Artistic Judgement PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES SERIES VOLUME115 FoundedbyWilfridS.SellarsandKeithLehrer Editor StephenHetherington,TheUniversityofNewSouthWales,Sydney,Australia SeniorAdvisoryEditor KeithLehrer,UniversityofArizona,Tucson,AZ,U.S.A. AssociateEditor StewartCohen,ArizonaStateUniversity,Tempe,AZ,U.S.A. BoardofConsultingEditors LynneRudderBaker,UniversityofMassachusetts,Amherst,MAU.S.A. RaduBogdan,TulaneUniversity,NewOrleans,LA,U.S.A. MarianDavid,UniversityofNotreDame,NotreDame,IN,U.S.A. JohnM.Fischer,UniversityofCalifornia,Riverside,CA,U.S.A. AllanGibbard,UniversityofMichigan,AnnArbor,MI,U.S.A. DeniseMeyerson,MacquarieUniversity,NSW,Australia FrançoisRecanati,InstitutJean-Nicod,EHESS,Paris,France MarkSainsbury,UniversityofTexas,Austin,TX,U.S.A. StuartSilvers,ClemsonUniversity,Clemson,SC,U.S.A. BarrySmith,StateUniversityofNewYork,Buffalo,NY,U.S.A. NicholasD.Smith,Lewis&ClarkCollege,Portland,OR,U.S.A. LindaZagzebski,UniversityofOklahoma,Norman,OK,U.S.A. Forfurthervolumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6459 Graham McFee Artistic Judgement A Framework for Philosophical Aesthetics 123 GrahamMcFee VicarageRoad19 EastbourneBN208AS UnitedKingdom [email protected] ISBN978-94-007-0030-7 DOI10.1007/978-94-007-0031-4 SpringerDordrechtHeidelbergLondonNewYork ©SpringerScience+BusinessMediaB.V.2011 Nopartofthisworkmaybereproduced,storedinaretrievalsystem,ortransmittedinanyformorby anymeans,electronic,mechanical,photocopying,microfilming,recordingorotherwise,withoutwritten permissionfromthePublisher,withtheexceptionofanymaterialsuppliedspecificallyforthepurpose ofbeingenteredandexecutedonacomputersystem,forexclusiveusebythepurchaserofthework. Printedonacid-freepaper SpringerispartofSpringerScience+BusinessMedia(www.springer.com) Preface Preamble Asked by a colleague, some time ago, to set out my account of philosophical aes- thetics(and,associatedly,ofart),myfirstresponsewasthatIhadnosuchaccount: that any of my views was also held by someone else! But my colleague insisted that,onthecontrary,myviewsbothofaestheticsandofthenatureofartweredis- tinctive.Sodidthatdistinctivenessresideinthecombinationoftheseviewsonthe varioustopics,ratherthaninanyparticularviewofmine?Tounderstand,Iidentified andexploredeachofthese‘distinctivenesses’inturn.Thisexercise,first,prompted small-scale elaborations of specific issues: how did my institutional theory differ fromthosestandardlyoffered?Diditsuccumbtothesameobjections?Andsoon. Second,itproducedlarger-scaleexplorationsoftheextenttowhichthisaccountof philosophical aesthetics was illuminating (and perhaps even accurate). Issues here included the nature of truth, of rationality or of philosophy as much as aesthetic matters.SoIplannedabooktotakeallthesetopicsfurther.And,dearreader,you arenowlookingattheoutcome. Thistextpresentsapositionbothdistinctiveandpowerful.Atitsheart,theperva- sivenessoftheartistic/aestheticcontrastcombineswithmy‘take’onit.Inthisway, a framework for philosophical aesthetics is offered: that is, one for making sense of our appreciation and judgement of artworks of all kinds, and our appreciation and judgement of other objects inwhich wetake an interestexpressed intermsof grace,orline,orbeauty—ortheiropposites.Thisisaframeworkpartlyinoffering afairlyabstractpicture,whichwouldneedapplicationto,say,one’sconcernswith the aesthetics of dance (a special favourite of mine). Further, illustrative examples areofferedwheretheyseemtooccurnaturally. This picture of philosophical aesthetics rests on five main concerns, roughly reflectedbythechaptershere: (a) it insists on the importance of contrasting our judgement and appreciation of artworkswithallourotheraestheticjudgements; (b) itrecognizestheconnectionofartisticvaluetohumanlife,andexplainswhyno comprehensiveabstractaccountispossibleonthistopic; v vi Preface (c) itgivesanaccountofartwhichpermitscriticalcommentaryonartworkstobe true,partlybegivingdueweighttotheintentionsofartists; (d) ittreatsthosetruthsasmutableunderforcesinhistoryingeneralandespecially inthehistoryofart(whatIcall“thehistoricalcharacterofart”); (e) it stresses the role of practices of recognizing and appreciating art within a wider community and of presenting artworks to that community, as well as otherassociatedpracticessuchastherestoringofart:thatis,itoffersabroadly institutionalaccountofart. Inaddition,itdrawsonacontext-sensitiveaccountofunderstandingandmeaning: although this is sketched in broad terms in Chapter 2, its impact is felt through- outthetext.Evenfurtherback,adistinctiveviewofthenatureofthephilosophical