MADNESS CRACKED m i c k p o w e r M A D N E S S C R A C K E D 1 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, ox2 6dp, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Oxford University Press 2015 The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2015 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2014947152 ISBN 978–0–19–870387–7 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Oxford University Press makes no representation, express or implied, that the drug dosages in this book are correct. Readers must therefore always check the product information and clinical procedures with the most up-to-date published product information and data sheets provided by the manufacturers and the most recent codes of conduct and safety regulations. The authors and the publishers do not accept responsibility or legal liability for any errors in the text or for the misuse or misapplication of material in this work. Except where otherwise stated, drug dosages and recommendations are for the non-pregnant adult who is not breast-feeding Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials contained in any third party website referenced in this work. For Charlie –with lifelong thanks PREFACE Almost anything that has been said about madness, and almost any approach to what madness is, has some grain of truth in it, and every proposal that comes down on one side is guaranteed to be vehemently disagreed with by opponents from several other sides. Let us therefore consider in shorthand what some of these dis- putes are by beginning with the following two examples: John believes that he is mad, but he isn’t. Tom believes that he is not mad, but he is. These sentences summarize some of the conundrums that face any discussion or review of how we approach the question of madness. If we take a purely subjec- tive approach to madness, John would be mad because he believes himself to be so, whereas by the same subjective logic Tom would not be mad because he does not believe himself to be so. Many practitioners working in clinical psychology might well endorse this subjective approach. For example, a client who suffers from panic attacks and believes that he is mad might well be offered a cognitive therapy intervention including challenging his beliefs about madness. Equally, a clinical psychologist working with Tom, who is hearing voices but who doesn’t believe himself to be mad, might well be happy with Tom’s belief and make no attempt to challenge it, while providing better coping mechanisms for managing his voices. In other words, the subjective approach to madness is alive and well and helps clients on a daily basis. The objective approach is even more dominant and forms part of the medical model approach to madness. In this approach, John’s belief that he is mad would be dismissed if on a clinical diagnostic interview none or insufficient numbers of specific symptoms were deemed to be present to warrant a diagnostic label. At least some psychiatrists would be tempted to dismiss John’s belief in his “madness” as simply that of the “worried well.” Equally, Tom’s belief that despite hearing voices he isn’t mad would be likely to be deemed a “lack of insight” and therefore one of the present- ing symptoms for the objective conclusion that he exceeded the threshold on a range of symptoms in a clinical diagnostic interview. vii preface Before anyone thinks that the problem of madness is merely that of a resolution of subjective versus objective standpoints, French philosophy, especially the provoca- tive work of Michel Foucault, has presented an alternative middle way that cocks a snook at our simplified subjective versus objective descriptors. Again, let us take two examples in an attempt to highlight what the issues are: Carol believes that she is mad, society believes that she is mad, but she isn’t. Jane believes that she is not mad, society believes that she is mad, but she isn’t. There are of course further possible combinations that can be added to these two examples, but the core of what they attempt to capture is the social constructionist possibility that madness is a societal construct that overrides the individual’s beliefs, no matter what those beliefs are. Constructionists such as Mary Boyle (2013) would argue that the subjective approach of the clinical psychologist already outlined is wrong because it is individualistic and ignores the role of social construction, and that the objective medical model of psychiatry is pseudoscientific and reductionist because it reduces social–psychological phenomena to biological mechanisms. Stig- matization of different groups has occurred throughout history, and the “mad” rep- resent a socially constructed stigmatized group that has been targeted in our recent industrial and post-industrial ages. However, social constructionists such as Mary Boyle miss the possibility that construction also occurs at an individual intrapsychic level because they reject the individual psychological level of explanation. Individual cognitive constructive processes (e.g., Neisser, 1976) must be considered alongside social constructive processes to cover at least the following category of possible models: Sergei believes that he is mad, but society believes that he is not mad. In this example, Sergei has a personal construction that he is mad, whereas society does not believe him to be mad. Any constructionist approach to madness therefore needs to allow for inconsistent and contradictory constructions between the psycho- logical and social levels, in addition to contradictory constructions within each level that, for example, would allow for state-dependent models of the form: On Mondays Victor believes he is mad, but for the rest of the week he believes that he is not mad. While anxious, Jeremy believes he is mad, but not when he is feeling happy. The general situation represented by the subjective, the objective, and the con- structionist approaches may seem as irresolvable as the conflicts between the three great monotheisms of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. And just as pointing to the viii preface Bible as the shared book of the three monotheisms is likely to annoy all and satisfy none, perhaps there is a meta-level at which the subjective, objective, and construc- tionist viewpoints all say something important about madness: What if John’s subjective belief that he is mad is important? What if Tom’s belief that he isn’t mad is mistaken, that it is a false belief? And what if society does construct stigmatized groups, of which madness is a cur- rent historical example? That is, what if the concept of madness has to be understood as the interplay between all of these possible approaches, because no one approach is absolutely right, but equally no one approach is absolutely wrong. Each approach describes a different part of the mad elephant in the dark room, as it were. Now tough-minded proponents of each of these three approaches will lay into such a proposal as morally and philosophically bankrupt, inconsistent, and contra- dictory. However, what the approach actually attempts is an integration across sev- eral levels of explanation, including the biological, the psychological, and the social, which proposes that understanding at one level cannot and should not be reduced to understanding at a lower level; nevertheless, effects permeate across the levels, though not in simple one-to-one mapping rules. Madness therefore is a construc- tion, by the individual, by society, or by both, of a set of biopsychosocial presenting problems, but these constructions cannot simply be reduced to a set of biological signs and symptoms, in contrast to the standard medical model for physical illnesses which can be understood at a purely biomedical level. At best, the solution might be to use a “majority report” in which at least two of the systems agree on “madness” even if the third does not, as we will argue later in the book. Let us return to Tom, who is hearing voices. A clinical diagnostic interview admin- istered by a psychiatrist deems Tom to be suffering from schizophrenia with a lack of insight into his disorder. He is therefore prescribed medication against his will and put under section for further observation because he represents a potential danger to society. Cases such as Tom’s highlight the conflict between the objective (medical model) and constructionist approaches. The stigmatization of Tom as dangerous and lacking insight leads to a social construction, which may be as inappropriate in its application to Tom as it is to the average person on the Clapham Omnibus. Social control of “madness” quite rightly becomes the focus of the conflict in such cases. OK. Let’s imagine that the Wizard of Oz has just waved his wand and we have turned into a perfectly tolerant and perfectly supportive society. There are no stigmatized groups and everyone is given the best possible care when they suffer or experience ix