M ,M 1 2 κ δ1 δ2 are not isomorphic when: ⊠ (a) T has the strong independence property (see Definition 0.2) and (b) λ = λ<λ regular uncountable, λ > |T|,λ > κ = cf(κ) and λ+ = 2λ (c) M is a saturated model of T of cardinality λ+ (d) hM : α < λ+i is ≺-increasing continuous sequence with union M, α each of cardinality λ. NO LIMIT MODEL IN INACCESSIBLE 7 1.9 Theorem. Assume ⊠ of 1.8. 1) For some club E of λ+, if δ < δ < δ are from E and δ ∈ Sλ+ then 1 2 3 ℓ λ ϕ ϕ (M ,M ) ≇ (M ,M ), moreover inv (M ,M ) 6= inv (M ,M ) for some δ1 δ2 δ1 δ3 6 δ1 δ2 6 δ1 δ3 ϕ. 2) If M ≺ N are models of T of cardinality λ, then for some elementary extension ∼ N ∈ EC (T) of N we have N ≺ N ∈ EC (T) ⇒ (M,N ) = (M,N ). 1 λ 1 2 λ 1 2 Discussion: We shall below start with M ∈ EC (T) and sequence hb : i < λi λ i of distinct members such that hϕ(b ,y¯) : i < λi are independent, and like to find i N,ha¯ : i < λi such that M ≺ N ∈ EC (T) and the hb : i < λi has a real i λ i ϕ affect on the relevant ϕ-invariant, in the case of 1.9(1) this is inv (M,N): for 6 a stationary set of δ < λ it add something to the δ-th component in a specific representation, i.e. assuming f : N → λ is a one-to-one function and we deal with ϕ hinv (δ,f ,M,N) : δ < λi. We have freedom about ϕ(b ,¯a ) and we can assume 5 1 i α b ∈ M\{b : i < λ} ⇒ N |= ¬ϕ[b,a ]. i α But the relevant P is influenced not just by say hb : i ∈ [δ,2|δ|)i but by later δ i b ’s (and earlier b ). To control this we use below ha¯ : α < λi,S,E such that we i i α deal with different δ ∈ S in an independent way; this is the reason for choosing the c ’s. α Proof 1.8. By [Sh 877, §2] without loss of generalityλ is strongly inaccessible. Choose θ ∈ Reg ∩λ\{ℵ }, will be needed when we generalize the proof in §2. 0 Let hU : i < κi be a ⊆-increasing sequence of subsets of λ such that U − = i i U \∪{U : j < κ} has cardinality λ for each i < κ. Let ϕ(x¯,y) ∈ L(τ ) have the i j T strong independent property, see Definition 0.2. Let S = {µ : µ = i for some α < λ}. Let E,ζ,hC : α < λi be such that: ∗ α+ω α ⊛ (a) C ⊆ α∩S 1 α ∗ (b) β ∈ C ⇒ C = C ∩β α β α (c) otp(C ) ≤ θ α (d) E is the club {δ < λ : δ = i } of λ ∗ δ (e) C ⊆ E and otp(C ) = θ iff α ∈ E ∩Sλ α ∗ α ∗ θ (d) if α ∈ S := E ∩Sλ then α = sup(C ). ∗ θ α We shall prove that ⊛ if ⊡ below holds, then there is a pair (β,h) such that ⊙ holds where: 2 2 2 ⊡ (a) α < λ+,i < κ 2 (b) f is a one-to-one function from M onto U α i (c) E ⊆ E is a club of λ such that δ ∈ E ⇒ f(M ) ↾ δ ≺ f(M ) ∗ α α 8 SAHARON SHELAH (d) P¯ = hP : δ ∈ Si δ (e) Pδ ⊆ P(δ) and ∅ ∈ Pδ and Pδ ⊆ [ Pδℓ,∗ where ℓ≤2 (α) P∗,0 = {A ⊆ δ : sup(A) = δ and A ⊆ ∪{[µ,2µ) : µ ∈ C }, δ δ (β) P∗,1 = ∪{P∗,0 : µ ∈ S ∩δ}, δ µ (γ) P∗,2 = {A ⊆ δ: for some µ ∈ λ\(δ+1) we have δ A ⊆ ∪{[∂,2∂) : ∂ ∈ C ∩δ} µ (f) if δ < δ are from E then 1 2 (α) [A ∈ P ⇒ A ∈ P∗,1 ⊆ P ] δ1 δ2 δ2 (β) [A ∈ P ⇒ A∩δ ∈ P∗,2 ⊆ P ], δ2 1 δ1 δ1 (γ) for any δ ∈ S the family P∗,1 ∪P∗,2 is a set of bounded δ δ subsets of δ; (this follows) (g) bδ,U ∈ Mα for δ ∈ E,U ∈ Pδ are such that bδ ,U = bδ ,U ⇒ 