ebook img

aquinas on attachment, envy, and hatred in the summa theologica PDF

27 Pages·2007·0.24 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview aquinas on attachment, envy, and hatred in the summa theologica

BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 AQUINAS ON ATTACHMENT, ENVY, AND 2 HATRED IN THE SUMMA THEOLOGICA 3 4 5 Keith Green 6 7 8 9 10 ABSTRACT 11 ThisessayexaminesAquinas’sdiscussionsofhatredinSummaTheologica 12 I-II,Q.29andII-II,Q.34,inordertoretrieveanaccountofwhatcontempo- 13 rarytheoristsoftheemotionscallitscognitivecontents.InAquinas’sview, 14 hatredisconstitutedasapassionbyanarrativepatternthatincludesits 15 intentionalobject,beliefs,perceptionsofchangesinbodilystates,andmoti- 16 vateddesires.ThisessayendorsesAquinas’sbroadly“cognitivist”account of passional hatred, in line with his way of treating passions in general. 17 I suggest that Aquinas’s account of hatred’s arising out of attachment is 18 compelling.However,IalsoarguethatifAquinas’streatmentofhatredis 19 tohelpusunderstandthephenomenonofhate,whereclassesofpeopleare 20 abominatedforanidentitytheybear,andtoavoidequatinganoppressor’s 21 hatredwiththatoftheoppressedfortheoppressor,thecognitivepathway 22 tohatredmustbebroaderthanthroughenvy. 23 KEY WORDS: Attachment, envy, hatred, bigotry, passions, emotion, love, 24 Aquinas 25 26 1. Introduction 27 28 Evenwiththerevivalofphilosophicalinterestinemotionsandvirtues, 29 there are few philosophical discussions of hatred as such. A search of 30 the Philosophical Index turns up two articles in the last twenty-five 31 years, and only one book in which hatred or its relation to hate is a 32 significant theme.1 Although there is growing philosophical literature 33 on different forms of “hate” in civil discourse, these discussions of such 34 issues as racism, misogyny, and homophobia have not examined their 35 relationship to hatred as an emotion.2 We might well begin to address 36 37 1Thetwoarticlesinthelasttwodecadesofotherwiseprodigiousphilosophicalliterature 38 ontheemotionsareBen-Zeev1992andKolnai1998.ThebookisbyMurphyandHampton 39 1988.Thenatureandjustificationofretributivehatredanditsrelationshiptoforgiveness isanissueaddressedbyMurphyinotherwritings,andbyotherauthorsrespondingto 40 hisviews.However,thisconversationoccursinworkprimarilyfocusedonforgivenessand 41 punishmentandnotonthecharacterofhatredasapassionorvice. 42 2In current political speech and civil discourse, “hate” broadly refers to prejudicial 43 beliefs and actions that defame bearers of an abominated identity. I will use the term 44 “hatred,”bycontrast,todesignateanemotionalresponsethatabominatesitsobject,and generatesadesiretoharmorextirpatethatwhichcannotbeassuagedinanyotherway.Itis 45 46 JRE35.3:403–428.!C 2007JournalofReligiousEthics,Inc. BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 404 JournalofReligiousEthics 2 3 this deficit by taking an inventory of resources in our philosophical 4 traditions. 5 Inthisessay,Iproposetocontributetothisinventorybyreexamining 6 aspectsofthediscussionsofhatredinAquinas’sSummaTheologicaI-II, 7 Q.29andII-II,Q.34.3Hisviewofhatredismultilayered,andattheon- 8 tologicallevel,itnamestherepulsionthateveryfinitebeinghasforthat 9 whichharmsordestroysit.Inthissense,loveandhatreddonotreferto 10 “mentalevents”or“tokensofconsciousness”;theyrefertothetendency, 11 forexample,ofplantstogrownearwaterorindampsoil,orofanyanimal 12 tofleeitspredator.Iwillfocus,however,onAquinas’smoralpsychology 13 ofhatredasapassion,sinceonemightfindhis“phenomenology”ofpas- 14 sionalhatred—andhismoralappraisalofvicioushatred—compellingin 15 itsownrightasa“folkpsychology”ofhatred.4 Aquinas’sunderstanding 16 ofthehatredthatrisestothelevelof(human)experiencemustbeunder- 