ebook img

Nine Papers on Logic and Group Theory PDF

262 Pages·1967·22.936 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Nine Papers on Logic and Group Theory

http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/trans2/064 AMERICAN MATHEMATICA L SOCIET Y TRANSLATIONS Series 2 Volume 6 4 NINE PAPERS ON LOGIC AND GROUP THEORY by S. D. Berman M . I. Graev G. S. Ceitin A . I. Kostrikin D. K. Faddeev M . A. Naimark I. M. Gel'fand V . A. Rohlin A. V. Gladkii R . T. Vol'vacev Published by the AMERICAN MATHEMATICA L SOCIET Y Providence, Rhode Island 1967 Copyright © 196 7 by the American Mathematical Society Library of Congress Catalog Number A51-5559 Printed in the United States of America All Rights Reserved No portion of this book may be reproduced without the written permission of the publisher TABLE O F CONTENT S Page Ceitin, G . S. Algorithmi c operator s i n constructiv e metri c spaces . [UewTiiH, T . C . AjiropM(J)MMqecKM e onepaTopb i B KOHCTpyKTMBHbix MerpwqeCKMX npoCTpaHCTBax. ] Trud y Mat. Inst. Steklov. 6 7 (1962), 295-361 1 Gladkii, A. V. O n the recognitio n o f replaceabilit y i n recursiv e lan - guages. [TjiaAKHM , A . B. 0 pacno3HaBaHM M 3aMemaeM0CT M B peKypCMBHblX H3blKax. ] Algebr a i Logika Sem. 2 (1963) No. 3, 5-22 8 1 Faddeev, D . K. O n the semigroup of genera in the theory of integer repre - sentations. [<f>aAaeeB , J\. K. 0 nojiyrpynn e POAO B B TeopwM IjejioqMCJieHHblX npeACTaBJieHMM. ] Izv . Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser . Mat. 28 (1964), 475-478 9 7 Naimark, M. A, Th e structure of unitary representations o f a locally com - pact group in a space Uy [HaMMapK , M . A. 0 CTpyKTyp e yHMTapHbi x npeACTaBJieHMM jioKajibH o 6wK0MnaKTHbi x rpynn B npocTpaHCTBe n .] i Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser . Mat. 29 (1965), 689-700 10 2 Gel fand, I . M. and Graev, M. I. Finite-dimensiona l irreducibl e representa - tions of the unitary and the full linea r groups, and related specia l func - tions. [ Tejib^aHA, M . M. M TpaeB, M . 14. KoHeqHOMepHbi e Henpw - BOAMMbie npeflCTaBJieHMfl yHMTapno w n nojmo w jMHeftHO M rpynnb i M CBH3aHHbie c HMM M cnerjna/ibHbi e (JjyHKijnM. ] IZV . Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser. Mat. 29(1965), 1329-135 6 11 6 Berman, S. D. Representation s o f finit e group s over an arbitrary fiel d an d over rings of integers. [BepMaH , C . fl. ripeflCTaBJieHM H KOHeMHbl X rpynn Ha # npon3BOJibHbi M nojie M w HaA KOJibijaMn ijejibi x qwceji. ] Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser . Mat. 30 (1966), 69-132 14 7 Vol vacev, R. T . Sylo w p-subgroup s o f th e genera l linea r group . [BojibBaqeB, P. T. p-noArpynn w Ck/ioB a nojmo H jinHeMHO M rpynnw. ] Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser . Mat. 27 (1963), 1031-1054 21 6 Page Rohlin, V. A. Metri c properties o f endomorphisms o f compact commuta - tive groups. [POXJIMH , B . A. MeTpnuecKH e CBOHCTB a 3HAOMOP4)M3MO B KOMnaKTHbix KOMMyTaTHBHbi x rpynn.] Izv . Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser . Mat. 28 (1964), 867-874 24 4 Kostrikin, A. I. O n the definition o f a group by generators and definin g relations. [KocTpwKMH , A. 14. K 33.j\3.nn\o rpynn o6pa3yioiuMM M M 0npeflejlHK)mwMM COOTHOllieHMHMM. ] I7v . Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser . Mat. 2 9 (1965), 1119-1122 25 3 IV http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/trans2/064/01 ALGORITHMIC OPERATORS IN CONSTRUCTIVE METRIC SPACES G. S. CEITIN CONTENTS Chapter I. Statemen t of the problem and formulation of the fundamental theore m 1 Chapter II. Additiona l information abou t the theory of algorithms 9 Chapter III. Proof of the fundamental theore m 2 6 Chapter IV. Operator s on general recursive function s 4 5 Chapter V. Constructiv e function s o f a real variable 5 7 Bibliography 7 9 CHAPTER I Statement of the problem and formulatio n of the fundamental theore m Many objects constructe d in constructive mathematic s ar e connected wit h algorithmically developed processes. Thu s with a recursively enumerable se t there is associated th e process o f generating its elements , wit h a partial recur - sive function th e process o f computing its value for different value s of its argu - ment (mor e precisely, th e process of generating equations of the form