CALCULUS An Intuitive and Physical Approach Morris Kline SECOND EDITION DOVER PUBLICATIONS, INC. Mineola, New York Copyright Copyright © 1967, 1977 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. All rights reserved. Bibliographical Note This Dover edition, first published in 1998, is an unabridged republication of the work originally published in 1977 by John Wiley and Sons, Inc., New York. Readers who would like to receive the solutions to the exercises may request them from the publisher at the following e-mail address: [email protected] Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Kline, Morris, 1908– Calculus : an intuitive and physical approach, second edition / Morris Kline. p. cm. “An unabridged republication of the work originally published in 1977 by John Wiley and Sons, Inc., New York”—T.p. verso. Includes index. ISBN-13: 978-0-486-40453-0 ISBN-10: 0-486-40453-6 1. Calculus. I. Title. 98-36211 QA303.K68 1998 CIP 515—dc21 Manufactured in the United States by Courier Corporation 40453609 www.doverpublications.com Dedicated to the memory of Morris Kline 1908–1992 Mathematician, Educator PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION The basic features of the first edition have been retained, such as the intuitive approach and real applications. As to the approach, the last chapter introduces a rigorous treatment. Though this chapter could be used in conjunction with the opening chapters of the book, I do not recommend doing so; the rigorous presentation is difficult to grasp and obscures the understanding. Rigor undoubtedly refines the intuition but does not supplant it. The rigorous approach should be reserved for a course in advanced calculus for mathematicians. Most of the applications still belong with the physical sciences; however, no knowledge of physics is presupposed. Several sections on physical applications have been dropped and applications to the social and biological sciences have been added instead. These applications are vital. The theory and technique of the calculus are, in themselves, meaningless. Moreover, since most students who take calculus will be scientists or engineers, they will be highly motivated by the applications. Many calculus texts dispose of applications by asking students to calculate centers of gravity and moments of inertia. But since students have no idea of how these quantities are used, the only consequence is that the gravity of the problems produces inertia in the students. In addition to extending the scope of the applications, I have made a number of other improvements. More drill exercises have been added, the exercises have been carefully graded as to difficulty, and there are more illustrative examples. Students doing homework exercises acquire the habit of searching for an illustrative example which they can imitate and thereby do the exercises without thinking. To counter this many illustrative examples are incorporated into the text instead of being set apart formally. Hopefully the students will read the text instead of mechanically following the technique of the usual illustrative example. A chapter on differential equations and a section on such numerical methods as Simpson’s rule and the trapezoidal rule have also been added. More use has been made of vector analysis, particularly in treating velocity and acceleration. Chapter 9, “The Definite Integral,” has been moved forward so that students using the mathematics in another course taken simultaneously can utilize the concept sooner. Some changes in notation are unquestionably an improvement. The notation has been restricted to the customary situation where time is the independent variable; in other situations y′, dy / dx and f′(x) are used. The notation ∫y dx has been introduced early to denote antidifferentiation. The use of dy / dx from the outset is the result of numerous requests. Admittedly, a useful notation in showing the variables involved, it also suggests that the derivative is a quotient, whereas we must take great pains to convince the student that it is not. The pace of the first few chapters has been speeded up somewhat. However, it does seem desirable, because students are weak in algebra, to keep the algebra simple at the outset while students are acquiring the concepts of the calculus. Two other changes may be helpful. Since not all classes go at the same pace or have the same objectives the two volumes of the first edition have been replaced by the present single volume. Thereby instructors are freer to choose the topics they deem most appropriate. Second, since time may not permit the inclusion of all the applications, those sections that can be omitted without disrupting the continuity have been starred. Some figures have been improved; where the precise shape is significant the computer has been employed to achieve accuracy. An instructor’s manual which contains full solutions of all the exercises, suggestions for teaching, and additional material for advanced students is available to instructors on request to the publisher. Morris Kline New York, N. Y. August, 1976 PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION Anyone who adds to the plethora of introductory calculus texts owes an explanation, if not an apology, to the mathematical community. I believe that an introductory course in the calculus should present the subject intuitively and should relate it as closely as possible to science. A text for such an approach is not available. In this book the justification of the theorems and techniques is consistently intuitive; that is, geometrical, physical, and heuristic arguments and generalizations from concrete cases are employed to convince. The approach is especially suitable for the calculus because the subject grew out of physical and geometrical problems. These problems tell us what functions we should take up, what concepts we want to formulate, and what techniques we should develop. In view of the fact that the human mind learns intuitively and that time does not permit both an intuitive and a rigorous presentation in elementary calculus, it seems to me that the approach adopted is the correct one. The intuitive approach is explained to the student so that he will know what kind of evidence is being used to support arguments. Thus he is told that a graph of a typical function may not represent all functions. On the other hand, he is also told that the elementary functions are well behaved except at isolated points and that he can usually trust his intuition. As he works with the ideas of the calculus, he will sharpen his intuition. If he continues with mathematics, he will learn the analytical foundations and proofs that guard against the failings of intuition. The use of an intuitive approach in the first treatment of a subject is not an innovation. Arithmetic is learned intuitively in elementary school and then the logic of it is learned gradually through the work in algebra. Geometry is learned intuitively in junior high school and then the formal deductive approach is presented in senior high school. A difficult subject such as the calculus, therefore, should certainly be introduced by an intuitive approach. This approach has many merits beyond that of being the only feasible one. Every pedagogue today champions discovery, but few teach it. How does one discover in mathematics? By thinking in physical and geometrical terms, by conjecturing or guessing, by formulating hypotheses and testing them, and by generalizing on specific cases. Physical problems that call for the creation of mathematics set the stage for discovery. That the intuitive approach may lead to errors is granted, but “truth emerges more readily from error than from confusion.” The student must be allowed to make mistakes, for if he makes no mistakes, he will not progress. After the basic material has been