ebook img

Naming Evil, Judging Evil PDF

247 Pages·2008·0.82 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Naming Evil, Judging Evil

Naming Evil, Judging Evil Naming Evil Judging Evil Edited byRuth W. Grant With a Foreword byAlasdair MacIntyre The Universityof Chicago Press I Chicago & London RUTHW. GRANTis professor of political science and philosophy at Duke University and a senior fellow at the Kenan Institute for Ethics. She is the author of John Locke’s Liberalism andHypocrisy and Integrity,both published by the University of Chicago Press. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London © 2006 by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published 2006 Printed in the United States of America 15 14 13 12 11 10 09 08 07 06 1 2 3 4 5 ISBN-13: 978-0-226-30673-5 (cloth) ISBN-10: 0-226-30673-9 (cloth) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Naming evil, judging evil / edited by Ruth W. Grant ; with a foreword by Alasdair MacIntyre. p. cm. Revisions of papers presented at a conference held Jan. 27–29, 2005 at Duke University. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-226-30673-9 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Good and evil—Congresses. 2. Judgment (Ethics)—Congresses. I. Grant, Ruth Weissbourd, 1951– BJ1401.N36 2006 170—dc22 2006010697 ∞ The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48–1992. Contents Foreword byAlasdairMacIntyre vii Preface xi Introduction 1 Part1: Speaking AboutEvil Chapter 1 Where Did Allthe EvilsGo? 15 Michael Allen Gillespie Chapter 2 Seeing Darkness, Hearing Silence: Augustine’sAccountofEvil 35 Stanley Hauerwas Chapter 3 The Rousseauan Revolution and the Problem ofEvil 53 Ruth W. Grant Chapter 4 Inequalityand the Problem ofEvil 75 Nannerl O. Keohane Part2: Making Judgments, Passing Judgment, Taking a Stand, Biting Your Tongue Chapter 5 The Butler Did It 103 J. Peter Euben Chapter 6 Eviland the MoralityofConviction 121 David Wong Chapter 7 Combining Clarityand Complexity: A Layered Approach to Cross-CulturalEthics 139 Elizabeth Kiss Chapter 8 LiberalDilemmasand MoralJudgment 175 Malachi Hacohen Chapter 9 Between Bigotryand Nihilism: MoralJudgmentin PluralistDemocracies 191 Thomas A. Spragens, Jr. Bibliography 219 Name Index 231 v Foreword There are these days all too many not quite good enough academic con- ferences and all too many not quite good enough books manufactured from papers delivered at such conferences. What a pleasure then to be asked to write a foreword to a book of papers from a conference that, unlike most, I wish that I had attended, a book that poses questions as interesting as any that there are! Yet, although I am delighted, I am not surprised. For the papers in this volume are by a group of colleagues at Duke University who have sustained an admirable tradition of collegial friendship among those in Duke’s various departments and schools— Political Science, History, Philosophy, the Divinity School—who engage with central issues of political philosophy. They represent a range of viewpoints, and they have different projects and concerns. But over time their work has been informed by their shared reading, by extended inter- disciplinary conversations and arguments, and by learning from each other’s work. I was privileged to be part of this for a number of years. This particular conference was the outcome of a set of discussions that had gone on for over two years, and the final versions of the participants’ papers, now published in this volume, benefited significantly from com- ments presented at the conference by scholars from outside Duke. This has been a collective enterprise in a way that has too few parallels, at least in the humanities. It was and is of course important that conver- sation and enquiry about the subject matter that the participants addressed, which is inexhaustible, first opened up, at least according to the author of Genesis, in words exchanged by God, Adam, Eve, and the serpent, and is still carried on in our own day by Hannah Arendt and her numerous successors. So it would be ludicrous to expect anything like a conclusive treatment of the issues raised, either by our various and often incompatible understandings of the nature of evil or by our con- frontations with evil in our own lives. Yet why speak of evil at all? Why is it not enough to speak of good and bad rather than good and evil? The contributors to this volume suggest several possible answers. Let me add to their suggestions one more but begin with a warning of dangers to be avoided. One such arises from the current climate of political incivility in the United States, which permits both liberal and conservative agitators vii viii Alasdair MacIntyre to employ types of rhetoric that debase the linguistic currency and make it easy to use the word “evil” lightly, promiscuously, and irresponsibly. This kind of corruption of speech is itself a great evil. A second danger derives from what Wittgenstein called an unbalanced diet of examples. By allowing one or two examples to engross not only the mind but also the imagination, we may give to striking features of those particular examples a significance that may obscure the character of evil. It is impossible now to think about evil without thinking about the Holocaust. And part of the horror that thought of the Holocaust elicits is the sheer number of murders. But