f{k, • ••,m)=ft, where / i s a symbol for the function an d k, • • •, m, n ar e natural numbers) , with a constructive rea l number the proces s of computing its successiv e approxi - mations. Th e same holds for constructive measurable sets , measurabl e functions , etc. introduced by N. A. Sanin [12> 14] , wit h which are associated processes fo r approximating them in a special way by sets o r functions respectively . Ever y such process i s characterize d b y some prescription, accordin g to which it i s carried out; thi s prescription, code d in the form of a word in some alphabet, i s considered t o be the transcription of that object with which the given process i s associated (i n some cases th e object itsel f i s suc h a transcription) . Two processes, define d generall y speaking b y different prescriptions , ca n give the same or, i n a certain sense, simila r results. I n these cases th e corre - sponding objects ar e usually considered t o be equal. Precisel y thi s property i s possessed b y the equality of partial recursive functions , constructiv e rea l num- bers, etc . In this sectio n we shall use an imprecise notion of algorithm . 1 2 G. S. CEITIN An operator on such objects is given in the form of some rule according t o which, starting from one algorithmically developed process (calle d the given proc- ess), w e construc t another such process (calle d the desired process). Moreover , we must satisfy th e requirement of correctness, namely that if the operator is ap- plicable t o some object, the n it is also applicable to every object equal to it, and for equal objects the operator gives equa l objects (operator s are not assume d to be everywhere defined). I n the definition of such operators two approaches occur. The first approach consists in giving a prescription which enables us t o carry out the desired process parallel to the given one, usin g the results of the given process. Th e prescription itself of the given process i s not used here for the performance of the desired process. On e can imagine that the desired proc- ess i s carrie d out by two people such that the prescription of the given proces s is know n to the first person, wh o carries out this process and communicates th e results t o the second person; th e latter, using these results, carries out the de- sired process, eve n though he does not know the prescription of the given proc- ess. Partia l recursiv e operators \} , §63 ] give n by a scheme computing the value of the desired function from values of the given one, hav e precisely thi s character. I n exactly the same way, th e definition of the sum of two construc- tive real numbers contains a rule for computing an approximation of the sum for approximating values of the summands, and the definition of the measure of a con- structive measurable set [12 , 14 ] contain s a rule for computing approximate val - ues of the measure for approximations of the set . If two given objects ar e assumed equal only when the results of correspond - ing processes coincide , the n the requirement of correctness i s fulfilled automat - ically here. I f for the equality of given objects onl y "similarity'' of results of corresponding processes suffices , the n to guarantee correctness it is necessar y to introduce some additional condition of a kind of continuity. Operator s of the kind described will be called Kleene operators. In the second approach an operator is give n by means of some algorith m which, fro m the prescription for the development of the given process, give s a prescription for the development of the desired process; th e correctness require - ment is in this case a n additional condition imposed on the algorithm. Th e con- structive function s introduce d by A. A. Markov [5] ar e operators of this kind. The concept of effective operatio n introduced in the paper [*6 ] o f Myhill and Shepherdson is also of the same type. W e shall call such operators Markov oper- ators. * The concept of constructive functio n use d in this paper is a variant of this concep t and is essentially equivalent to the concept employed by A. A. Markov in his later paper [7], ALGORITHMIC OPERATOR S 3 It is not difficult t o see that every Kleene operator can be represented in the form of a Markov operator. I n fact, i n order to obtain the prescription of the de- sired process fro m the prescription of the given process, i t suffices t o add to it the prescription of the operator (jus t as the addition of the scheme of a partial recursive operato r to the scheme of the given function gives a scheme of the de- sired function). Th e question arises a s to the truth of the converse, i . e. i s every Markov operator representable a s a Kleene operator ? In dealing with operators transforming a partial recursive function into a partial recursive function, th e role of Kleene operators is played by partial re- cursive operators, an d it is natural to present a Markov operator by some partial recursive function / giving , fo r a Godel number of the given function, a Godel number of the desired function, wher e the correctness conditio n has the followin g form: i f k an d I are Godel numbers of one and the same partial recursive func - tion and f(k) i s defined, the n f(l) i s defined and the function wit h Godel num- ber f(k) i s equal to the function with Godel number /(/) . Myhil l and Shepherd- son call such Markov operators effective operations . The y proved [*" ] tha t every effective operation coincides with some partial recursive operator. Thi s also follows fro m more general results of V. A. Uspenskii [9 , Theorem s 10 , 10 ]. Now we shall consider operators transforming a general recursive functio n into a partial recursive function. A s before, partia l recursive operators remai n in the role of Kleene operators; fo r Markov operators it is necessary to replace in the preceding formulation of the correctness conditio n the words "partia l re- cursive* ' by the words "genera l recursive", a s a result of which the conditio n becomes weaker. I n [16 ] th e question is posed as to the equivalence of suc h operators and partial recursive operators. I n the present paper it is prove d (Theorem 2, Chapte r IV, §l ) tha t every such Markov operator can be extended , in a certain sense, t o a partial recursive operator. I n particular, if an operator gives, fo r every general recursive function, anothe r general function, the n it co- incides with some partial recursive operator. Th e problem as to what the do- main of definition of such a Markov operator can be remains open. In dealing with operators transformin g a constructive real number into a con- structive real number, constructiv e function s play the role of Markov operators. To formulate here the concept of Kleene operator is more complicated, bu t it is clea r that, sinc e the approximate values of the function defined by a Kleene operator are computed from approximate values of the argument, suc h a function possesses certai n continuity properties. Doe s a n arbitrary constructive functio n possess suc h properties? A similar result has bee n obtained by Kreisel, Lacombe, and Shoenfield [15] . 4 G . S. CEITIN It has been established b y A. A. Markov [5], [7] tha t a constructive functio n cannot have constructive discontinuities , i . e. tha t there cannot be a constructiv e sequence o f real numbers X , X X • • • constructively convergin g to som e Q y v number x suc h tha t the value of the function i s defined fo r all elements o f thi s sequence an d for x, an d there exists a positive number y suc h that, fo r ever y n, th e value of the function fo r X differ s fro m th e value of the function fo r x b y R more than y. In the present paper this result is strengthene d an d the constructive continu - ity of every constructive functio n a t every constructive point is proved in th e "e-8 sense " (Theore m 3 , Chapter V, §l) . W e shall als o prove the uniform ap - proximability of constructive function s b y so-called pseudopolygonal function s (Theorem 4 , Chapter V, §2) . Apparently , th e concept of a function constructivel y uniformly approximabl e by pseudopolygonal function s als o corresponds t o the concept of a Kleene operator on constructive rea l numbers. Th e question as t o what the domain of definition o f a constructive functio n ca n be remains, a s i n the case o f operators on general recursive functions , open . In considering Markov operators on general recursive functions an d on con- structive rea l numbers a great resemblance manifest s itself . I t is natural t o see k some general concept, specia l