ebook img

How Should One Live?: Essays on the Virtues PDF

270 Pages·1998·2.54 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview How Should One Live?: Essays on the Virtues

Crisp, Roger (Editor), Fellow and Tutor in Philosophy, St Anne's College, Oxford How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues Publication date 1998 (this edition) Print ISBN-13: 978-0-19-875234-9 doi:10.1093/0198752342.001.0001 Abstract: Contains 14 specially commissioned papers on aspects of virtue ethics, and a substantial introduction that also serves as an introduction to virtue ethics. Topics covered include the practical application of the theory, ancient views, partiality, Kant, utilitarianism, human nature, natural and artificial virtues, virtues and the good, vices, emotions, politics, feminism and moral education, and community. Keywords: ancient ethics, community, emotions, feminism, human nature, Kantian ethics, moral education, moral theory, partiality, utilitarianism, virtue, virtue ethics, well- being Table of Contents 1. Modern Moral Philosophy and the Virtues Introduces a collection of specially commissioned articles on central topics in virtue ethics. Also provides an introduction to virtue ethics. The following topics are discussed: the ancient roots of virtue ethics; the nature of virtue ethics; the good of the virtuous agent; the demandingness of morality; universality tradition, and practice; community and gender; practical reason, moral knowledge, and moral education. 2. Normative Virtue Ethics Shows that virtue ethics can specify right action and defends the view that the sort of practical guidance it provides accommodates several conditions of adequacy that any normative ethics should meet. It is argued that (1) it generates an account of moral education, (2) it incorporates the view that moral wisdom cannot simply be acquired from textbooks, and (3) it can resolve resolvable dilemmas or moral conflicts but is not committed in advance to there being no such things as irresolvable dilemmas. 3. The Virtues: Theory and Common Sense in Greek Philosophy Begins by setting out several common-sense claims about the virtues—e.g. that they are separable or not good for the agent. Then proceeds to show how the main tendency of Greek ethics was to reject many of them. Focuses primarily on Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics. 4. Partiality and the Virtues Argues that the ethical excellences unfolded in the classical Aristotelian conception of the virtuous life presupposes a pre-existing network of partialistic preferences, and that its resulting rootedness in the real world gives virtue theory a decisive edge over its more abstract competitors. The ‘autocentric’ perspective of virtue ethics need not, however, imply a complacent and unfeeling social conservatism. Finally, charts the shift between such autocentric conceptions of ethics and more universalist accounts of morality, with special reference to Cartesian ethics, where we find an uneasy blend of traditional ‘aretic’ and proto-Kantian elements. 5. Kant's Virtues Kant's ethics is often but wrongly criticized for neglecting the virtues or offering a poor account of them. He in fact offers a rich and careful account, and a plausible reading of his theory of action shows that it is neither too inward nor too individualistic. In particular, maxims of virtue are ‘not objects of introspection’ (Kant denies that we have adequate self-knowledge) and ‘not constructed by ascription’ (their relation to action is too indeterminate). Rather, Kant sees maxims of virtue as ‘prescriptions’, which can be used to guide virtuous action, but may provide no way of showing whether virtue has been achieved. 6. Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Symmetry Unlike Kantian and common-sense morality, both utilitarianism and our common-sense thinking about the virtues place ultimate normative weight on benefiting both oneself and others. But for utilitarianism the self counts equally with each and every other person, whereas in our thought about how it is admirable to behave the interests of the self are roughly balanced against those of others ‘as a class’. This then yields, from the standpoint of common-sense virtue ethics, a distinctive general injunction to act from balanced concern for self and others (considered as a class). Understood in this way, virtue ethics is a distinctive approach to the question ‘how should one live’? 7. The Virtues and Human Nature The concept of human nature has entered into virtue theory at two levels. The first is psychological: what are human beings like? This paper argues that it is a mistake to define virtue in terms of particular types of intentional psychological states. The second level concerns human flourishing. Here, the paper argues that one can develop a theory of virtue independently of the notion of flourishing. 8. Natural and Artificial Virtues Hume's distinction of natural virtues and artificial virtues grows out of his explanatory scheme. But the distinction seems well founded and shows a puzzle in Aristotle's account of the virtues. Hume's account of the artificial virtues is in outline convincing and has the effect of qualifying his title to be a straightforward ‘virtue theorist’. 9. Does Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent? Theories of individual well-being fall into three main categories: hedonism, the desire- fulfilment theory, and the list theory (which maintains that there are some things that can benefit a person without increasing the person's pleasure or desire-fulfilment). The paper briefly explains the answers that hedonism and the desire-fulfilment theory give to the question of whether being virtuous constitutes a benefit to the agent. Most of the paper is about the list theory's answer. 