enterpriseisbothexemplified and (occasionally) discussedhere:thatviewhasthe writings of Wittgenstein as its remote source and those of Gordon Baker as its proximateone. Readersmayhavethreemisplacedreactionstothistext,eachofwhichisnever- theless not without justification. Since they lead to ‘taking one’s eye off the ball’, theseobjectionsshouldbeforestalledhere.Thefirstisthatthisisallratherfamil- iar, just lining-up ‘the usual suspects’. This objection derives from the fact (noted above)that,inoneway,myviewiscompoundedoutofpositionssharedwithothers. Butthatfailstorecognizeitsfundamentaldistinctiveness(es).Centralamongthese is my radical version of the artistic/aesthetic contrast which, I insist, is (or should be)fundamentaltothinkinginphilosophicalaesthetics. Second,andrelated,theclaimthatthisisjustacollectionofviews—thatis,not asinglepositionbutamélange—warrantsthesamereply.Formyviewisrootedin theartistic/aestheticcontrast(and,ifmoreisneeded,intheconceptionofmeaning and understanding that sustains it); and, correspondingly, in my views of both the historicalcharacterandinstitutionalnatureofart. Third, some chapters might seem to bicker, having a structure based on “X said, Y said” (or, worse, “X said, I said”). Again, this objection cannot be fundamental here, not least because my focus involves addressing perplexities, meeting objections. Of course, there is some contrasting of views (and especially of my view with others) and some responding to what might seem like obvious objections—especiallywherethesewereexplicitlyraised.Yetthisisneversimply thecontrapositionofviews:whatsustainsthepresentationisthatitmovesthedis- cussionforwardbymeetingfundamentalobjections—again,thisprojectshouldbe obviousintherelevantpassages. Inoneway,thistextisaproductofmythinkingonaestheticsingeneralfromthe timeIenteredtheprofession(ifnotbefore).SinceIhavebeen thinkingaboutthis topic, in different ways, for the past 35 years, not all I would want to say is here; but,wherepossible,Ihaveofferedcross-referencestootherworks—oftenworksof mine—wherethepictureiselaborated. Further, I have refrained from proliferating examples, preferring instead to see howasmallishnumberofexamplesfareinthedifferentcontextsconstitutedbythe variousdiscussionsinthistext.Havingthissmallsetofcasesattheargumentative Preface vii heartoftheworkisanadvantage,aslongasitisrecognizedthat—farfromrepre- senting“anunbalanceddiet”,inwhich“onenourishesone’sthinkingwithonlyone kind of example” (PI §593)—the thinking derives for a generous consideration of cases,withany(apparent)narrownessconcerningclarityofpresentationonly. The selection of examples poses an further difficulty. For instance, I take the Alexandria Quartet to be one of the greatest books ever written in English (and, actually, one of the greatest punkt). And reference to Durrell occurs in my other works(forinstance,UD:182–183;189–190)aswellashere.Moreover,pointsare clearertomewhenIbelieveintheexamples.ButmyjudgementoftheAlexandria Quartet,say,cancloudthediscussion:myconsiderationsinphilosophicalaesthet- ics cannot depend on my being right about particular artworks. Of course, that discussion always needs exemplification with concrete cases: hence, conclusions concerning particular artworks must inevitably occur. One strategy, used to good effect in McFee, 1992a (UD), involves relying for exemplifications on the judge- mentofcritics.Anotherstrategy(fromthelastchapterofMcFee,1978)iswriting asacriticoneself.Butthenmyown‘take’ontheartworkscanseemeitherunder- ratedorover-ratedrespectively.Yetnothingturnsontheexamplesassuch,atleastif readerswhodisputethemcan(nevertheless)supplyexamplesoftheirowntomake similarpoints. Finally, it is a commitment of this work that its assertions answer perplexities (questions),andthatadifferentperplexity(question)canberaisedinthesameform of words (see Section 2.4). So no author can hope to address all the possible per- plexities in an area in all the detail the ‘perplexed’ might require. Hence, I have donemybest,focusingonthosequestionsraisedintheliteratureorindiscussion; andIhaveofferedsomethingtothosedifferently‘perplexed’,occasionallyinclud- ingreferencetootherworks(especiallyotherworksofmine)whereeitherasimilar position put in a different way might be found or a fuller version in roughly the sameway. Thisworkisself-contained,althoughdrawingonargumentssketchedelsewhere, and operating at a level of considerable generality in (typically) talking globally aboutthearts—whilerecognizingdifferencesamongthearts.But,inmythinking, this is also the first volume of a two-volume project, which (following