ebook img

Distinguish to Unite or, Degrees of Knowledge PDF

494 Pages·1959·20.358 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Distinguish to Unite or, Degrees of Knowledge

DISTINGUISH TO UNITE OR The Degrees of Knowledge by JACQUES MARITAIN Newly translated from the fourth French edition under the supervision of GERALD B. PHELAN CHARLES SCRIBNER’S SONS NEW YORK BY JACQUES MARITAIN Reflections on America On The Philosophy of History A Preface to Metaphysics Existence and the Existent Ransoming the Time The Range of Reason Approaches to God True Humanism Freedom in the Modern World Christianity and Democracy The Rights of Man and Natural Law The Person and the Common Good Man and the State Education at the Crossroads Art and Scholasticism Art and Poetry Art and Faith Creative Intuition in Art and Poetry Prayer and Intelligence (in collaboration with Raissa Maritain) The Situation of Poetry (in collaboration with Raissa Maritain) The Social and Political Philosophy of Jacques Maritain (edited by Joseph W. Evans and Leo R. Ward) Copyright © 1959 Jacques Maritain This book published simultaneously in the United States of America and in Canada- Copyright under the Berne Convention All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form without the permission of Charles Scribner’s Sons. C-6.63[q] PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 59-12892 TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE Preface to the Original French Edition ix Foreword xvii I The Majesty and Poverty of Metaphysics i First Part: The Degrees of Rational Knowledge: Philosophy and Experimental Science II Philosophy and Experimental Science 21 i The Object of This Chapter Science in General Necessity and Contingency A Digression on “Determinism in Nature” Another Digression. How Do We Attain Essences? Sciences of. Explanation (In the Full Sense of the Word) and Sciences of Observation n The Degrees of Abstraction Table of the Sciences m Science and Philosophy Classifications on the Notion of Fact The Structures and Methods of the Principal Kinds of Know¬ ledge The Proper Conditions for Philosophy. Its Relation to Facts Knowledge of the Physico-Mathematical Type and Philosophy Knowledge of a Biological and Psychological Kind Conclusion Speculative Philosophy III Critical Realism 71 1 “Critical Realism” Scio aliquid esse n Realism and Common Sense Truth Thing and Object Digression on Phenomenology and the Cartesian Meditations Concerning Idealism m Concerning Knowledge Itself The Concept Idealistic Positions and Attempts at Reaction The Universe of Existence and the Universe of Intelligibility Being of Reason v VI CONTENTS IV Knowledge of Sensible Nature i The Main Types of Knowing Modern Physics Considered in its General Epistemological Type Real Being and Being of Reason in Physico-Mathematical Knowledge Ontological Explanation and Empiriological Explanation and Some Recastings of the Notion of Causality The New Physics A Digression on the Question of “Real Space” n The Philosophy of Nature Complementary Elucidations ui Mechanism Dangerous Liaisons Ontology and Empiriology in the Study of the Living Organism The Anti-Mechanist Reaction in Biology Concerning the True and the False Philosophy of the Progress of the Sciences in Modern Times V Metaphysical Knowledge i Dianoetic Intellection and Perinoetic Intellection Scholastic Digression The Human Intelligence and Corporeal Natures n The Metaphysical Intelligible The Metaphysical Transintelligible and Ananoetic Intellection in The Divine Names The Name of Person The Way of Knowing and the Way of Non-Knowing The Superanalogy of Faith Second Part: The Degrees of Suprarational Knowledge VI Mystical Experience and Philosophy i The Three Wisdoms n Sanctifying Grace The Indwelling of the Divine Persons in the Soul The Gifts of the Holy Ghost Knowledge by Connaturality Fides Illustrata Donis hi Transition to a Few Problems Is There an Authentic Mystical Experience in the Natural Order? First Objection Second Objection Third Objection Does Metaphysics of Itself Demand Mystical Experience? Natural Analogies of Mystical Experience Connections Between Metaphysics and Mysticism CONTENTS Vll VII Augustinian Wisdom 291 A Typical Problem The Gift of Wisdom Making Use of Discourse Platonic Reason and the Gifts of the Holy Ghost The Character of Augustine’s Doctrine Augustinism and Technical Differentiations Within Christian Thought Thomas Aquinas, Augustine’s Heir Thomism and Augustinism VIII St. John of the Cross, Practitioner of Contemplation 310 1 Communicable Knowledge and Incommunicable Knowledge n The Speculative Order and the Practical Order Practically Practical Science The Practical Science of Contemplation m The Meaning of Human Life Theological Faith rv The “Practicality” of St. John of the Cross’ Vocabulary The Doctrine of the Void v Mystical Contemplation Contemplative Purity and Poverty of Spirit IX Todo Y Nada y 352 Appendixes Appendix I: The Concept 3^7 Appendix II: On Analogy 4*8 Appendix III: “What God Is” 422 Appendix IV: On the Notion of Subsistence 430 Further Elucidations (1954) Appendix V: On a Work of Father Gardeil 445 Appendix VI: Some Clarifications 451 Appendix VII: “Speculative” and “Practical 45^ 1 On the Proper Mode of Moral Philosophy n General Remarks About the Speculative and the Practical Appendix VIII: “Le Amara Tanto Como es Amada” 465 Appendix IX: The “Cautelas” of St. John of the Cross 468 Index 471 PREFACE TO THE ORIGINAL FRENCH EDITION The title of this work1 suffices to declare its plan and purpose. To scatter and to confuse are both equally inimical to the nature of the mind. “No one, says Tauler, understands true distinction better than they who have entered into unity. ’ So, too, no one truly knows unity who does not also know distinction. Every attempt at metaphysical synthesis, especially when it deals with the complex riches of knowledge and of the mind, must dis- tinguish in order to unite. What is thus incumbent upon a reflexive and critical philosophy is above all to discriminate and discern the degrees of knowing, its organization and its internal differentiations. Idealism usually chooses a particular order of sciences as the univocal type of the world of knowing and constructs its whole philosophy of knowing with reference to that chosen type. Not only does it thus systematically neglect vast areas of knowledge but it also tends to reduce the diversities of the life of the mind to a noetic monism, more sterile, no doubt, and less excusable than the ontological monism of the first philosophers. (For, after all, the mind knows itself; and what excuse can idealism offer when it deceives itself about the very structures of thought?) In retaliation, many realists seem disposed to abandon the problems proper to the mind as the price they pay for the possession of things. And we are witnessing today a new cultural” dogmatic identifying the anti-idealism of which it makes profession with dialectical materialism. We hope to show in this book that Thomistic realism, in preserving, according to a truly critical method, the value of the knowledge of things, opens the way to an exploration of the world of reflection in its very inward¬ ness and to the establishment of its metaphysical topology, so to speak; thus, philosophy of being” is at once, and par excellence, “philosophy of mind.” The mind, even more so than the physical world and bodily organisms, possesses its own dimensions, its structure and internal hierarchy of causalities and values—immaterial though they be. Contemporary idealism, in the last analysis, refuses to recognize that mind has any nature or any structure. It sees it only as a pure movement, a pure freedom. Hence, it never really gets beyond spreading it out, whole and entire, upon a single plane of intellection, like a two-dimensional world, infinitely flat. One is, however, justified in thinking that the four dimensions of which St. Paul speaks “quae sit latitudo, 1 The French title of this book is: Distinguer pour unir, ou Les degrfa du savoir (tr.). ix * PREFACE et longitudo et sublimitas et profundum,”1 belong not only to the sphere (or super¬ sphere) of the contemplation of the saint, but, generally, to the fundamental organization and structure of the things of the mind, both in the natural and in the supernatural order. From the noetic point of view which we have adopted, let us say that “length” symbolizes for us the manner in which the formal light that char¬ acterizes a particular type of knowing falls upon things and defines in them a certain line of intelligibility: to “breadth” corresponds the ever-increasing number of objects thus known; to “height” corresponds the difference of level created among different sorts of knowing by the degrees of intelligibility and immateriality of the object and from which there follows for each difference of level an original and typical mode of procedure; as to the fourth dimen¬ sion, “depth,” it represents, in our view, those more hidden diversities which depend upon the manner in which the mind, in its freedom, still further diversifies its objects and its ways of conforming to the real,’according to its own proper finalities. The difference between speculative and practical philosophy offers the simplest example of such diversities, but it is not the only one. However, it is important to bring to light not only the structure, but also the movement and elan of the mind, as well as that admirable law of unsatis¬ factoriness, even in the security of acquired certitudes, in virtue of which the mind, starting with sense experience, enlarges, heightens and transforms its own life step by step by involving itself in diverse worlds of knowledge, heterogeneous, indeed, yet solidary, and by bearing witness that to tend towards infinite amplitude is, for an immaterial life, to tend towards an infinite object, an infinite reality which it must needs, in some way, possess. We have endeavoured to point out in this book the principal reasons and modalities of this movement and of those phases through which it passes. It is easy to see why this work must explore the most varied domains. After a sort of general introduction dealing with the question of the Grandeur and Misery of Metaphysics, the first problems to be treated will be those of the experimental sciences, and the degree of knowing which they represent. Before pressing on, it is necessary to turn our attention to knowledge itself and as such, and to establish (Ch. Ill) the principles of a philosophy of the intellect; there we shall cross the threshold of critical metaphysics and thence¬ forth keep to that point of view. The two following chapters will deal with the philosophy of nature considered notably in its relations with the sciences, particularly physics, and with metaphysical knowledge, especially in its noetic structure and in its relations to negative theology. When we come to knowledge by faith and the “superanalogy” proper to it, we shall rise to the super-rational degrees of knowing, whose highest form is mystical experience. 1 Eph. hi. 18. PREFACE XI Chapter VI is devoted to problems concerning mystical experience and Chapters VII and VIII consider two eminent cases involving what we have called above the “depth” of the things of the mind. Therein we shall inquire first, what is the nature of Augustinian wisdom?