10. Deadly Vices? The overall thesis is that there is a set of vices (the so-called deadly sins) that are corruptive of the self and the possession of which thus prevents an agent from leading a flourishing life. While it does not follow that therefore the virtues are needed for flourishing, it offers some support for this claim of traditional virtue theory by arguing that absence of such vices is at any rate a necessary condition for leading a good life. The nature of the harm done to the self is illustrated by a detailed discussion of the vice of sloth. 11. How Emotions Reveal Value and Help Cure the Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories Many modern ethical theories are schizophrenic, allowing a split between value and motivation. These theories do not make room for goods in which motivation and value must come together, such as love and friendship. This paper argues that, since the emotions do not allow for this schizophrenia, their place within virtue ethics allows that tradition to provide an important corrective to schizophrenic theory. 12. MacIntyre on Modernity and How It Has Marginalized the Virtues Political philosophers have again become concerned with the role of the virtues in justifying social, political, and economic arrangements, and have explored the issue of which institutions can provide space for the virtues to flourish. In After Virtue, MacIntyre launched an attack on liberalism, arguing that the institutions it defends undermine the virtues. This paper examines MacIntyre's account and the responses it has provoked. It argues that MacIntyre makes an important criticism of liberalism that liberals have not yet fully answered, but which also creates problems for his own account. 13. Feminism, Moral Development, and the Virtues Focuses on the virtue ethics of Aristotle and of MacIntyre, and suggests three problems within virtue ethics for a feminist. Firstly, accounts of the virtues in themselves may not meet an expectation of equal concern and respect. Secondly, it may be assumed that women are incapable of truly ‘human’ virtue. Finally, there are problems with the claim that there is in virtue ethics something especially feminine. 14. Community and Virtue Distinguishes several different kinds of connection between community and virtue— sustaining, content providing, agency constituting, worth defining, and others—using as a reference point MacIntyre's Is Patriotism a Virtue?A detailed exploration of the example of Le Chambon, a French Protestant village that sheltered many Jews during the Nazi occupation, illustrates these connections. The concept of ‘supererogation’ masks how communities can sustain virtue in its members. Bibliography Index How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues CLARENDON PRESS · OXFORD 1996 end p.iii Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi São Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © the several contributors and in this volume Oxford University Press 1996 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographcs rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data How should one live? : essays on the virtues / edited by Roger Crisp. Includes bibliographical references. 1. Virtue 2. Ethics. I. Crisp, Roger, 1961–. BJ1521.H83 1996 179′.9—dc20 95–25349 ISBN 0–19–824058–9 end p.iv Contents N otes on Contributors vii 1. M odern Moral Philosophy and the Virtues Roger Crisp 1 2. N ormative Virtue Ethics Rosalind Hursthouse 19 3. T he Virtues: Theory and Common Sense in Greek Philosophy T. H. Irwin 37 4. P artiality and the Virtues John Cottingham 57 5. K ant's Virtues Onora O'Neill 77 6. V irtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Symmetry Michael Slote 99 7. T he Virtues and Human Nature Julia Driver 111 8. N atural and Artificial Virtues: A Vindication of Hume's Scheme David Wiggins 131 9. D oes Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent? Brad Hooker 141 10.D eadly Vices? G abriele Taylor 157 N otes on Contributors vii 11.H ow Emotions Reveal Value and Help Cure the Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical T heories Michael Stocker 173 12.M acIntyre on Modernity and How It Has Marginalized the Virtues A ndrew Mason 191 13.F eminism, Moral Development, and the Virtues S usan Moller Okin 211 end p.v 14. C ommunity and Virtue Lawrence Blum 231 F urther Reading 251 I ndex 255 end p.vi Notes on Contributors Lawrence Blum is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts at Boston. He is the author of Friendship, Altruism, and Morality, A Truer Liberty: Simone Weil and Marxism, and Moral Perception and Particularity. John Cottingham is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Reading and editor of the journal Ratio. He is author of Rationalism, Descartes, The Rationalists, and A Descartes Dictionary. He is a co-translator of The Philosophical Writings of Descartes and the editor of The Cambridge Companion to Descartes. Roger Crisp is Fellow and Tutor in Philosophy at St Anne's College, Oxford. He is an associate editor of Utilitas and a member of the Analysis Committee. He is currently working on a book on J. S. Mill's Utilitarianism. Julia Driver is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Brooklyn College and the Graduate Center of the City University of New York. She is currently working on a book titled Uneasy Virtue, which presents a consequentialist account of the virtues. Brad Hooker teaches in the Philosophy Department at the University of Reading. He is an associate editor of Ratio and Utilitas, and is currently writing a book on rule- consequentialism. Rosalind Hursthouse is Head of the Philosophy Department at the Open University. She is the author of Beginning Lives and recently wrote ‘Applying Virtue Ethics’ for Virtues and Reasons, a book edited by her, Gavin Lawrence, and Warren Quinn. Terence Irwin is Susan Linn Sage Professor of Philosophy, Cornell University. He is the author of Aristotle's First Principles, Classical Thought, and Plato's Ethics, and has translated and edited Plato's Gorgias and Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. Andrew Mason is Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Reading. He is the author of Explaining Political Disagreement, and is currently working on a book on the notion of community. end p.vii Susan Moller Okin is Professor of Political Science at Stanford University. She is author of Women in Western Political Thought and Justice, Gender, and the Family. Onora O'Neill is Principal of Newnham College, Cambridge. She writes mainly on ethics, political philosophy, and in particular conceptions of practical reason. She is the author of Faces of Hunger: An Essay on Poverty, Development and Justice, and Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Michael Slote is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Maryland. He is the author of From Morality to Virtue, and is currently collaborating with Marcia Baron and Philip Pettit on a book debating the merits of Kantian ethics, consequentialism, and virtue ethics. Michael Stocker is Guttag Professor of Ethics and Political Philosophy at Syracuse University. He is the author of Plural and Conflicting Values and Valuing Emotions. Gabriele Taylor was formerly Fellow in Philosophy at St Anne's College, Oxford. She is author of Pride, Shame, and Guilt. David Wiggins is Wykeham Professor of Logic at New College, Oxford. He is author of Sameness and Substance and Needs, Values, Truth. end p.viii 1 Modern Moral Philosophy and the Virtues Roger Crisp Abstract: Introduces a collection of specially commissioned articles on central topics in virtue ethics. Also provides an introduction to virtue ethics. The following topics are discussed: the ancient roots of virtue ethics; the nature of virtue ethics; the good of the virtuous agent; the demandingness of morality; universality tradition, and practice; community and gender; practical reason, moral knowledge, and moral education. Keywords: ancient ethics, demandingness, moral knowledge, practical reason, virtue, virtue ethics 1. An Ancient Question Should I go into business or into politics? Should I live the contemplative life, or seek after pleasure? Should I be just? These were among the questions Aristotle tried to answer over two thousand years ago in his lectures on ethics in Athens. Aristotle was working through an agenda already laid down by Socrates and Plato; in one of Plato's dialogues, Socrates asks, ‗What would even a person of little intelligence be more concerned about than this: how should one 1 live?‘ 1 c Plato, Gorgias 500 2–4. Our question, then, is an ancient one; but, on one view of the history of moral philosophy, it has in the modern era faded into the background. Our morality is heavily influenced by the Judaeo-Christian tradition, and has its roots in conceptions of divine law. This has had two results. First, the primary question has been not ‗How should I live?‘, but ‗How should I act?‘ Secondly, answers to the question about how to act have been put in terms of obligations. Morality is seen as a lawlike set of principles which binds us to perform or not to perform certain actions. The two moral traditions which have come to dominate modern philosophy certainly fit this description. One tradition begins with the German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), according to whom the right action is the one performed out of respect for the moral law. The other tradition, utilitarianism, has also focused almost without exception on the act which one is required to perform by morality (the act, in this case, that will produce the greatest overall good). This view of the legalistic turn in ethics was stated first in one of the most influential philosophy articles of the twentieth century, Elizabeth end p.1 PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com) © Copyright Oxford University Press, 2006. All Rights Reserved 2 Anscombe's ‗Modern Moral Philosophy‘, published in 1958. 2 G. E. M. Anscombe, ‗Modern Moral Philosophy‘, Philosophy 33 (1958), 1–19. Anscombe charged all contemporary moral philosophers with seeking foundations for pseudo-legalistic moralities of obligation that make little sense in the context of disbelief in the authority of a divine lawgiver. Anscombe's remedy for the modern malaise was that moral philosophy be put aside until an adequate philosophy of psychology, including analyses of notions such as action, intention, and pleasure, became available. ‗Eventually,‘ she claimed, ‗it might be possible to advance to considering the concept ―virtue‖; with which, I suppose, we should be 3 beginning some sort of a study of ethics.