17 stoodintermsofhisoverallaccountofthepassions,shapedasitisbyhis 18 reading of Aristotle’s De Anima III.4, 10–13, and Rhetoric ii.2–12. The 19 theologicaldiscussionofhatredofpersonsasaviceinSTII-II,Q.34also 20 contributescriticaldetailstohisaccountofhatredasapassion,having 21 its etiology in attachment and envy. From these details we may derive 22 anintuitive,ifincomplete,sketchofwhatcontemporarytheoristsofthe 23 emotionswouldcallthecognitivecontentsofhatred.Myaimhereissim- 24 plytodelineatethissketch,asabeginningpointforbroaderdiscussion 25 of philosophical issues about hatred and its relation to hate. As such, 26 my aim is not Aquinas’s; I am not yet taking up moral and theological 27 questions,whicharehisprincipalconcerninSTII-II,Q.34. 28 I will argue that Aquinas’s grounding of hatred of persons in envy is 29 toonarrowasanaccountofthecognitivecontentsofhatredfelttoward 30 31 32 safetosaythatinpoliticalandcivildiscourse,andinsomepsychologicaldiscussions,hate 33 issimplytreatedessentiallyasanexpressionorextensionofhatred.Notableexamples include Robert J. Sternberg 2003 and the influential work of Gordon W. Allport (1954, 34 1979). 35 3AllcitationsofThomasAquinas’sSummaTheologicaarefromthecompleteEnglish 36 translationbytheFathersoftheEnglishDominicanProvince(1981). 37 4Boththeterms“phenomenology”and“folkpsychology”demandcomment,lestmyuse 38 ofthemsuggeststhatIthinkweshouldfindAquinas’sviewofhatredmerelyofantiquarian value.Iuse“phenomenology”torefertotheessentiallydescriptiveenterpriseoflocating 39 generalfeaturesoftheexperienceswhichhumans,aslanguage-usingsubjectsandagents, 40 describeinparticularlinguisticterms.Itanswersthequestion,askedforaspecificgroup 41 ofpersons(assubjects)definedbysharingalanguageofself-description,“whatiscalled 42 ‘hatred?’” Such an account is also “folk psychology” to the degree that it articulates a 43 “taxonomyofemotiontypesbasedonthemeaningascribedbythesubjecttothestimulus situation.”ThisdefinitionisthatofPaulE.Griffiths2003,11.Assuch,itisacriticalstepin 44 anytheoryofemotion,psychologicalorphilosophical,thoughnotalltheoristsagreeabout 45 thenatureofitssignificanceandvalue,andinparticular,whetheremotiontypescanonly 46 bedefinedintermsofsubjects’meanings. BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 AquinasonAttachment,Envy,andHatred 405 2 3 persons. However, I also show that he entertains a broader account of 4 thecognitivefeaturesofhatredofpersons.Boththetheologicalcontext 5 of his discussion and the cognitive parameters of passional hatred as 6 he delineates them suggest a much richer account. This account is not 7 in itself a critique of what Aquinas does say. Aquinas does not discuss 8 hatred of persons perceived to bear an abominated identity that seems 9 tojustifytreatingtheminwaysnotregardedasmorallypermissiblefor 10 persons in general.5 If passional hatred is a common constituent of all 11 formsofhate,orifwearetounderstandtheprimarymoralriskofhate 12 asthatitpredisposesagentstofeelandactuponhatredindiscriminately 13 forwholeclassesofpersons,thena“folkpsychology”ofhatredmusttake 14 accountofmuchbroaderpatternsofmeaning“ascribedbythesubjects” 15 of hatred to its “stimulus situations” (Griffiths 2003, 39). However, the 16 accountthatAquinasgivesofthesourcesofhatredinattachmentshows 17 that any meaningful psychological theory of hatred as an emotion—or 18 anyaccountofhatredasavice—requires,ifnotentails,anevaluationof 19 thelovesinvirtueofwhichthesubjectsofhatredhate.Itisthisfeatureof 20 Aquinas’streatmentthatpointsbeyondfolkpsychologytoameaningful 21 accountofhatredasamoralchallenge—anissuetobetakenupinfuture 22 workanddiscussions. 