—and then, what are the distinctive features and the proper perspective of the “practico-practical” science of contemplation such as it is found in a St. John of the Cross? The last chapter forms the conclusion of the whole work. It deals with the doctrine of the “All and Nothing,” expounded by the same mystical Doctor, St. John of the Cross, and with the highest degree of knowledge and wisdom accessible to man in this life. We have purposely run through so vast a range of problems and sketched a synthesis (starting with the experience of the physicist and ending with the experience of the contemplative), the philosophical stability of which is guaranteed by the rational certitudes of metaphysics and critique. Only thus could we show the organic diversity and the essential compatibility of those zones of knowledge through which the mind passes in its great movement in quest of being, to which each one of us can contribute only tiny fragments, and that at the risk of misunderstanding the activity of comrades devoted to other enterprises equally fragmentary, the total unity of which, however, reconciles in the mind of the philosopher, almost in spite of themselves, brothers-in-arms who knew not one another. From this point of view it may also be said that the work which metaphysics is called upon to do today is to put an end to that kind of incompatibility of temper which the humanism of the classical age had created between science and wisdom. Some there are who will reproach us, no doubt, for not remaining through¬ out on the plane of pure philosophy and for having taken into account, in the second part of the present book, certitudes that depend upon lights of another order. We shall do nothing to turn aside that sort of reproach since we are convinced, in fact, that when a philosopher adopts as the object of his study, something which impinges upon the existential conditions of man and his activity as a free person—and that is just what happens when he studies those degrees of knowledge which are themselves beyond philosophy and imply, in their very essence, a personal relation of the knowing subject with his final end—he can proceed scientifically only if he respects the integrity of his object and, consequently, the integrity of those realities of the super¬ natural order which are, as a matter of fact, implied in it. We have explained our views on this point in an essay on the notion of Christian philosophy.1 No philosophical pretension can do away with the fact that man does not exist in the state of pure nature but in the state of fallen and redeemed nature. The first obligation of the philosopher is to recognize what is. And if, in some cases, he can only do so by adhering by faith to the First Truth—which, 1 Revue PUo-Scholastique de philosophie, Louvain, May 1932, pp. 178-180. See our De la philosophie critienne (Paris, 1933). As I have pointed out in an appendix to this little book, moral philosophy adequately understood is necessarily subordinate to theology. Xll PREFACE though it be reasonable to do so, is nevertheless due to a grace which tran¬ scends reason—he is still a philosopher (though not purely a philosopher) when he uses this very adherence to discern and examine the essential char¬ acteristics and the explicative reasons of what lies before his eyes. Then, although he borrows higher lights which he combines with those of reason, he carries through according to his own proper mode of procedure—not as a theologian but as a philosopher—analysing his data in order to rise to their ontological principles and integrating within his investigation of causes, points of information which he gets from the theologian, just as, on other occasions, he likewise integrates points of information that he gets from the biologist or the physicist. Whenever an unbeliever who reads these pages finds that he cannot grant the truth of the principles of solution which we have assumed, he can at least understand the methodological reasons which make it necessary to have recourse to those principles, and can judge from the outside, as it were, the logical structure of the whole which is presented to him. Moreover, many parts of this whole—to wit, all that deals with the degrees of rational knowing —rely on reason alone. And the doctrines of science which are here proposed, notably those which concern the physico-mathematical knowledge of nature, the philosophy of nature, the divine names and the rational knowledge of God, although they do not constitute the loftiest parts of that edifice, are yet its central parts, just as the doctrine of critical realism is its foundation. Let it be added that this work has not been conceived as a didactic treatise but rather as a meditation on certain themes linked together in a continuous movement. That is why certain degrees of knowing of major importance in themselves, such as mathematical knowledge and theological knowledge, have not been made the object of a special ^hapter, although we have not, therefore, refrained from considering and characterizing them. A special study, alien to the philosophical purpose we aim to pursue in this work, would be required for each of them. As far as the foundations of mathematics in particular are concerned, we are of the opinion that many preliminary studies are needed before Thomistic philosophy is in a position to propose a systematic interpretation in which all the critical problems raised by modem developments of the mathematical sciences may find solution. Nevertheless, we have tried on several occasions (Chs. II, IV, V) to give precision in this connection to a certain number of doctrinal points which appear to us to be of particular importance and which already indicate quite definitely, in what spirit, it seems to us, a philosophy of mathematics should be elaborated. Those who agree to read these pages attentively will, perhaps, notice that while we rigorously maintain the formal line of Thomistic metaphysics, rejecting any sort of compromise or watering-down designed to render Thomism acceptable to irrational prejudices, we have tried to clear the ground on several points and to push back the frontiers of the Thomistic synthesis.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.