Aristotle’s Modal Proofs The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 68 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, Princeton University RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln ROGER ARIEW, University of South Florida E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University PAUL HOFFMAN, University of California, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, Northwestern University, Evanston ALAIN DE LIBERA, Université de Genève JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Università degli Studi di genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Stanford University For other titles published in this series, go to www.springer.com/series/6608 Adriane Rini Aristotle’s Modal Proofs Prior Analytics A8 22 in Predicate Logic – 123 Dr.AdrianeRini MasseyUniversity Philosophy-HPC PrivateBag11-222 PalmerstonNorth NewZealand [email protected] ISBN978-94-007-0049-9 e-ISBN978-94-007-0050-5 DOI10.1007/978-94-007-0050-5 SpringerDordrechtHeidelbergLondonNewYork (cid:2)c SpringerScience+BusinessMediaB.V.2011 Nopartofthisworkmaybereproduced,storedinaretrievalsystem,ortransmittedinanyformorby anymeans,electronic,mechanical,photocopying,microfilming,recordingorotherwise,withoutwritten permissionfromthePublisher,withtheexceptionofanymaterialsuppliedspecificallyforthepurpose ofbeingenteredandexecutedonacomputersystem,forexclusiveusebythepurchaserofthework. Printedonacid-freepaper SpringerispartofSpringerScience+BusinessMedia(www.springer.com) ARISTOTLE’S MODAL PROOFS Prior Analytics A8–22 in Predicate Logic Acknowledgements ............................................... vi Introduction ...................................................... 1 Part I: Modern Methods for Ancient Logic Chapter 1 The Non-Modal Syllogistic: An. Pr. A1–7 ..... 11 Chapter 2 The Assertoric Syllogistic in LPC ............ 21 Chapter 3 A Realm of Darkness ..................... 32 Chapter 4 Technicolour Terms ...................... 39 Chapter 5 Representing the Modals .................. 45 Part II: Necessity in the Syllogistic: An. Pr. A8–12 Chapter 6 Syllogizing in Red: Trivializing the Modals .... 63 Chapter 7 First Figure Mixed Apodeictic Syllogisms ..... 72 Chapter 8 Modal Conversion in the Apodeictic Syllogistic . 79 Chapter 9 Against the Canonical Listings .............. 95 Chapter 10 Apodeictic Possibility .................... 106 Part III: Contingency in the Syllogistic: An. Pr. A13–22 Chapter 11 Contingency (A13, A14) .................. 119 Chapter 12 Realizing Possibilities .................... 135 Chapter 13 Barbara XQM .......................... 146 Chapter 14 First Figure X+Q (A15) .................. 157 Chapter 15 First Figure L+Q, Q+L (A16) .............. 169 Chapter 16 Contingency in the 2nd Figure (A17–19) ...... 180 Chapter 17 Contingency in the 3rd Figure (A20– 22 ) ...... 194 Chapter 18 Summary and Conclusion ................. 217 Appendix: The LPC Framework .................................... 232 Bibliography ................................................... 238 Index ......................................................... 241 v Acknowledgements This research is supported by the Marsden Fund Council from Government funding, administered by the Royal Society of New Zealand. And I thank especially Peter Gilberd and the Marsden team at the Royal Society for their encouragement and support for this research over the years. I am also grateful to VLAC (Vlaams Academisch Centrum) Centre for Advanced Studies of the Royal Flemish Academy of Belgium for Science and the Arts, which provided support while I was on leave during the final production of the manuscript. Thec hapters below carry through ona project begun in a serieso fa rticles( Rini 1995, 1996, 1998, 2000, 2003, 2007). There are two people without whose help and insight this book could not have been written: Robin Smith and Max Cresswell. Smith’s (1989) translation of the Prior Analytics and his extensive commentary on the syllogistic have helped to make Aristotle’s technical works more easily accessible and help to identify and isolate the stages, methods and problems that characterise the modal syllogistic. Cresswell kept reminding me of the importance of asking what logical point is being made in a portion of Aristotle’s text. I also thank an anonymous reader from Springer whose thoughtful comments and criticisms prompted substantial improvements in the manuscript. I am grateful to Helga Kocurek for English translations of passages from Ebert and Nortmann’s (2007) German translation and commentary on Aristotle’s Prior Analytics. Finally, I thank Springer’s editorial and production staff for their courteousness and helpfulness at all stages. Readers familiar with the literature on Aristotle’s Prior Analytics will appreciate the influence that earlier studies by Paul Thom, Ulrich Nortmann and others have had on my thinking. While we are not always agreed on our readings I am greatly in their debt. Note on the translations: Unless otherwise stated all translations from the Prior Analytics are from: Aristotle: Prior Analytics, translated with introduction and commentary by Robin Smith, ©1989 by Robin Smith. Reprinted by permission of Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. All rights reserved. vi Introduction Aristotle invented logic. He was the first to devise a way to study not just examples of human reasoning but the very patterns and structures of human reasoning. This invention is the subject of the early chapters of Aristotle’s Prior Analytics. Aristotle is keenly aware that he has created a new and useful tool – he himself sees his system of syllogistic as the foundation of all our scientific reasoning about the world, and he takes great care to show how the syllogistic can accommodate the kind of necessity and possibility that together form the basic building blocks of his science. But his exploration of syllogisms involving necessity and possibility is generally thought to cast a shadow over his otherwise brilliant innovation. Until recently the standard view of