ebook img

Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism PDF

198 Pages·1986·7 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism

HILBERT'S PROGRAM SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Florida State University, Tallahassee Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON, University of California, Berkeley GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden WES"LEY C. SALMON, University ofP ittsburgh VOLUME 182 MICHAEL DETLEFSEN Department of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame HILBERT'S PROGRAM An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism '"' SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging.in·Publication Data Detlefsen, Michael, 1948- Hilbert's program. Bibliography: p. lncludes index. 1. Mathematics-Philosophy. 2. Hilbert, David, 1862-1943. 1. Title. QA9.2.D48 1986 510'.1 86-6460 ISBN 978-90-481-8420-0 ISBN 978-94-015-7731-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-7731-1 AII Rights Reserved © 1986 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originaily published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland in 1986 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1s t edition 1986 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permis sion from the copyright owner. To Martha, Hans, Anna and Sara T ABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE IX ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xiii CHAPTER I: THE PHILOSOPHICAL FUNDAMENTALS OF HILBERT'S PROGRAM 1 1. Introduction 1 2. Hilbertian Instrumentalism 3 3. Hilbert and Quine: Frege's Problem Revisited 24 4. Concluding Summary 34 5. Notes 36 CHAPTER II: A CLOSER LOOK AT THE PROBLEMS 45 1. Introduction 45 2. The Status of Induction 46 3. Poincare's Problem 59 4. The Dilution Problem 62 5. Notes 73 CHAPTER III: THE GODELIAN CHALLENGE 77 1. Introduction 77 2. The Standard Argument 78 3. The Stability Problem 80 4. Strict Instrumentalism 83 5. The Convergence Problem and the Problem of Strict Instrumentalism 85 6. Conclusion 90 7. Notes 91 vii viii TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER IV: TH E ST ABILITY PROBLEM 93 1. Introduction 93 2. The Standard Choice of '(/f 94 3. Arithmetization 97 4. Mostowski's Proposal 101 5. The Kreisel-Takeuti Proposal 113 6. The Classical Proposal? 124 7. Conclusion 129 8. Notes 129 CHAPTER V: THE CONVERGENCE PROBLEM AND THE PROBLEM OF STRICT INSTRUMENTALISM 142 1. Introduction 142 2. Localization 145 3. The Problem of Strict Instrumentalism 148 4. The Convergence Problem 152 5. Conclusion 155 6. Notes 157 APPENDIX: HILBERT'S PROGRAM AND THE FIRST THEOREM 161 REFERENCES 179 INDEX 183 PREFACE Hilbert's Program was founded on a concern for the phenomenon of paradox in mathematics. To Hilbert, the paradoxes, which are at once both absurd and irresistible, revealed a deep philosophical truth: namely, that there is a discrepancy between the laws accord ing to which the mind of homo mathematicus works, and the laws governing objective mathematical fact. Mathematical epistemology is, therefore, to be seen as a struggle between a mind that naturally works in one way and a reality that works in another. Knowledge occurs when the two cooperate. Conceived in this way, there are two basic alternatives for mathematical epistemology: a skeptical position which maintains either that mind and reality seldom or never come to agreement, or that we have no very reliable way of telling when they do; and a non-skeptical position which holds that there is significant agree ment between mind and reality, and that their potential discrepan cies can be detected, avoided, and thus kept in check. Of these two, Hilbert clearly embraced the latter, and proposed a program designed to vindicate the epistemological riches represented by our natural, if non-literal, ways of thinking. Brouwer, on the other hand, opted for a position closer (in Hilbert's opinion) to that of the skeptic. Having decided that epistemological purity could come only through sacrifice, he turned his back on his classical heritage to accept a higher calling. And if that meant living a life of epistemological poverty in the eyes of the world, then so be it; poverty would find its consolation in purity. To Hilbert, this was hollow piety. Homo mathematicus some times goes astray, but he is not born in sin. Therefore, the answer is not for him to deny his nature, but rather to take precautions to see that he does not succumb to the false beauty of paradox. This way, he can live a life not only of holiness, but also of abundance; ix x PREFACE and such a life is surely preferable to that of the needless self denial preached by the intuitionists. In this spirit, Hilbert boldly set forth his program to vindicate the patterns of reasoning to which homo mathematicus'cognitive nature predisposes him. This program had two parts; one descriptive, the other justifica tory. The aim of the former was to produce the sort of description of our natural ways of mathematical reasoning that makes precise evaluation of that reasoning possible. For Hilbert, this amounted to formalizing mathematical thought in the manner so ably illustrated by the work of Russell and Whitehead. Thus, he was led to say that The formula game that Brouwer so deprecates has, besides its mathematical value, an important general philosophical significance. For this formula game is carried out according to certain definite rules, in which the technique of our thinking is expressed. These rules form a closed system that can be discovered and definitively stated. The fundamental idea of my proof theory is none other than to describe the activity of our understanding, to make a protocol of the rules according to which our thinking actually proceeds. Thinking, it so happens, parallels speaking and writing: we form statements and place them one behind another. If any totality of observations and phenomena deserves to be made the object of a serious and thorough investigation, it is this one ... (Hilbert [1927), p. 475) The aim of the justificatory part of Hilbert's Program was to produce a finitary proof of the reliability of our natural modes of mathematical reasoning. And, as is well known, it is this part of the program that became the target both of a massive technical assault by Godel's Theorems, and of a sustained philosophical attack based on anti-Cartesian epistemological views. In our opinion, most of this criticism is mistaken. We take Hilbert's Program, as reconstructed here, to be a philosophically sophisti cated and convincing defense of mathematical instrumentalism. And we also believe that it can withstand the usual technical criticisms based on Godel's Theorems. These are the central themes of this essay, and the main reasons for writing it. In Chapter I we set out the chief philosophical problems confronting Hilbert's instrumentalist outlook. These include (1) a PREFACE xi problem of Frege's concerning the compatibility of treating a mathematical proof both as a purcly formal cntity and as a means of knowledge towards the proposition expressed by its conclusion, (2) a problem of Poincare's concerning a possible vicious circu larity in Hilbert's metamathematical use of induction, and (3) a problem concerning how the instrumentalist can be sure that in taking the epistemic shortcuts provided by his instrument, he does not dilute the epistemic quality of the product that results from its use. In Chapter II we show how Hilbert's Program is equipped to deal with the first two problems, and how it is out of concern for the third problem that its finitism is best motivated. The rest of the main body of the text is given to a discussion of the third problem, which we call the Dilution Problem. This problem is given urgency by GCidel's Second Theorem, which threatens its solvability by allegedly ruling out a finitary proof of the reliability of all but the weakest systems of mathe matics. The argument underlying this allegation is set out in considerable detail in Chapter III, and its more serious inade quacies are exposed in Chapters IV and V. Finally, in the Appen dix we contend with some of the supposedly anti-Hilbertian con sequences of Godel's First Theorem, dismissing them as unfounded. The end result, we hope, is an essay which helps the philoso pher of mathematics and the philosophically interested logician or mathematician to come to a better understanding and appreciation of Hilbert's Program and mathematical instrumentalism generally. If it goes even a little way toward counteracting the common misunderstandings of GCidel's Theorems and the crude charges of formalism that have sullied the literature on Hilbert's Program, we will consider it a success.

Description:
Hilbert's Program was founded on a concern for the phenomenon of paradox in mathematics. To Hilbert, the paradoxes, which are at once both absurd and irresistible, revealed a deep philosophical truth: namely, that there is a discrepancy between the laws accord­ ing to which the mind of homo mathema
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.