1 1 2 2 δ = δ ∧U = U 1 2 1 2 ⊙ (α) β ∈ (α,λ+) 2 (β) h is a one-to-one mapping form M onto U extending f β i+1 (γ) for a club of δ ∈ E there are a¯ ∈ (U ∩δ) for α < δ such that α i+1 the following conditions on U ⊆ δ are equivalent: (i) U ∈ P δ (ii) forsomeb ∈ M wehave: foreveryγ < δ,f(M ) |= ϕ[a¯ ,b] α β γ iff γ ∈ U (iii) clause (ii) holds for b = bδ,U. [Why? Every δ ∈ E is a strong limit cardinal and |δ| = |δ ∩U | = |δ ∩U \U |. i i+1 For each δ ∈ E let hUδ,ε : ε < |Pδ| ≤ 2|δ|i list Pδ and let bδ,ε := bδ,U . δ,ε Let Γ = {ϕ(b )if(γ∈Uδ,ε) :δ ∈ E and ε < |P |} x¯γ,δ,ε δ ∪{¬ϕ(x¯ ,b) : γ < λ,b ∈ M and for no γ α δ ∈ E,ε < |P | do we have b = b }. δ δ,ε As ϕ(x¯,y) has the strong independence property, clearly Γ is finitely satisfiable in M , but M is λ+-saturated, M ≺ M and |Γ| = λ hence we can find a¯ ∈ M for α α γ NO LIMIT MODEL IN INACCESSIBLE 9 γ < λ such that the assignment x¯ 7→ a¯ (γ < λ) satisfies Γ in M. Lastly, choose γ γ β ∈ (α,λ+) such that {a¯ : γ < λ} ⊆ M and let h be a one-to-one mapping from γ β M onto U extending f and let E∗ = {δ ∈ E : h(a¯ ) ∈ U ∩ δ iff γ < δ for β i+1 γ i+1 every γ < λ}. Now check.] ¯ Now we can choose f such that ⊛ (a) f¯= hf : α < λ+i 3 α (b) f is a one-to-one function from M onto λ α α ⊛ for every α < λ+ there is P¯ α = hPα : ε < λi such that 4 ε (ii) Pα ⊆ P(ε) are as in ⊡ (e) above ε 2 (ii) for every β ≤ α, for a club of δ < λ we have Pα ∈/ invϕ (δ,f (N )). δ 7,κ β β ϕ [Why? For every β ≤ α and δ ∈ (κ,λ) we have inv (δ,f (N )) is a subset of 7,κ β β P(P(δ)) of cardinality ≤ 2|δ|. As the number of β’s is ≤ λ by diagonalization we can do this: let α + 1 = [ uε and uε ∈ [α + 1]<λ increasing continuous for ε<λ ε < λ; moreover, |uε| ≤ ε. By induction on ε ∈ (κ,λ)∩S choose Pεα ⊆ [ Pα∗,ℓ ℓ<3 which includes ∪{Pα : ζ ∈ ε∩S}∪P∗,2 and satisfies P∗,0 ∩Pα ∈ P(P∗,0))\∪ ζ α α ε δ {invϕ (f (N ))∩P∗,0 : β ∈ u }.] δ,κ β β δ ε Now choose pairwise distinct bδ,U ∈ M0 for δ ∈ E,U ∈ Pδ∗,0 ⊛ for every α ≤ α < λ+ for some β ∈ (α,λ+) and a¯ ∈ ℓg(y¯)M for γ < λ 5 ∗ γ β the condition in clause (γ) of ⊙ holds with P¯ α1 here standing for P¯ there 2 and the bδ,U chosen above. [Why? By ⊛ .] 2 ⊛ let E = {δ < λ+ : δ is a limit ordinal such that for every α < δ there is 6 β < δ as in ⊛ }. 5 Clearly E is a club of λ+. ⊛ if δ < δ are from E ∩Sλ+ then M ,M are not isomorphic. 7 1 2 κ δ1 δ2 [Why? We consider P¯ δ1 which is from ⊛ . On the one hand {ε < λ : Pδ1 ∈/ 4 ε invϕ (ε,f,δ (M ))} contains a club by ⊛ (ii). 7,κ 2 δ2 4 On the other hand choose an increasing hα : i < κi with limit δ satisfying α = i 2 0 10 SAHARON SHELAH 0,α = δ such that (δ ,α ,α ) are like (α ,α,β) in ⊛ . Now by 1.7, {ε < 1 1 1 1+i 1+i+1 ∗ 5 λ : Pεδ1 ∈ invϕ7,κ(ε,f,δ2(Mδ2))} contains a club. Hence by the last sentence and the end of the previous paragraph M ≇ M as required.] δ δ 1 2 So we are done. (cid:3) 1.8 Proof of 1.9. Similar but easier (for λ regular not strong limit (but 2λ > 2<λ) also easy), or see the proof of 2.7. (cid:3) 1.7

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.