what made the Holocaust a very great evil was not the number of deaths. With evil, quantity is not the issue. And so it is not the issue either over massacres in Bosnia or in Rwanda. A third very different type of danger arises from putting too great an emphasis upon choice, so that evil is taken to consist in the making of bad choices. But evil can arise from inaction as much as from action, from failures to will as much as from willing. Some evils result from our not having learned what it was our responsibility to learn and from con- sequent failures to recognize where and when we may have a duty to intervene. A failure by myself or by others to enquire, a lack of any impulse to enquire, about the oppression and exploitation that is occur- ring close at hand, but in disguised forms—a failure rooted in our desire to go on leading comfortable and undisturbed lives—can be quite as much an evil as oppression and exploitation are. Yet these warnings, just because they draw our attention to a variety of evils, may themselves point us in the wrong direction, by tempting us to conclude—prematurely—that there is after all no such thing as evil, but only evils, and that evils have no one thing in common but resemble each other in an indefinite variety of ways. After all, we may ask, what do the corruption of language, the massacres of innocent people, and the negligent failure to unmask and confront oppression and exploitation have in common? And, looking for an answer, we may follow Susan Neiman’s lead and began to think of these examples as members of a very much larger class. Stanley Hauerwas quotes Neiman’s remark that “noth- ing is easier than stating the problem of evil in nontheist terms” (Evil in Modern Thought [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002], p. 5). She goes on: “Every time we make the judgment this ought not to have happened we are stepping onto a path that leads straight to the problem of evil . . . For what most demands explanation is not how moral judgments are justified, but why those that are so clearly justified were disregarded in the past.” But this is to confuse the problem of evil with the problem of evils and both with the problem of bads—if I may use a rare, but badly Foreword ix needed word—and they are, so I am going to suggest, not at all the same. The problem of evil is a much narrower and more particular problem. For evil, as Ruth Grant points out, is one particular kind of badness, yet it differs strikingly from most other kinds. A starting point for enquir- ing what it is might be by considering further questions that Grant and Nannerl Keohane open up in their essays. Both examine claims advanced by Rousseau, who connects the origin of evil with on the one hand inequality, on the other amour-propre. So Keohane in her paper focuses on aspects and types of inequality that are a source of evil. Yet we have to remember—pace Rousseau—that not all inequality is bad, let alone evil. All government, including the best of governments, necessarily involves inequality in respect of authority and power. All military organizations, including the best of armies fighting in the best of causes, requires such in- equality. The inequalities that corrupt are of a different kind: inequalities of respect that result in inadequate recognition for someone’s qualities as a human being, inequalities that violate the norms of justice in respect of need and desert, inequalities that are arbitrary and imposed for no good end. Such types of inequality bring us to the threshold of evil, because they are apt to involve just that thought that informs the intentions of an evil will: “I / weare going to impose my / ourwill. This may be a matter of my / our visiting affliction upon you—whether there is one of you or six million of you—to achieve what it pleases me / usto achieve, no matter what the cost in pain, humiliation, and death to you, no matter what norms and values may be violated, and for no sufficient reason except that it is my / ourwill to do so. Or it may be a matter of my / ourwill and pleasure in securing a tranquil and pleasant existence for me / us, no matter what evils are being visited upon others. But, either way, let my / ourwill be done, just because it is mine, just because it is ours.” This is the voice of pride. It is a voice that we may fail to recognize because its utterances can be and often are high- minded and moralistic. So it may on occasion speak in the vocabulary of a relentless benevolence, telling those upon whom it visits affliction that it is only doing this for the sake of their own good but omitting to add that what makes the achievement of that good its motivation is just that it is its own will and pleasure to do so, irrespective of what those others may need or desire. It was of course one of Nietzsche’s insights that morality can be the mask worn by this kind of pride. And Nietzsche had been anticipated in this by Augustine. Have we by identifying the part that pride so understood plays in human life also understood the nature of evil? Have we arrived at a uni- tary core conception of evil? If I am tempted to say “Yes,” as I am, then the

Description:
Naming Evil. Judging Evil. Edited by Ruth W. Grant. With a Foreword by Alasdair MacIntyre. The University of Chicago Press I Chicago & London
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.