Aristotle’s syllogistic has been that it separates into two parts. First, there is the basic syllogistic set out in Prior Analytics A1–7, made up of fourteen argument forms. This was the traditional logic taught in universities right up until it was replaced by modern formal logic in then ineteenthc entury, andt hisb asics ystemo fs yllogisticis w hatto day is often called non-modal (or sometimes the assertoric) syllogistic.T herei sa c laritya nd simplicity to the non-modal syllogistic that is easy to see – and anyone who thinks logic is beautiful will likely find that beauty alive in Aristotle’s non-modal syllogistic too. By and large a modern reader can approach it with an easy familiarity. It looks in the main how we expect a logic to look. We can see what Aristotle is doing, and we can see why it is good. The second part is the modal syllogistic, Prior Analytics A8–22, in which Aristotle studies syllogisms about necessity and possibility. While the invention of the simple system of syllogistic logic – i.e., the non-modal syllogistic – is almost always rated as one of mankind’s greatest accomplishments, the modal syllogistic has been infamously labelled ‘a failure’, ‘incoherent’, ‘a realm of darkness’. This book is written in the conviction that whether or not the modal syllogistic is a realm of darkness is a question of logic. The Prior Analytics is after all a work of logic. That is why this must be a logic book. It is a logic book in the tradition of work by McCall (1963), Johnson (1989), Thomason (1993, 1997), Patterson (1995), Nortmann (1996), Thom (1996), Schmidt (2000), Malink (2006), and others, who offer formal modellings of Aristotle’s modal syllogistic. Many of those who produce a formal modelling for the modal syllogistic present a set of axioms or principles from which they derive as theorems formal representations of those and only those syllogisms that they consider Aristotle accepted, or ought to have accepted. But the modal syllogistic is more than just a list of valid forms. In it Aristotle tries to explain just why modal conclusions really do follow from modal premises. I have made it my project to present and evaluate his proof methods. I have tried to show that there is a simple logical structure to this part of the Analytics. The first and most noticeable respect in which the present work differs from many of these other modern interpretations is in the fact that it is concerned with a logical representation of the ways in which Aristotle himself tries to prove his modal syllogisms. A second respect in which the present work differs from others is that it uses standard predicate logic translations with only de re modality. The reason for preferring 11 INTRODUCTION predicate logic is philosophically important. Certainly, part of what I want to illustrate in the course of the following chapters is that when our project is interpreting Aristotle’s Prior Analytics A8–22, then we need something which gives a precise representation by formulae which have standard and well-understood meanings. The simplest way to achieve that, in my view, is to make use of modern modal predicate logic. Of the recent scholarly interpretations mentioned above, only Nortmann (1996) and Schmidt (2000) study Aristotle using modern modal predicate logic. But their interpretations include in addition to de re modals, also de dicto modals, and this saddles them with more sophisticated formal techniques than the present study requires. Perhaps most scholars who work on the subject will disagree with this predicate logic approach. Some resist it strongly. They object to the introduction of such powerful tools as the individual variable and all that it affords. And, to be sure, Aristotle does not have the individual variable and the associated combination of unrestricted quantifiers and truth-functional connectives. But because logicians and philosophers know how to interpret predicate logic this makes it an especially useful tool. Clearly it is a far more powerful tool than we want to attribute to Aristotle, but that is a different point altogether. Another major need in any interpretation of Aristotle’s syllogistic is close adherence to the text of the Prior Analytics. I have based my discussion on Smith’s (1989) translation, and I have consulted other translations and referred to the original Greek whenever this has seemed necessary. In fact the problems in interpreting An.Pr. A8–22 are primarily logical and philosophical, and are only peripherally illuminated by the nuances of Aristotle’s Greek. I have of course paid close attention to those cases where the Greek itself is vital. The question of adherence to the text takes another form also. There is a well-known need for an account of how Aristotle’s system of logic relates to the rest of his philosophy. A careful and conscientious scholar looks to identify and investigate links between individual parts of the Prior Analytics and other parts of Aristotle’s works. There is not anyone who disputes this – it is one of the big questions within Aristotle scholarship. We all want the links between the Prior Analytics and the rest explained, and eventually that must be done. But before we can study the links, we first need an account of what is going on in An.Pr. A8–22 – an account that deals with the modal syllogistic itself, that closely respects Aristotle’s textual discussion in those chapters. Whether we can relate the logic to other parts of Aristotle’s philosophy is an important consideration, but it should not be allowed to get in the way of the more basic project of explaining the modal syllogistic as it is set out in An.Pr. A8–22. One criticism of the ‘logical’ approach may be that it is going to distort Aristotle. Undoubtedly there is much truth in that. Predicate logic translations are one distortion. In this study I allow what might appear to be a second distortion: I distinguish different kinds of terms which I label ‘red’ and ‘green’. Red terms are terms like ‘horse’, ‘plant’ or ‘man’. They name things in virtue of features those things must 2