ebook img

Generic species and basic levels: Essence and appearance in folk biology PDF

27 Pages·1997·15.9 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Generic species and basic levels: Essence and appearance in folk biology

Summer Journal Ethnobiology 17(l):17-43 1997 of AND GENERIC BASIC SPECIES LEVELS: AND APPEARANCE FOLK BIOLOGY ESSENCE IN ATRAN SCOTT Research Institute for Social Michigan University of MI Ann 48106-1248 Arbor, PAUL ESTIN and Psychology Cognition Perception Michigan University of MI Ann 48106-1248 Arbor, JOHN COLEY DOUGLAS MEDIN Department Psychology of Northwestern University 60208-2710 Evanston, IL ABSTRACT.— same taxonomic rank cognitively privi- Results indicate that the is two populations: people raised in Michi- leged for biological induction in diverse — and Maya This the generic species the level gan, of the Peten rainforest. is Itzaj — rank but with a of oak and robin which coextensive with Berlin's folkgeneric is unaccounted cannot and Rosch her example, col- For measures taneously of privilege. yield different — — and bird rather than leagues suggest forms the level of tree that life many Americans. Rosch, like Berlin, folkgenerics comprise the "basic level" for account for privileged cat- advances such domain-general models of similarity to best repre- perceptual attributes that egories as maximally informative clusters of However, favors cross-cultural dif- this sent "objective discontinuities" in nature. function of differences in famil- ferences in the rank privileged in induction as a some relative Although our data indicate with environment. iarity the natural Americans among industrialized rank downgrading knowledge higher a of to among Maya, these differences are and upgrading lower rank silvicultural to a generic spe- privilege of absolute To account for the clearly a second-order effect. favors offered. view folkbiology It of is domain-specific cies in diverse cultures, a domains ontological of the partitioning the idea of the generic-species level as a and the bio- The of essence, attribution of plant and animal into causal essences. experience or independent of actual go with part in logical expectations that is it, This reflects a cogni- kind question. with in degree the of perceptual familiarity and domain- perceptual heuristics between domain-general tive division of labor may design. which be an evolutionary mechanisms, specific learning ATRAN, COLEY MEDIN ESTIN, and No.l 18 Vol. 17, — RESUMEN. mismo Nuestros resultados indican que rango taxonomico es el privilegiado cognoscitivamente en dos poblaciones gente que credo diferentes: en Michigan, en Estados Unidos de Norteamerica, Mayas de selva los y Itzaj la — tropical del Peten en Guatemala. Este rango taxonomico es especie generica la — el nivel del encino y el petirrojo que coincide con lo que Berlin llama el nivel generico pero un Los modelos de formation 'folk' tiene sentido teorico distinto. de categorias e induccion basados en similitud no pueden dar cuenta de estos la resultados porque tales modelos no pueden producir simultaneamente diferentes medidas de privilegio. Por ejemplo, Rosch y sus colegas sugieren que son las formas — — de vida el nivel al que pertenecen arbol y pajaro mas que los genericos 'folk' que comprenden muchos las el "nivel basico" para norteamericanos. Rosch, al igual que Berlin, propone tales modelos de similitud, generates a todo dominio, para como maximamente explicar las categorias privilegiadas conjuntos, informativos, de atributos perceptuales que mejor representan las "discontinuidades objetivas" de la naturaleza. Esto, sin embargo, favorece las como diferencias entre culturas en rango privilegiado en induccion funcion el la de las diferencias en familiaridad con medio ambiente. bien nuestros datos el Si indican disminucion cierta relativa del conocimiento hacia rangos superiores en- tre los norteamericanos industrializados, y un aumento del conocimiento hacia rangos inferiores entre los silvicultores mayas, estas diferencias son claramente un de segundo efecto orden. Para responder privilegio absolute de especie al la generica en diversas culturas, ofrecemos una perspectiva de dominio especifica de la biologia 'folk'. Esta perspectiva favorece idea del nivel de especie generica la la como una de division los dominios ontologicos planta y animal en esencias La causales. atribucion de esencia, y las expectativas biologicas que conlleva, son independientes en parte de la experiencia real o grado de familiaridad percep- el con tual en la clase cuestion. Esto una refleja division cognoscitiva del trabajo entre la heuristica perceptual de dominio general y los mecanismos de aprendizaje de dominio especifico, division que puede un diseno ser evolutivo. RESUME.— Notre enquete indique que dans deux populations ha- distinctes, les Hii-Antc r^rirriK^ii-ac- _-._» \/f;^U. t7j.