the good advice of my wife Myrene) I call The Muscular Aesthetic. The second volume, should it appear, will be more concrete and—consonant with my interests—will haveaclearerfocusontheperformingarts,andespeciallydance. This, then, is the culmination of much of my thinking both in philosophical aesthetics and in philosophy more generally. In that sense, it is the PhD thesis I should have written, if I had seen matters that clearly then! Some of the ideas here were central to my actual PhD thesis, others were prefigured in early publi- cationsor(unpublished)presentationstoconferences.Inparticular,myadmiration forJohnWisdom’sversionof(broadly)Wittgensteinianthoughtmademeadvocate a case-by-case answer to very many difficulties, especially those in philosophical aesthetics.ItisconsolingtofindotherswhoseworkIadmire(forexample,Danto, 2000:132–133)nowrespondinginthisway.Butitmakesmewishthatsomeofthe detailsofmyideashadbecomemorewidelyknownatthetimeIformulatedthem. viii Preface SomeareinMcFee(1978):others,whichIhavebeenassertingfor20years,have noobviousanddefinitivepublishedhome. TextualAcknowledgements Much of the material here had an ‘earlier life’ in conference presentations and articles: I welcome the opportunity to integrate these materials, not all previously published(and,ifso,fullyrevised).Themajorpublishedpiecesare: • 1985:“WollheimandtheInstitutionalTheoryofArt”,PhilosophicalQuarterly, 35,139:179–185(mainlyinChapter6) • 1989: “The Logic of Appreciation in the Republic of Art”, British Journal of Aesthetics,29:230–238(inChapter6) • 1992b: “The Historical Character of Art: A Re-Appraisal” British Journal of Aesthetics,32,4:307–319(mainlyinChapter5) • 1995:“BacktotheFuture:AReplytoSharpe”BritishJournalofAesthetics,35, 3:278–283(inChapter5) • 2001a: “Wittgenstein, Performing Art and Action” in R. Allen & M. Turvey (eds.) Wittgenstein, Theory and the Arts. London: Routledge: 92–117 (mainly inChapter2) • 2004c:“WittgensteinandtheArts:UnderstandingandPerforming”,inP.Lewis (ed.) Wittgenstein, Aesthetics and Philosophy, Aldershot: Ashgate: 109–136 (in Chapters2and4) • 2005b:“Art,UnderstandingandHistoricalCharacter:AContributiontoAnalytic Aesthetics” in K. Mey (ed.) Art in the Making: Aesthetics, Historicity and Practice.NewYork:PeterLang:71–93(inChapter5) • 2005a: “The Artistic and the Aesthetic” British Journal of Aesthetics, 45: 368– 387 (Chapter 1 is a revised and expanded version, incorporating, in particular, materialpresentedatOxfordUniversity,May2005) • 2008:“The FriendsofJones’Paintings:ACaseofExplanation intheRepublic ofArt”ContemporaryAesthetics,6(inChapter6) Further,Chapter2minesmaterialfromSRV:47–52. OtherAcknowledgements Therearetoomanydebts(overtoolongatime)tomentioneveryonewho,through discussionorcorrespondence,hascontributedtomythinkinghere:tostandforall therest(herebythanked),Iwillmentionthefollowingspecialcontributions: • amongaestheticians,TerryDiffeyandNickMcAdoo,bothofwhomcommented indetailonanearlierdraft,aswellasthelateRichardWollheim(whosupervised thePhDthesisIdidwrite); Preface ix • among philosophers more generally, the late Gordon Baker, David Best, Katherine Morris, Charles Travis, the late John Wisdom; and also Brian Smart, whotaughtmefirst; • my wife, Myrene: who fulfils for me all the tasks Lawrence Durrell also requiredofawoman(“lover,intellectualcompanion,nurse,mother,cook,host- ess, manager, critic, typist, proofreader ...”: MacNiven, 1998: 555) and many more. IshouldalsoacknowledgetheUniversityofBrighton,forgivingmetimetowritea substantialfirstdraftoftheseideas(particularlytoPaulMcNaught-DavisandAlan Tomlinson);andespeciallytothosecolleaguesintheChelseaSchoolwhocovered myteachingandadministration.Further,Iwouldmentionthelesstangiblebutstill fundamentalsupportofmycolleaguesatCaliforniaStateUniversityFullerton.And, onceagain,thevillageofJoncelets,France. Abbreviations (a) formyownworks: McFee(1992a—“UD”) McFee(2000—“FW”) McFee(2004a—“SRV”) McFee([1994],2004b—“CDE”) McFee(2010a—“EKT”) (b) standardabbreviationsfortheworksofWittgenstein: Wittgenstein(1953—“PI”) Wittgenstein(1958—“BB”) Wittgenstein(1967—“Z”) Wittgenstein(1975—“PR”) Wittgenstein(1979—“WWK”)(basedontheGermantitle) Wittgenstein(1980—“CV”) Wittgenstein(1993—“PO”) Wittgenstein(2005—“BT”) [Other references to Wittgenstein use the standard enumeration of items from the Nachlass:seePO:480–510] Permissions ThankstoHenryHoltandCompanyLLCforpermissiontoincludethepoem“Fire and Ice” by Robert Frost, which appears in Chapter 4, from The Poetry of Rober FrosteditedbyEdwardConneryLatham.PublishedbyHenryHoltandCompany, LLC.1969.
Description: