FOUNDATIONS OF LOGICO-LINGUISTICS SYNTHESE LANGUAGE LIBRAR Y TEXTS AND STUDIES IN LINGUISTICS AND PHILOSOPHY Managing Editors: J A A K K 0 H IN T I K K A • Academy of Finland and Stanford University S TAN LEY PET E R S. The University of Texas at Austin Editorial Board: EM M 0 N B A C H • University ofM assachusetts at Amherst J 0 A N B RES NAN. Massachuestts Institute of Technology J 0 H N L YON S. University of Sussex JU LIU SM. E. MORA VCSIK. Stanford University PAT R IC K S U PPE S. Stanford University DAN A S COT T • Oxford University VOLUME 2 WILLIAM S. COOPER FOUNDATIONS OF LOGICO-LINGUISTICS A Unified Theory 0/ In/ormation, Language, and Logic D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT: HOLLAND / BOSTON: U. S. A. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Cooper, William S. Foundations of logico·linguistics. (Synthese language library; v. 2) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Language and logic. 2. Information theory. I. Title. II. Series. P39.C68 410 78-552 ISBN·I3: 978·90·277·0876·2 e·ISBN·13: 978·94·009·9820·9 DOl: 10. I 007/978·94·009·9820·9 2-0876-0619·500·NC Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, Dordrecht, Holland Sold and distributed in the U.S.A., Canada, and Mexico by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Inc. Lincoln Building, 160 Old Derby Street, Hingham, Mass. 02043, U.S.A. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1978 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form by or any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner For friend CLARE FOREWORD In 1962 a mimeographed sheet of paper fell into my possession. It had been prepared by Ernest Adams of the Philosophy Department at Berkeley as a handout for a colloquim. Headed 'SOME FALLACIES OF FORMAL LOGIC' it simply listed eleven little pieces of reasoning, all in ordinary English, and all absurd. I still have the sheet, and quote a couple of the arguments here to give the idea. • If you throw switch S and switch T, the motor will start. There fore, either if you throw switch S the motor will start, or, ify ou throw switch T the motor will start. • It is not the case that if John passes history he will graduate. Therefore, John will pass history. The disconcerting thing about these inferences is, of course, that under the customary truth-functional interpretation of and, or, not, and if-then, they are supposed to be valid. What, if anything, is wrong? At first I was not disturbed by the examples. Having at that time consider able personal commitment to rationality in general and formal logic in par ticular, I felt it my duty and found myself easily able (or so I thought) to explain away most of them. But on reflection I had to admit that my expla nations had an ad hoc character, varying suspiciously from example to example. Moreover, I had no idea whether these were isolated oddities or per vasive problems: for all I knew there might be many more such examples where those eleven came from. Under the influence of a temporary fit of intellectual honesty I asked Adams if such was indeed the case. It was. I then experimented with further argument forms generated more or less randomly. It began to appear that once one got beyond the simple inference patterns discussed in logic textbooks, English arguments for which the classical rules oflogic failed to work right (when applied in textbook fashion) were almost as common as those for which they did. One might almost as well flip coins as use the classical logic to try to predict which English argu ments would seem reasonable and which not! vii viii FOREWORD My confidence in formal logic still shaken only slightly, I concluded that either the English-to-Iogic 'translation' rules suggested in elementary text books needed very substantial elaboration, or else that English conformed better to one of the well-known nonclassical systems such as n-valued, intuitionistic, or modal logic than to the classical two-valued system. The latter possibility seemed especially real; after all, some of the founding fathers of the nonclassical systems had expressed their dissatisfaction with the classical conditional, explicitly mentioning its faults as a motivating factor in the establishment of their systems. I found, however, that none of these sys terns survived the test of actual experiment. Typically, they at first raised my hopes by reversing the predictions of the classical logic for at least some of the troublesome English examples for which the latter had failed. The prob lem was, as further checking always seemed to show, that they reversed its predictions in just as many cases where it had succeeded. The net gain in fidelity to what seemed reasonable in English was approximately nil. Well, there were still a number of lesser-known systems of logic to try - systems proposed in the logico-philosophical journal literature as offering conditional connectives more 'natural' in some senses that the standard con ditionals. Discouragingly, none of those I examined fared much better than their standard predecessors at capturing the properties of the colloquial if-then and the other connectives. In fairness it must be noted that some were never intended to do so. But I was surprised to discover that others, which did seem to make some such claim, were typically based on only one or two interesting but isolated examples of English usage - hardly a massive body of evidence. Eventually I grew weary of checking out empirically unsup ported systems and stopped. It seemed to me that a claim to have captured the properties of the English if-then was essentially a linguistic claim, hence a scientific claim calling for empirical justification. Anyone making such a claim ought to accept the burden of presenting some evidence in support of it, I thought, and not simply leave the empirical testing as an exercise to the reader. Of course, there is not necessarily anything wrong with a system of logic which fails to conform to ordinary English usage. But it seemed nonetheless legitimate to ask: If none of the usual systems of logic is the logic ofE nglish, what is? To this question there appeared to be no convincing answer in either the logico-philosophical or the linguistic literature. Conceivably the question FOREWORD ix was wrongly posed; for instance, for all I knew one of the standard systems could still be the basic underlying logic of English, but with English-logic translation rules far more subtle and elaborate than had been generally sup posed. But if so, the question would merely arise in a different form, namely, What are the translation rules? The problem of how to discover the underlying logic of a natural language seemed to me then a serious and important one, and it has left me without excuse for idleness ever since. There are two general problems involved, both formidable. The first is the matter of evidence. What sorts of empirical observations are needed to lay bare a language's 'logical' structure? Is there a practical informant technique, as might be hoped on the basis of experience in conventional linguistics, or is some radically different experimental methodology indicated? The second problem, really an elaboration of the first, is that of constructing a foundational theory within which to interpret or even motivate the observations. It is recognized these days that just as scientific theories need to be tested out against observation, so one needs a prior theoretical framework (or 'paradigm') before one can draw interesting conclusions from the data or even know what data to gather. What then should be the paradigm within which to explore natural language logic? Issues relating to these questions have of course been illuminated by many prominent thinkers, usually from the point of view of one particular disci line. Yet the problem as a whole remains elusive. The trouble seems to be that when the matter of the logical structure of natural language is examined from the perspective of anyone of the existing disciplines (with the possible exception of philosophy), the problem either cannot be perceived at all or else appears already solved. Nor is it clear that if the problem as a whole were to be solved, the solution would be recognized as a solution within any pres ently existing tradition. (One is reminded of the man who saw a jigsaw puzzle before and again after it had been assembled. When an attempt was made to point out to him the beautiful picture which had emerged he remarked, "But what has been accomplished? There are no new pieces there at all!") It may be that most of what is needed to construct a unified theory of language and logic is already at hand, lacking only the connecting links. Most of the pieces of the jigsaw puzzle may already be in plain sight, in other words, in which case it is high time to start fitting them together. I personally suspect this to be the case, and hope that the present work may contribute to x FOREWORD the fitting-together process. To be specific, I believe that it is now possible to start to integrate parts of mathematical logic, descriptive linguistics, the phil osophy of language and logic, automata theory, Bayesian probability theory, and certain areas of artificial intelligence research, into a coherent logico linguistic theory of human communication. Having admitted to unification as my ulterior motive, I must quickly beg for charity. Tolerance is needed on the part of the reader of a work con cerned with unification. Since each reader is apt to be acquainted with some but not all of the disciplines involved, a certain amount of introductory material must be included for every field touched upon - to the annoyance of those already familiar with it. A related problem is that of mathematical level. The goal of unification demands clarity as to which are the primitive terms of the theory, which the definitions, and which the theorems - in other words a formal mathematical development. Such a development is bound to be too technical for some and not detailed enough for others. The compromise adopted here is to assume familiarity with elementary logic and set theory, the rudiments of probability theory, and a nodding acquaintance with descriptive linguistics. To ease the mathematical burden all formal develop ments are presented in the sans-serif typeface in which this sentence is set. Readers interested only in the intuitive drift of the argument may wish to skip or skim much of this material. The mathematical proofs can in any case be omitted by those willing to take the theorems on faith. In an area as difficult as the foundations of language and logic, the only certainty is that any large new theory will tum out to be wrong in at least some points, and will eventually be superseded. Theories should therefore be stated as precisely as possible, not because their proponents are sure they are correct, but because an exact statement makes it easier for others to discover wherein they err and to improve them. It is in the spirit of this dialectic pro cess that the present theory is set forth in rigorous mathematical dress (in the sans-serif type) as well as by looser intuitive arguments. Colleagues have commented that Chapter 8, in which the previously developed abstract theory is applied in a case study of an actual linguistic construction (the English conditional), makes everything else coalesce and ought on all sound heuristic principles to come at the beginning. They agree, however, that logically it has to remain near the end because it treats of hypotheses which cannot even be stated precisely, let alone tested scientifically, FOREWORD xi without benefit of the preceding theoretical development. I think the advice they would have me convey to you is this: If the going gets uncomfortably abstract, don't give up until you reach Chapter 8, and if necessary skip to it. Many friends and colleagues influenced the ideas in this book and encouraged the writing of it. While I don't suppose they would go so far as to share the blame for it, still I'd like to mention some of them. Victor Yngve of the University of Chicago was kind enough to comment on the first draft. It was Professor Yngve who first stimulated my interest in scientific language study as early as 1958, and who several years later drew to my attention the possible significance of automata theory as a vehicle for serious pragmatic language investigations. Phyllis Baxendale, then at the !.B.M. Research Lab oratory in San Jose, made possible some early computer experimentation in an area of overlap between logic and linguistics. Don Swanson of the Univer sity of Chicago commented on an early draft, after having deaned into exist ence the favorable conditions which allowed it to be written. My indebted ness to Ernst Adams, particularly in the matter of if-then, should be obvious. I have also benefited from conversations on that topic with Brian Skyrms of the University of Illinois. M. E. Maron of the University of California at Berkely offered some valuable expository advice on the early chapters. Patrick Wilson of the same institution supplied specific criticisms and general encouragement in exquisitely balanced proportions. The exposition has also profited from a number of specific suggestions by J. L. Kuhns of Operating Systems, Inc. lowe much to Paul Huizinga of the University of California and Ian Carlstrom, now of Case Western Reserve University, for checking the mathematical proofs and in one instance suggesting a stronger theorem. I was assisted by the thoughtful commentary of the publisher's reviewer. I am also grateful for the extensive and very useful notes of another reviewer whose identity is unknown to me but is presumably known to him. Berkeley, April 1977 W.S.C.
Description: