ebook img

Measurement, Realism and Objectivity: Essays on Measurement in the Social and Physical Sciences PDF

357 Pages·1987·6.507 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Measurement, Realism and Objectivity: Essays on Measurement in the Social and Physical Sciences

MEASUREMENT, REALISM AND OBJECTIVITY AUSTRALASIAN STUDIES IN HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE General Editor: R. W. HOME University of Melbourne Editorial Advisory Board W. R. ALBURY, University of New South Wales B. D. ELLIS, La Trobe University L. A. FARRALL, Deakin University F. R. JEVONS, Deakin University R. JOHNSTON, UniversityofWollongong H. E. LE GRAND, University of Melbourne A. MUSGRAVE, University of Otago D. R. OLDROYD, University of New South Wales J. RONAYNE, University of New South Wales J. J. C. SMART,AustralianNational University VOLUME 5 MEASUREMENT, REALISM AND OBJECTIVITY Essays on Measurement in the Social and Physical Sciences Edited by JOHN FORGE School of Science, Griffith University, Queensland, Australia D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP DORDRECHT/BOSTON/LANCASTER/TOKYO Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Measurement, realism, and objectivity. (Australasian studies in history and philosophy of science ; v. 5) Includes bibliographies and indexes. 1. Physical measurements. 2. Science-Philosophy. 3. Science-history. 4. Realism. 5. Objectivity. I. Forge, lohn, 1946-- . II. Series. QC39.M396 1987 530.1'6 87-26301 ISBN-13: 978-94-010-8238-9 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-3919-6 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-3919-6 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.o. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland All Rights Reserved © 1987 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 15t edition 1987 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner TABLE OF CONTENTS FOREWORD vH INTRODUCTION ix ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xvH JAMES R. FLYNN I The Ontology ofIntelligence 1 HENRY KRIPS I Quantum Measurement and Bell's Theorem 41 S. O. FUNTOWICZ AND J. R. RAVETZ I Qualified Quantities: Towards an Arithmetic of Real Experience 59 DA VID R. OLDROYD I Punctuated Equilibrium Theory and Time: A Case Study in Problems of Coherence in the Mea surement of Geological Time (The 'KBS' Tuff Controversy and the Dating of Rocks in the Turkana Basin, East Kenya) 89 JOHN NORTON I Einstein, the Hole Argument and the Reality of Space 153 IAN LOWE I Measurement and Objectivity: Some Problems of Energy Technology 189 ROBERT McLAUGHLIN I Freudian Forces 207 CHRIS SWOYER I The Metaphysics of Measurement 235 JOHN FORGE IOn Ellis' Theory of Quantities 291 D. M. ARMSTRONG I Comments on Swoyer and Forge 311 BRIAN ELLIS I Comments on Forge and Swoyer 319 INDEX OF NAMES 327 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 333 FOREWORD The institutionalization of History and Philosophy of Science as a distinct field of scholarly endeavour began comparatively early - though not always under that name - in the Australasian region. An initial lecturing appointment was made at the University of Melbourne immediately after the Second World War, in 1946, and other appoint ments followed as the subject underwent an expansion during the 1950s and 1960s similar to that which took place in other parts of the world. Today there are major Departments at the University of Melbourne, the University of New South Wales and the University of Wollongong, and smaller groups active in many other parts of Australia and in New Zealand. "Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science" aims to provide a distinctive publication outlet for Australian and New Zealand scholars working in the general area of history, philosophy and social studies of science. Each volume comprises a group of essays on a connected theme, edited by an Australian or a New Zealander with special expertise in that particular area. Papers address general issues, however, rather than local ones; parochial topics are avoided. Further more, though in each volume a majority of the contributors is from Australia or New Zealand, contributions from elsewhere are by no means ruled out. Quite the reverse, in fact - they are actively encour aged wherever appropriate to the balance of the volume in question. R. W. HOME General Editor Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy ofS cience vii INTRODUCTION The essays in this volume are concerned more or less directly with the theory and practice of measurement. As a theme or organising principle for the collection, I suggested to contributors that they might explore some of the implications of the theory and practice of measurement for the realist interpretation of science and for the claim that scientific knowledge is objective, or, conversely, to consider some of the ways the realist interpretation