case s o f which would be general recursive func - tions, an d constructive real numbers suc h that one could then prove some genera l theorem from which would follow the above-mentioned propositions abou t opera - tors on general recursive function s an d on constructive real numbers. N . A. Sanin suggested t o the author using for this purpose th e concept of constructive metri c space, whic h was outlined in his paper [ 12] (cf . als o [14]). I n §3 o f this chap - ter the definition o f this concep t will be given and the fundamental theore m wil l be formulated . Brief exposition s of the results of this paper were contained in [10] an d t11]. Except for small changes, th e present paper is a Candidate dissertation . The author expresses his great appreciation t o his thesi s directo r A. A.Markov, as well as t o N. A. Sanin and I. D. Zaslavskii fo r advice and remarks which wer e of great help in the writing of this paper . §2 We shall employ the apparatus of normal algorithms developed by A. A. Markov [6]. If 2 1 is an algorithm in some alphabet A , an d P i s a word which is not a word in A , the n we shall say that 2 1 is not applicable t o P, an d the expressio n 2I(P) wil l be considered meaningles s (cf . [ 6, Chapte r III, §1 . 5]). The designation 2Ip , wher e 2 1 is an algorithm and P i s a word, wil l some - ALGORITHMIC OPERATOR S 5 times replace the designation 2I(P) . We shall assum e that, fo r every alphabet in which the objects we shall con- sider are built up, w e have fixed some two-letter extension (calle d the standard extension) fo r the construction of algorithms over this alphabet . W e also assum e fixed a method of forming transcriptions of algorithms [6 , Chapte r IV, §3 - 3 J in this standar d extension, wit h the difference that , instea d of the letters a an d b used in [ 6L w e shall use the letters 0 an d | . By the transcription of the algorithm 2 1 with respect to the alphabet A we shall mean the word obtained in the following way : w e define th e translation op- eration [ 6 , Chapte r I, §6 ] fro m the alphabet in which the algorithm 2 1 is con - structed into the standard extension of the alphabet A , no t changing the letters of A , the n we construct the translation of the algorithm 2 1 [6, Chapte r III, §7. l], and, finally , w e construct the transcription of the resulting algorithm; i n order for this definition t o be single valued, i t is necessary t o fix an order among those letters in the alphabet of the scheme of 2 1 whic h do not belong to the alphabe t A. Thu s the transcription of the algorithm 2 1 with respect to A is the transcrip- tion of a certain algorithm in the standard extension of A whic h is equivalent to the algorithm 2 1 wit h respect to A . Th e transcription of 2 1 with respect to A will be denoted byc c 21, A I We shall use the following notation for certain fixed alphabets: T. Q = {0, |}, \ = {0, |, - }, ^ 2 = {0, | , - , / i and ^ = {0, | , -, /,. §1 Transcription s of al- gorithms are words in the alphabet ^Q . The letters D and * wil l be employed as separating signs. W e shall assume that these letters will not be used for the extension of alphabets in the construction of new algorithms. Below we shall introduce the concepts o f words of type H , typ e T, typ e P, and type $ . Th e symbols a^ , a^ . . . , wher e a i s one of the letters H , T P, y and /{ , wil l be used as variables whose admissible value s ar e words of type a . We shall also introduce variables H an d H« fo r words in the alphabet ^L . Th e letters i, j wil l play the role of "metamathematical " variables for natural num- bers. I n the formulation of statements containing variables, w e shall sometime s omit reference t o universal quantifiers, s o that if it is not clear from the tex t that the variable in the given formulation is boun d by some quantifier or that it occurs fre e (fo r example, afte r the words "le t us fix"), the n we shall assum e that the variable is bound here by a universal quantifie r whose scope extend s t o the whole formula . The definitions give n in this paper of words of the indicated type s (natural, integral, rational numbers, and duplexes) do not differ essentiall y fro m the corresponding defini - tions in N. A. Sanin's paper [14],

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.