‘ 3 Ibid. 15. Anscombe believed that a return to an Aristotelian view of ethics, in which norms are founded not legalistically but on a conception of human flourishing with virtue at its centre, provided for moral philosophy the only hope of its retaining any significance. Why did utilitarianism and Kantianism dominate moral philosophy for so long? Anscombe's reference to the attraction of legalism undoubtedly has something in it, as do many of the alternative explanations that have been offered: the need for a rapprochement between various points of view facilitated by the notion of natural rights, the fact that it was Kant's earlier ethics that came to dominate discussion, the increasing complexity of society and the consequent need for rules, diminishing personal relations and increasing commercial and individualist relations, the simplicity and unity of some versions of utilitarianism and Kantianism, the modern emphasis on the 4 voluntary, and so on. 4 See J. Schneewind, ‗The Misfortunes of Virtue‘, Ethics 101 (1991), 42–63; E. Pincoffs, ‗Quandary Ethics‘, Mind 80 (1971), 552–71; M. Stocker, ‗The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories‘, Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976), 453–66; A. MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (London, 1981); A. Flemming, ‗Reviving the Virtues‘, Ethics 90 (1980), 587–95; H. Alderman, ‗By Virtue of a Virtue‘, Review of Metaphysics 36 (1982), 127–53; G. Hartz, ‗Desire and Emotion in the Virtue Tradition‘, Philosophia 20 (1990), 145–65. But whatever the reasons, it is hard to deny that the predominance of utilitarianism and Kantian ethics is at least under threat, and possibly already over. For Anscombe's challenge has been taken up by many philosophers, most of them intent on developing or meeting it. One effect of this work has been the emergence, or perhaps re-emergence, of what is now called ‗virtue ethics‘ or ‗virtue theory‘. Although virtue theory does have ancient roots, it is far from mere revivalism. Modern writers on the virtues, however keen they are on end p.2 PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com) © Copyright Oxford University Press, 2006. All Rights Reserved bridge-building, are not unaware of the vastness of the gulf that lies between us and the ancient Greeks. One of the central contrasts between ancient and modern virtue ethics is brought out nicely in Chapter 3 by Terence Irwin. Having noted that any Greek answer to the question of how one should live would most naturally be couched in the language of virtue (or aretē, ‗excellence‘), Irwin goes on to show how Greek philosophers rejected many common-sense views of the virtues: that they are concerned primarily with action, that different social roles require different virtues, that one can possess one virtue while lacking others, that they may be bad for the person who possesses them, and that they require not knowledge but the correct intuitive response. There is an interesting contrast here with the modern move in the direction of the virtues, which can be seen partly as an attempt to close a yawning gap between common sense and moral theory opened up by the ethical theory of the last few centuries. 2. About This Book Comparisons between ancient and modern treatments of the virtues, then, must be treated with care. But so must all generalizations about virtue theory. The idea for this book came to me while trying to teach Oxford undergraduates, who have less than a week to work on any one topic, about virtue ethics. So many philosophers have become involved, so many issues have been discussed from so many points of view, that I found myself unable to recommend a set of readings which would allow the students to see the main lines of argument, their subtlety and importance. This book, then, is in part an attempt to fill the gap in my reading list. Each contributor was commissioned to write on a specified topic central to virtue theory. The result is that the main strands in virtue theory have been teased out and woven together in such a way that even a reader without a philosophical background will be enabled to grasp them. Much of the writing in virtue theory has been negative, and the wide- ranging critique of Kantianism and utilitarianism will be further developed in this book (see especially the papers by Michael Slote, John Cottingham, Michael Stocker, and David Wiggins). But the second main aim of the book is positive: to suggest a broad agenda for future thought. This aim is achieved largely because the contributors themselves end p.3 PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com) © Copyright Oxford University Press, 2006. All Rights Reserved have played an important part in the debates which they clarify and continue in this volume. In this introduction, I shall offer my own account of virtue ethics and virtue theory, providing an overview of the main areas under debate and placing each paper in the volume on the philosophical map that emerges. But let me first briefly describe the structure of the book. In Chapter 2, Rosalind Hursthouse characterizes virtue ethics, and demonstrates how it can offer practical guidance. Terence Irwin in Chapter 3 puts virtue ethics into historical perspective, and in Chapter 4 John Cottingham brings out the importance of Aristotelian partiality in contrast to modern impartialist accounts of ethics. Focus then shifts to modern history, and the relationships between virtue ethics and its two main rivals, Kantianism and utilitarianism, are covered by Onora O'Neill and Michael Slote in Chapters 5 and 6 respectively. Aristotle grounded his virtue ethics in a conception of human nature, and in Chapter 7 Julia Driver discusses this idea, linking it to a utilitarian or consequentialist theory of the virtues (hence her place in the volume after Slote). Human nature was also appealed to by David Hume (1711–1776) as the foundation for the ‗natural‘ virtues, and David Wiggins provides in Chapter 8 an authoritative account of how these virtues are to be distinguished from others. Human nature and the human good are closely linked. In Chapter 9, Brad Hooker considers the claim, central to Greek ethics, that a flourishing human life will involve the virtues. Gabriele Taylor in turn shows in Chapter 10 how certain vices are incompatible with living a good life. In their accounts of the place of virtue in the good life, both Plato and Aristotle put a great deal of emphasis on reason. But both were also concerned with the emotions, and many modern writers have claimed

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.