covered, the need for rigor is motivated, and the last two chapters of Part 2 of this book do offer an introduction to precise language and proof. These chapters are intended as a transition to advanced calculus. One alternative to an intuitive approach is a rigorous treatment. In my opinion, a rigorous first course in the calculus is ill advised for numerous reasons. First, it is too difficult for the students. Beginners are asked to learn a mass of concepts so subtle that they defied the best mathematicians for two hundred years. Even Cauchy, the founder of rigor, gave formulations that are crude compared to what the current rigorous presentations ask students to absorb. And Cauchy, despite his concern for rigor, missed the distinctions between continuity and differentiability and between convergence and uniform convergence. Before one can appreciate a precise formulation of a concept or theorem, he must know what idea is being formulated and what exceptions or pitfalls the wording is trying to avoid. Hence he must be able to call upon a wealth of experience acquired before tackling the rigorous formulation. Furthermore, having students master a polished deductive organization does not teach them how to think and how to do mathematics, for thinking and doing are not deductive processes. How can discovery take place when students are asked to work with ideas that are already overladen with sophistication and refinement? Finally, the rigorous approach is misleading. Because the introductory calculus course is the student’s first contact with higher mathematics, he obtains the impression that real mathematics is deductive and that good mathematicians think deductively. Rigor has its place in mathematics education. It is a check on the creations and it permits an aesthetic (as well as an anaesthetic) presentation. But it is also to some extent gilt on the lily and an interdiction against the inclusion of functions which rarely occur in practice and which must even be invented with Weierstrassian ingenuity. A rigorous first course in calculus reminds one of the words of Samuel Johnson; “I have found you an argument but I am not obliged to find you an understanding.” Even if the rigorous material is understood, its value is limited. As Henri Lebesgue pointed out: “Logic makes us reject certain arguments but it cannot make us believe any argument.” The reasons often given for a rigorous presentation—that students must learn what a real proof is or that students should not be asked to unlearn later what they have already been taught—are hollow. One cannot give the whole truth at once in any subject. Even we, as teachers, do not face the whole truth for, in fact, the whole question of what is rigorous in mathematics was never so much up in the air as it is now. At any rate, what may seem ideally right and efficient is pedagogically intolerable. There is also the alternative of compromising on rigor by offering precise definitions and proofs in some portions of the text and intuitive or pseudorigorous arguments in others. This alternative seems to me to have almost all of the disadvantages of a rigorous presentation and the additional one of confusing the student about what proof really is. The second essential respect in which this book differs from current ones is that the relationship of mathematics to science is taken seriously. The present trend to separate mathematics from science is tragic. There are chapters of mathematics that have value in and for themselves. However, the calculus divorced from applications is meaningless. We should also keep in mind that most of the students taking calculus will be scientists and engineers, and these students must learn how to use mathematics. But the step from mathematics to its applications is not simple and straightforward and it creates difficulties for the student from the time he is called upon to solve verbal problems in algebra. The mathematics courses fail to teach students how to formulate physical problems mathematically. The science and engineering courses, on the other hand, assume that students know how to translate physical problems into mathematical language and how to make satisfactory idealizations. The gap between mathematics and science instruction must be filled, and we can do so to our own advantage because thereby we give meaning and motivation to the calculus. In this book real problems are used to motivate the mathematics, and the latter, once developed, is applied to genuine physical problems—the magnificent, impressive, and even beautiful problems tendered by nature. I have selected those that do not require a background in physics. However, if the student is to think properly even about familiar concepts, such as weight, force, velocity, acceleration, light, and work, the book must say a little about them and about the physical laws that are involved. It does. To relegate physical problems only to the exercises is, in my opinion, ineffective in teaching students how to apply mathematics. If the student is not informed about the physics of a problem, all he can do in tackling an exercise is to apply a formula mechanically or guess what technical process is called for, do it, and check his answer. If the book does not supply an answer and if the student’s result is off by a factor of 1000, he will not realize it because he has no judgment about what to expect. I have tried to incorporate several other features that may contribute to the pedagogy. In many instances I have deliberately made false starts so as to have the student realize that correct methods and correct proofs are almost always preceded by groping and to have students appreciate why we finally take one course rather than another. I wish to dispel the impression that good mathematicians are able to proceed directly to the right conclusion because strict logic or a God-given insight guides them. I have given full details on the mathematical steps in the hope that the book will be readable. The style is informal. The pace of the first few chapters of Part 1 has been deliberately made slow. It is well known that calculus students are still struggling with elementary algebra. By keeping the opening algebra simple, I trust that the calculus ideas will stand forth. In later chapters the algebra becomes more difficult. The order of the mathematical concepts and topics was chosen so that applications could be introduced almost from the beginning. However, no artificial or complicated arrangement was necessary. Differentiation and antidifferentiation are the key concepts in the first thirteen chapters and then summation is introduced. The early introduction of applications should permit good correlation with physics courses if these are taken concurrently. The concept of differentials was deliberately delayed until Chapter 12 of Part 1. Most books do stress that the derivative is a limit of a quotient, but often present differentials early. No matter how much the student is cautioned that the derivative is not a quotient, if he is allowed to work almost at once with the quotient of the differentials, he tends to forget the true meaning of the derivative. Beyond the matter of the proper approach, there are a few other points that may warrant comment. Despite my own preference for a course in analytic geometry which precedes the calculus, I have included the former. This is a concession to the current fad. Some work with vectors is included, but I have not done much with the differentiation and integration of vector functions. I believe that this topic requires a new way of thinking and that we should not try to teach two major classes of techniques at the same time. The calculus of scalar functions is the basic one, and this should be mastered first. Apropos of the inclusion of vector analysis, the present trend to include this topic, linear