~ ___ t t__ • _ _ . i _ _ *Mkaya »-__• i i_ e _ _ _•_« • j gnitiv connaissance des elements biologiques. II — de s'agit l'espece generique gorge qui est coextensive au niveau du generique un populaire de Berlin mais qui a sens theorique Ces different. resultats ne peuvent modeles de s'expliquer par des la formation de categorielle et l'induction fondes sur de modeles la similarite, car tels momo DPUWnt ne fnirmir on meme ___ J„ urnir en ttnetmvip^so u.,n-e .i_._i.___ _•<-<•' _.__ '-i__ii mesure de predilection qui sont a l'a?uvre. Par exemple, Rosch collegues et ses — suggerent que pour de nombreux Americains, formes de niveau d'arbre les vie — le et d'oiseau constituent le "niveau de base" au des generiques populaires. lieu Comme Rosch Berlin, propose de tels modeles de domaines generaux de similarite pour rendre compte des categories privilegiees en que groupes porteurs tant d'lnformation maximale d'attributs perceptuels representant mieux les le — j^vx. ut ^ w> xa naiuic. luuieiuib, ceci iaisse croire a aes airrerenceb culturelles relatives a la selection inductive du rang de qui seraient fonction ... n iffPriori .roc r\r\ f<*«>% «1 ««*«..: .t,x ^ i_ ___•!• *^-^. < - donnees un Michigan un et May ' Summer JOURNAL OF ETHNOBIOLOGY 1997 19 evidemment un Une forestiers, ces differences constituent effet secondaire. per- spective specifique au domaine de biologie populaire peut rendre compte de la la predilection absolue pour niveau de l'espece generique dans diverses cultures. le Selon cette perspective, le niveau de Tespece generique serait le resultat d'un morcellement des domains ontologiques de plante d animal en essences causales. et — — L'attribution de l'essence attentes biologiques qui l'accompagnent est et les partiellement independante de l'experience concrete ou du degre de familiarite du perceptuelle avec sorte en question. Ceci reflete une division cognitive tra- la entre une heuristique perceptuelle orientee vers domaine general et des vail, le — mecanismes d'apprentissage tourne vers domaine specifique ce qui pourrait le d'un schema relever evolutif. INTRODUCTION i psychology inducth This paper uses a standard tool of cognitive — the ence explore the cognitive validity of folkbiological ranks. In particular, to .~— Aft . - * 1 maximizes - * inferences same The across cultures. crucial nomic concerning living kinds. example, findin up category members as fairly similar to the life-form industrialized society see and Boyes- Mervis, Gray, Johnson, that the level of tree or bird (Rosch, el. is. major breakpoint Braem Zubin and Kopcke 1986 Germany). so, the for If 1976; see between should appear the or elbow in inductive confidence in such cultures life- and by colleagues Berlin his form and observations level higher levels. In contrast, — — on oak and robin suggest that the of the salience of the folkgeneric the level should be between the folkgeneric breakpoint subsistence society in a small-scale following para- and Raven the and Breedlove, 1973). In level higher levels (Berlin, we present experiment. graphs develop these ideas to motivate the ethnobiological work and colleagues, Ever pioneering of Berlin his since the human everywhere have similar evidence has been accumulating that societies Hays and Raven Huron 1977; 1983; 1974; Breedlove, folkbiological structures (Berlin, similarities Brown These cross-cultural striking Atran Berlin 1992). 1984; 1990; systems define universally number organizing principles suggest that a small of are organized into groups, or taxa, of Folkbiological folkbiological classification. Most folkbiological ranks, which represent an embedding of distinct levels of reality. same rank are mutually and Taxa of the systems have between ranks. three six similar linguistic acteristics. Ranks and whether in taxa, them category mistake. Bioiogi and confounding a different logical orders, is wh kingdom) family, groups species, ranks are second-order classes of e.g., ( ranks se Folkbiological animal). elements are first-order groups (e.g., lion, feline, systems or belief function of theories vary cultures as a to across at little, if all, ATRAN, COLEY MEDIN 20 ESTIN, and No.l Vol. 17, other words, such ranks are universal but not the taxa they contain. Ranks are 2 intended to represent fundamentally different levels of not convenience. reality, The most general folkbiological rank the folk kingdom. Examples are plant is and animal Such taxa are not always explicitly named, and represent the most . fundamental divisions of the biological world. These divisions correspond to the notion of "ontological category" philosophy (Donnellan and psychology in 1971) From an humans any (Keil 1979). early age, appears, cannot help but conceive of it object they see in the world as either being or not being an animal and there is evidence for an early distinction between plants and nonliving things (Inagaki and Hatano in press). Conceiving of an object as a plant or animal seems to carry with assumptions it certain that are not applied to objects thought of as belonging to other ontological categories, like the categories of substance or artifact (Keil Mandler and McDonough Most form. or another life form. Life-form taxa often have unanalyzable names (simple lexically primary lexemes), such and some names as "tree" "bird," although life-form are analyzable, such "quadruped." members as taxon are Biologically, of a life-form diverse. Psychologically, members number of a life-form taxon share a small of perceptual stem diagnostics: and (Brown aspect, skin covering, so forth 1984). Life- may form taxa represent adaptations broad such to sets of ecological conditions, among as competition single-stem plants for sunlight and tetrapod adaptation to (Hunn life in the air 1982; Atran 1985). Classifying by form may occur early on: life two-year-olds distinguish familiar kinds quadruped dog and from of horse) (e.g., sea versus animals (Mandler air et 1991). al. The any core of folk taxonomy, according to Berlin, the folkgeneric level. is Like life-form named taxa, folkgeneric taxa are often by simple lexemes, such as "oak" and "robin." Sometimes, compounds, folkgenerics are labeled as binomial On "hummingbird." like may other occasions, they be optionally labeled as bino- mial // oak makes tree." In both cases the binomial between and generic form. t life Folkgenerics often correspond to scientific genera or species, at least for the most phenomenally salient organisms, such and flowering as larger vertebrates On plants. occasion generic species can correspond fragments to local of biologi- — — cal families (e.g., vulture) oorrddeerrss aanndd ((ee..gg..,, bbaatt)) especially with invertebrates , , may gical taxa (Atran 1987a; Berlin Folkgenerics 1992). also be the most categories easily recognized, most commonly named and most easily learned by children in small-scale Indeed, societies (Stross 1973). who ethnobiologists otherwise differ in their views of folktaxonomy tend to agree one that level best captures fundamen- discontinuities in nature and provides the tal constituents in systems all of and use folkbiological categorization, reasoning (Bulmer Hunn 1974; 1982; Ellen 1993). what we In follows, use term the "generic species," rather than "folk genera/ folk generic" (Berlin 1972) or "folk species/folk specieme" (Bulmer three for 1970), reasons. First, a principled between distinction biological genus and species is not pertinent to local folk around The the world. most Dhenomenallv spe- salient mans, mo including ms and monos belons cacti to Summer JOURNAL OF ETHNOBIOLOGY 1997 21 Hunn genus hard hence no mor- in a locale are often to distinguish, readily perceptible phological or ecological "gap" can be discerned between them (Diver 1940). second, the term // generi•c speci• es // reflects a more accurate sense or the corre- spondence between groups and psychologically privileged folkbiological initial wide "Age number of Exploration/' the order of magnitude. Foreign species were habitually joined to the most similar European species; that to the generic type in a "natural system." Historically, is, then, the distinction between genus and species did not appear until the influx of newly discovered species from around the world compelled European naturalists to mnemonically manage them within a worldwide system of genera built around ma As Third, the term "generic species" reflects their dual character. privileged mnemonic groups, they are akin to genera in being those groups most readily apparent the naked eye (Cain As privileged causal groups, they are akin to 1956). to species in being the principal loci of evolutionary processes responsible for the appearance (Mayr In Western science, the dual char- of biological diversity 1969). taxonomy // eventually "fissioned acter of this privileged level of folkbiological and genera (Tournefort into species (Cesalpino 1583) 1694). PpodIp in rnlhirpQ snnntaneouslv partition the ontoloeical categories ani ^11 mal and exhaustive manner. "Virtually plant into generic species in a virtually exhaustive" means when an organism encountered that not readily iden- that is is named expected belong tifiable as beloneine to a generic species, it is still to to named organism often assimilated to one of the taxa it resembles is « em rutiny sometimes assiened an // i is it "such-and-such a plant some [generic-species] kind of tree," cf. Berlin in (e.g., is and seems be part parcel of press). This partitioning of ontological categories to belong uniquely no animal can principle to the categories themselves: plant or fail in to a generic species. Moreover, from data presume kind have an "essence," or underlying each living to distincti re (Gelman kind appearance of that for the typical isible understanding and Wellman At presumption involves only global 1991). this first produced but perhaps that the readily outsides of living kinds are by, dif- visible Children lack concrete or specific ferent from, their initially invisible insides. initially Over they (Simmons and time, pieces of knowledge about each kind Keil 1995). presumed essences as responsible for try to flesh out the causal properties of these and and growth and Gelman inheritance (Springer Keil 1989), (Hickling 1995), and (Hatano kind complementary body parts in a living functioning of distinct presumed which universally to Inagaki Such causal essences, are 1994). intrinsic and substances) be both mechanical causes affecting inert teleological (unlike the unique appear be to to fashioned internally directed (unlike externally artifacts), domain kinds and primari cognitive of living cies. These taxa are may be divided into folkspecifics. further species c Compound "white names, like with secondary lexemes. binomially, ATRAN, COLEY MEDIN 22 ESTIN, and Vol. 17, No.l make oak" and "mountain robin." and have high generic species folkspecifics. Folkspecifics that tradition of cul- its may tural salience be labeled with primary lexemes, such as "winesap" kind of (a how apple tree) and "tabby" (a kind of cat). In general, whether and a generic cultural lm exam with trinomially, make lexemes that transparent their taxonomic relationship with superordinat n example "spotted white oak. Thus, in addition to generic species, people everywhere tend to form groups that are both subordinate and superordinate to the level of privileged groups. This regular "groups under grouping classification of groups... not arbitrary like the is of stars in constellations" arwin anisms svstem into a designed embedded to represent the structure of around with the generic- us, life may species level being most informative. In some but not people cultures, all, develop "theories" of life that are meant to cover living kinds, such as Western all theories of biology (Carey 1985; Atran 1995a). But the very possibility of such theo- would rizing not without provide exist a universal construal of generic species to the transtheoretical basis for scientific speculation about the biological world. Dif- — — ferent biological theories including evolutionary theory arose to initially account "common for the apparent constancy and the of [generic] species" for apparent similarities and differences between them Mayr (Wallace 1969:37). 1889:1; Given these observations, or results of psychological studies of privilege periments validity taxonomic measures they found that there indeed of is a "basic level" in category hierarchies "naturally occurring objects," such as "taxonomies" of as well as living artifacts kinds Brown, (cf. Kolar, Torrey, Troung-Quang, and Volkman For artifact 1976). and living kind hierarchies, the basic was where: many common features level (1) are listed for categories, consistent motor programs employed (2) are for the inter- action with or manipulation members have of category exemplars, category (3) enough similar shapes so that it is possible to recognize an average shape for ob- jects of the category. For example, many were more subjects able features for to list dog chair or than mammal, for furniture or but few added kitchen features for chair or They terrier. could also readily construct an average image chair or for dog but not mammal. for furniture or Rosch found also that basic-level cat- et al. egories are preferred in adult naming, and the level learned by children, at first which was categorization fastest. work Thus, by and Berlin Rosch both indicate a privileged level in cat- egory hierarchies. Moreover, both claim that this privileged take on naturally occurring objects directly is tied to objective discontinuities in the real world. These objective discontinuities provide the information-rich bundles of perceptual at- tributes that presumably allow a domain-general mechanism perceptual processing carve up to nature at fundamental its joints. Summer JOURNAL OF ETHNOBIOLOGY 1997 23 But here's the rub that motivates the present study: The basic level that Rosch was hammer, how- hypothesized confirmed et (1976) for artifacts guitar); al. (e.g., ever, the hypothesized basic level for living kinds maple, trout), which Rosch (e.g., presumed would was initially accord with Berlin's generic rank, not. Instead of maple and trout, Rosch found that tree and fish operated as basic-level cat- et al. egories for American college students. Except for very familiar animals dog, (e.g., chicken), Rosch's basic level for living kinds corresponds to Berlin's life-form level. To explore the cognitive basis for this apparent discrepancy between Berlin we and Rosch, introduce the examination of inductive inference into our study. knowledge beyond immediate Inductive inference allows people extend their to experience and beyond the information they are given, and a crucial part of is category formation and use (Rips 1975; Smith and Medin 1981). Although neither Berlin nor Rosch deal with inductive inference, such inferences are ar- explicitly what guably central to understanding preference for certain categories. For is mammal amount informa- privileged about or tabby that the of cat relative to is may maximized tion that can be inferred about the category be at the level of cat. may Thus, knowing that a tabby eats fish, be prima facie reasonable to infer that it mammals all cats eat fish, but unreasonable to infer from this that all eat fish. good an Moreover, knowing that a short-haired tabby eats fish is likely as indica- them tion that all cats eat as it is that all tabbies do. most information about the world, categories a privileged level carries the If what wide about at that level should strongly support a range of inferences is common among members. privileged category white oak to Inferences to a (e.g., much superordinate oak, tabby should be stronger than inferences to a to cat) subordinate category oak mammal). Moreover, inferences to a (e.g., to tree, cat to should tabby tabby) category white oak white oak, short-haired to spotted to (e.g., not be much stronger or different than inferences to a privileged category. taxonomic The our experiment that the privileged hypothesis motivating is remaining constant across the sense of level for biological induction absolute, in is Unlike relative culture, and not relative, in the sense of varying across cultures. by general notions of per- driven not primarily privilege, absolute privilege is the absolute inductive Instead, ceived experience, or cultural expertise. similarity, may assumptions be anchored in cognitive privilege of the generic-species level everywhere people The domain idea that peculiar to a universal of folkbiology. is govern the presume main causal processes that kinds be the loci of essential to and underlying apparent world, even the superficial structure of the biological if Medin and Ortony known (Atran 1987b; properties of such kinds are at first little Gelman, and 1989; Coley, Gottfried 1994). show ab- we members widely divergent cultures to Although expect of these we may also find generic-species level, solute psychological privilege at the knowledge leading to sec- evidence devolution of folkbiological of the effects of Dougherty Specifically, ondary induction patterns across cultures. differences in knowledge de- world leads to with natural the (1978) argues that lack of contact may show secondary privilege for Americans cay more thus at specific levels; with the bio- dependence on intimate interaction higher-order Likewise, taxa. Itzaj may secondary privilege lead to logical world, coupled with a silviculture tradition, for lower-order taxa. ATRAN No.l Vol. 17, 24 examining competing claims of absolute versus relative privi- In addition to the our experiment must also deal with claims for a more general sort of reasoning lege, What from most per- we deem missing which progressive privilege. is heuristic, accounts category formation in class-inclusion ception-based or similarity-based of how made taxonomy across the hierarchies an explanation of inferences are is understand the from one category to another. Such an explanation is necessary to any understand- and work do taxonomic reasoning, crucial to that categories in is most attempts to one elegant ing of underlying (biological) relationships. In of the Osherson, Smith, Wilkie, taxonomic explain similarity-based inference to date, pre- argument Lopez, and Shafir depict an inferential as categorical if its (1990) C C where a and form members have property P, is mises conclusion take the All of ROBIN same premises natural category or BIRD, and P remains the across like An mad cow and conclusions. example Guernsey cows are susceptible to disease; is mad cow The argument psychologically cows therefore are susceptible to disease. is all conclusion. strong to the extent that belief in its premises engenders belief in its perceived or Osherson model based exclusively on an evaluation of the et al.'s is presumed between premise and conclusion categories. similarities model The from that prediction of progressive privilege that follows this is any given premise category held constant a particular taxonomic level, ar- for at gument conclusion category. strength should decrease the higher the level of the Thus, inductive strength should decrease incrementally from varietal to specific, and kingdom. Also, for varietal to generic species, varietal to form, varietal to life argument strength any given conclusion category held constant at a particular level, the should increase as one changes the premise category to one that is closer to spe- conclusion category. For example, inductive strength from varietal to generic should be than from 5 By our hypothesis cies less specific to generic species. contrast, inference entails that absolute rather than progressive privilege will account for patterns across folkbiological ranks. METHODS — — — men women Twelve and in the village Itzaj participants. Itzaj six six living San Guatemala 6 Maya Amerindians of Peten, lose, participated in the study. are Itzaj men de- living in the tropical forest region of Peten, Guatemala. Until recently, women voted time and whereas their to shifting agriculture, hunting, silviculture, concentrated on the myriad tasks of household maintenance. The comprised Itzaj and the last independent native polity to be conquered by Spaniards (in 1697), Maya have preserved knowledge Lowland virtually ethnobiological recorded all for since the time of the initial Spanish conquest (Atran Despite the current 1993). awesome rate of deforestation and demise use language and culture, the in of Itzaj Maya among ethic of traditional silviculture very much evidence the in is still who generation of our informants range in age from 50 80 years old (Atran, to Medin, Lynch, Ross, Vapnarsky, and Ucan spoke Span- Ek' in press). Participants ish as well as Itzaj, but testing was exclusively in They were acquainted with Itzaj. the author, and compensated first at relative ease in the testing situation. All were for their participation. Summer JOURNAL OF ETHNOBIOLOGY 1997 25 — Michigan The American were men and women participants. 21 participants five 16 who ranged in age from 17 to 25. They were self-identified as people raised in Michigan, and recruited through an advertisement campus newspaper. in a local were All paid for their participation. — we Based on work Itzaj materials. extensive field with the Itzaj, chose a set of Itzaj kingdom folkbiological categories of the life-form generic-species (K), (L), (G), We and = folkspecific varietal (V) ranks. selected three plant forms: che' (S), life We 7 = = 'tree ak' 'vine', pok~che' 'herb' /'underbrush'. also selected three animal , life forms: b'a'al~che' kuximal = 'walking animal', mammal, ch'iich' - 'birds i.e., including kay = Three were chosen from each generic-species taxa bats', 'fish'. life form such that each generic species had a subordinate folkspecific, and each had 7 Although some names com- folkspecific a salient varietal. Itzaj life-form are posites (e.g., b'a'al~ che' kuximal) while others are primary lexemes (e.g., ch'iich'), previous experiments indicate that this linguistic difference has no impact on infer- ence patterns within forms (Lopez in press; Atran in press). Categories Itzaj life et al. used and their approximate English translations are presented in Table 1. — TABLE Natural kind used 1. stimuli in Itzaj study. Folk Kingdom Form Generic Species Folk Specific Varietal Life & & animal kuximal kay) (b'a'al~che' ch'iich' mammal (b'a'al~che') agouti (tzu') green agouti (ya'ax tzu') large green agouti (noj ya'ax tzu') squirrel (ku'uk) red squirrel (chak ku'uk) (chak ku'uk uchupal) female red squirrel monkey spider (tuuchaj) monkey black spider (b'ox tuuchaj) monkey tuuchaj male black spider (b'ox uxib'al) h') vulture (ch'om) ch'om) black vulture (b'ox ch'om chak red-headed black vulture (b'ox upol) hawk (ch'uy) hawk water (ch'uy-il ja') hawk black water (b'ox ch'uy-il ja*) (kolonte') kolonte') woodpecker black-backed red upach) (chak kolonte' b'ox fish (kay) catfish (lu ) kaj) village catfish (lu'-il (noj kaj) large village catfish lu'-il MEDIN COLEY ATRAN, and No.l ESTIN, Vol. 26 17, — TABLE Continued. 1. Kingdom Form Folk Generic Species Folk Specific Varietal Life (b'ox) yo'mojara (yo' b'ox) {mo'nok small yo'mojara yo' b'ox) sardine (chilam) red-tailed sardine (chak~nej chilam) male (chak-nej chilam sardine red-tailed uxib'al) fco (che') tree (p'ut) papaya village tree (p'ut-il kaj) papaya yellow put'-il village tree (k'iin kaj) savanna green joom savanna nance (ya'ax tree joom chakan) chi' hogplum tree (ab'al) hogplu forest (job k'aax) (p che') male cordoncillo (pu'uk che' uxib'al) (p chawak) uxib'al kits ip'ak) tomato breast (chu'chu' p'ak) p'ak) sweet breast tomato (ch'uuk chu'chu' pepper chili (ifc) sweet pepper (ch'uuk chili ik) red sweet pepper ch'uuk ik) chili (chiik JO bean (b'u'ul) bean red tzama bean tzama' b'u'ul) (chiik squash (k'uum) chuyut squash (chuyut k'uum) chuyut spring chayut squash (k'ik'i'ix k'uum)

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.