and the claim that scientific knowledge is objective might influence our ideas about measurement. In other words one could say that the volume focusses on the area of intersection of the topic of measurement and the topics of realism and objectivity. My aim has been not so much to achieve a consensus on a narrow range of issues but to produce a collection of papers which reflect the interests and concerns of the Australasian community of History and Philosophy of Science. While this aim is not necessarily incompatible with that of achieving consensus, it would, in view of the richness and diversity of the activities of those who belong to the Australasian H.P.S. com munity, be somewhat surprising if complete agreement were reached. The unity of the present volume is thus supplied more by its overall theme rather than by its substantive conclusions. In the remainder of this introduction I shall say something about each paper, not necessarily taking them in the order which they appear in the volume, and indicate some of the points of agreement between them. Jim Flynn's "The Ontology of Intelligence" is the first of two papers about psychology, and it deals specifically with intelligence testing in relation to the construct g, or general intelligence, of the Spearman Jensen theory. On the first page of his paper, Flynn asserts that the con cept of intelligence only has explanatory power if it can be measured, and hence the question is raised as to whether IQ tests do actually measure intelligence. This leads him to a careful and detailed discussion of what it is to measure intelligence, and then to consider the conditions under which the measurable quantity or construct g can be interpreted realistically. Flynn sets out four conditions, or assertions as he calls them, under which we would be justified in taking g to be real. These ix x INTRODUCTION conditions are quite stringent. Not only must g have a physiological subs~ratum, it must play a causal role in the world, which, for Flynn, amounts to its explanatory significance. The conditions for the realist construal of g are stated at roughly the half-way point of the essay. The remainder is taken up with an assessment of the Spearman Jensen theory in the light of these conditions. Flynn concludes that the theory, though not without its strengths, requires modification in several respects. The second of the two papers on psychology is Robert McLaughlin's "Freudian Forces". McLaughlin, unlike Flynn, is not concerned with any current theory of psychology, but rather with the historical question of the tenor of Freud's metapsychology. In particular, he is interested in the status of certain hypotheses in which Freud expresses himself in terms of ''force'', "energy", "resistance" and other such mechanical concepts. In considering how we should interpret such expressions, McLaughlin distinguishes between several different varieties of realism, and identifies realism in contrast to instrumentalism as the variety at issue. The question, then, is whether 'Freudian forces' are to be taken as instruments of prediction, after the manner of the typical nineteenth century interpretations of force in physics, or as real entities. One might suppose that if it were possible to assign values to these entities by well defined procedures of measurement, then this would be enough for a realist interpretation. McLaughlin denies this, and demonstrates that values can be assigned to so-called intervening variables which by definition are instruments of prediction. As with Flynn, it is the causal explanatory role played by an entity or construct which is said to be the basis of any realist construal. McLaughlin goes further than Flynn in this regard and spells out what it is for something to have a causal explanatory role by making use of Salmon's account of the causal structure of the world. The essays of Henry Krips and John Norton are concerned with some of the implications for measurement of, respectively, quantum mechanics and general relativity. Both papers contain some techni calities, but in neither case are the conclusions inaccessible to those unfamiliar with the mathematical apparatus employed. The upshot of Krips' paper "Quantum Measurement and Bell's Theorem" is that we must give up the principle that for any physical system S, quantity Q and time t, there always exists a value mv( Q, S, t) which S would exhibit for Q if only a measurement were performed on INTRODUCTION xi S at t. In other words, we must renounce the idea that physical systems exhibit quantities to some definite degree at all times. Krips states that this assumption has been taken as an underlying principle of classical physics. Why must it be given up? In the first section of his paper, Krips proves that the principle is incompatible with standard quantum mechanics in conjunction with the locality postulate which states that there are no faster than light causal influences. This reasoning is typical of discussions that involve Bell's theorem. The conclusion of such a discussion is typically that we are presented with a dilemma or. tri lemma: either standard quantum mechanics must be renounced or locality or . . . . Most philosophers of science, Krips included, do not consider giving up quantum mechanics or locality. Hence in this case it is the above-mentioned principle that must be relinquished. Krips does not think that this is a great loss since it only amounts to abandoning determinism. The classical metaphysician may not agree. Those readers familiar with operationism, the doctrine that quan tities are nothing more than sets of measuring operations, may be aware that certain remarks made by Einstein in his 1905 paper on special relativity were in part responsible for this doctrine. Bridgman, who defended this view of quantities in his Logic of Modern Physics, believed that Einstein's paper exemplified operationism. Norton in "Einstein, the Hole Argument and the Reality of Space" is concerned, not with the special theory of relativity, but with the general theory. In the development of this theory also, Einstein's pronouncements have some significance for our ideas about measurement. Norton quotes passages from Einstein in which he speaks of the requirements of his theory as robbing space and time of 'objective reality' and of the reference system (c o-ordinate system) as signifying 'nothing real'. If so, what are we measuring when we make measurements of lengths with measuring rods and time intervals with clocks, and what do co-ordinate systems refer to? Subjective impressions, phenomenal objects or what? Norton, however, wants to argue against the view that Einstein was in fact working out the implications for space and time of the non realist position of philosophers like Mach and Schlick. By a careful study of Einstein's rendering of two crucial arguments, the point-co incidence argument and the hole argument, Norton concludes that Einstein denied the substantivalist account of space and time, not the realist account. The substantivalist believes that space and time exist independently of any fields, such as the gravitational field. Norton xii INTRODUCTION conjectures that perhaps Einstein was an antisubstantivalist all along, and that his apparently anti-realist remarks of 1913-1916 should be construed as denying the existence of space and time independently of the fields they contain. Whatever Einstein's intentions, his arguments as reconstructed by Norton are telling only against the substantivalist. Measurement, then, is not to be conceived as reporting anything about spatial properties of objects nor the duration of events that are not determined to some extent by the nature of the fields pervading space and time. The passage from Einstein quoted in section 6 of Norton's paper makes this explicit: space has no metrical properties without the gravitational field. With regard to our understanding of Einstein, it would seem that the situation here resembles that to which I referred in connection with operationism: we should look carefully at what Einstein did, not at what he said - which is in fact his own advice to his readers! There are three papers in the present volume that deal explicitly with questions about the objectivity of statements about measured values. Ian Lowe in "Measurement and Objectivity: Some Problems in Energy Technology" takes the most radical line on the issues. He presents a number of real-life examples in which quite outrageous claims are made on the basis of supposedly objective measurements, such as those concerning the safety of certain methods of disposing of nuclear waste. Lowe rejects the suggestion that we distinguish his examples as belong ing to the sphere which Weinberg calls trans-science and hence deny that they are representative of actual scientific practice. He proposes that the lack of objectivity of measurements evident in his examples drawn from the policy sciences infects the natural sciences also. But this is not, I think, a conclusion that would be accepted without qualifica tion by Silvio Funtowicz and Jerry Ravetz, nor would it be accepted by David Oldroyd. "Qualified Quantities: Towards an Arithmetic of Real Experience" is co-authored by Funtowicz and Ravetz. Ravetz and Funtowicz agree with Lowe in questioning the objectivity of statements that attribute values to quantities, particularly in the context of the policy sciences. They propose a schema which they refer to by the acronym NUSAP, which stands for number, unit, spread, assessment and pedigree, in terms of which to express quantitative information. However, I take it that conformity with the dictates of the schema would produce objec tive knowledge. Turning to the detail of the schema, the ideas of

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.