23 24 2. Hatred and Love: Aquinas’s Moral Psychology 25 of Hatred as a Passion 26 27 STI-II,Q.29addressestheontologyandmoralpsychologyofhatred 28 withinthecontextofasectionoftheSummaTheologicafundamentally 29 concerned with theological anthropology, and specifically with the pas- 30 sionsanddispositions.Hatredisanalyzedhereintermsofitsontological 31 andpsychologicalplacewithinnaturalhumanagencyandends.Itisalso 32 in this Question that Aquinas accounts for two critical senses in which 33 hatred is the “opposite” of love. This analysis immediately follows, and Q1 34 presupposes,histreatmentofloveasa“movementofthesenseappetite” 35 or as a “passion.” The model for Aquinas’s treatment of the passions in 36 general, and of love and hatred in particular, is that of Aristotle’s De 37 Anima III.9–13, and more generally of De Anima I.1, Rhetoric ii.3, and 38 NicomacheanEthicsII.5,III.6–7(seeJordan1986).Aquinasdefinesnat- Q2 39 uralloveandhatredintermsofthemovementofappetiteasfollows: 40 41 Now with regard to the natural appetite, it is evident, that just as each 42 thing is naturally attuned and adapted to that which is suitable to it, 43 wherein consists natural love; so it has a natural dissonance from that 44 45 5MyremarksreflectthedefinitionsofracismsandracialprejudiceinKwameAnthony 46 Appiah’s“Racisms”(Goldberg1990). BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 406 JournalofReligiousEthics 2 3 whichopposesanddestroysit;andthisisnaturalhatred.Sotherefore,in 4 the animal appetite, or in the intellectual appetite, love is a certain har- 5 mony of the appetite with that which is apprehended as suitable; while 6 hatred is dissonance of the appetite from that which is apprehended as repugnant and hurtful. Now, just as whatever is suitable, as such, bears 7 theaspectofthegood;sowhateverisrepugnant,assuch,bearstheaspect 8 ofevil.Andtherefore,justasgoodistheobjectoflove,soevilistheobject 9 ofhatred[STI-II,Q.29,A.1,responsio]. 10 11 Itispartoftheorderofcreation,theorderofeternallaw,thateveryfinite 12 being “tends” to that which is conducive to its survival and flourishing, 13 and repels or avoids those things that harm or are inimical to its flour- 14 ishing. At the most basic level, the appetites are the form in animate 15 creaturesofthisbasicontologicalaffinitythatanythinghastowardthat 16 which sustains it as the kind of thing it is, and a repulsion toward that 17 whichharmsit.Invirtueofappetitus,whichincludesboth“beingmoved 18 toward” and “being averted from” objects that either are conducive or 19 inimicaltothesubject’sgood,subjectsareacteduponbyobjectsoutside 20 of them in accord with eternal law.6 Appetites in animals, furthermore, 21 consist partly of a “passive, sensible” component (complacentia) that is 22 “naturallymovedbythethingapprehended.”Ananimalappetiteis“pas- 23 sive”inthatitmustbe“moved”orbeanobjectperceivedbythesubject. 24 However,anappetitealsoincludesasacomponentanactive“movement,” 25 whichisaconsequentdesirethatmovesthecreaturewithrespecttowhat 26 itperceives(seeCrowe1959).Aquinasthenemploysfundamentaltech- 27 nicalnotionsofnaturaland“animal”appetiteandacriticaldistinction, 28 which he discusses in ST I, Q. 80 A.2, between “sensible” and “intellec- 29 tual”appetitetoaccountfortheessentialnatureandcomplementarityof 30 loveandhatred.ThroughoutSTI,Q.81,Aquinasspeaksofthefunction 31 ofappetitesasamovement,andexplainswhythisissoinSTI,Q.81,A. 32 2.Insensingandinformingbeliefsandsubsequentdesiresaboutwhat 33 oneperceives,thesubjectismovedtowardobjectsofdesireandaverted 34 fromobjectsperceivedasanevil.7 35 In rational creatures with a capacity for the formation of beliefs and 36 for deliberation, however, the natural animal appetite also includes a 37 “superior inclination” that involves a further element of judgment and 38 intention. Though the movement of appetites that is characteristic of 39 all animals is also present in rational animals, the appetites of ratio- 40 nal animals are moved by objects that are apprehended as the inten- 41 tional objects of perception and belief. Passions in rational animals are 42 43 6See Harak 1993 for his especially helpful treatment of appetitus and of the self as 44 “movedmover”(96–98),aswellashisdiscussionofthecausesofpassions(81–84). 45 7ForaclearandbasictreatmentofSTI,Q.80–81ontheappetites,seeBaker1941, 46 Harak1993. BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 AquinasonAttachment,Envy,andHatred 407 2 3 “cognitive” in the sense that they are “mental events”: this is what it 4 means to say that objects of passion are “apprehended.”8 In contempo- 5 rary philosophical language, a “passion” as Aquinas understands it is 6 a complex mental event or “extended mental episode” that necessarily 7 involvestheformationofbeliefsaboutaperceivedobjectandanensuing 8 pattern of affect or bodily change and motivated desire. Two words of 9 caution are in order here. First, “passion” or “a passion” cannot be re- 10 duced to any one of these elements and is not to be flatly assimilated 11 to a modern notion of “emotion” or “an emotion.”9 Second, the desires 12 thatariseinpassionarenottobeassociatedwith“will”assuch.Noting 13 that passion is often “felt” but not acted upon, Aquinas’s way of mak- 14 ing sense of this feature of passion is to associate “will” with “choice” 15 (electio).Thus,infeelinghatred,onemay“feel”themotivation,orhave 16 the desire, to attack and destroy another, but may choose not to do so. 17 If one unself-consciously acts upon the desires motivated by a passion, 18 then(perhapsthroughpoorhabituation),one’s“reason”issimplymoved 19 bypassion:thiswouldbeaninstanceofintemperance.Yetonemay“self- 20 consciously”eitherchooseorchoosenottoactuponthedesiresthatmay 21 quiteinvoluntarilyariseinsofarasoneisthesubjectofpassion.10 Ifone 22 23 8Jordan (1986, 88) helpfully comments on the distinction between intellectual and 24 sensitiveappetite(withspecificreferencetoSTI,Q.81,A.1,sedcontraandresponsio) 25 that“oneislikerest,theotherlikemotion”and,“Asthephysicalanalogiesmakeclear, 26 thisdistinctionoughtnottobereifiedasadistinctionbetweentwofaculties,muchless 27 twoentities.” 28 9In ST I-II, Q. 24, A. 2, responsio, Aquinas refuses the Stoic view that passions are “interruptions”ofreason’scontrolinconsciousexperience,andtherebytoberegardedas 29 “diseases” of the soul. He sides with the Aristotelian-Peripatetic that passion is an in- 30 terruptionofreason’scontrolonlyifitisbadlyhabituated.Alsonotehisendorsementof 31 Augustine’srefusalofCicero’scalling“whattheGreekscallpathe”“disturbances”inST 32 I-II,Q.22,A.2,sedcontra.Histreatmentofspecificpassions,furthermore,identifiesthem 33 withtheformationofspecificsortsofbeliefsaboutcertainkindsorcategoriesofobjects: hencethebeliefthatsomeonehas“slightedone’sexcellence”isnotonlya“constantlycon- 34 joined”preconditionofanger,butpartofit,asisthedesirethatitmotivatestoinflictpain 35 orharmuponitsobjectinproportiontothestandardsofretributivejustice.Onthedistinc- 36 tionbetween“passion”and“emotion,”andtheevolutionofmodernnotionsof“emotion” 37 fromearliernotionsofpassion,seeAme´lieO.Rorty1982and1993,andspecificallyher Q3 38 claimthatsentimentsarethedescendentsofstoicepithumeiaiandemotions,especially astheyaredefinedinthetraditionoftheorizingemotionsassociatedwithHumeandthe 39 James-Langeschool,thedescendentsofthekatalepticimpression.OntheStoicnotionof 40 passionsaskatalepsis,seeNussbaum1990,263–67,esp.265,n.7.SeealsoAquinas’sclaim 41 thatpassionsare“properlytobefound”inthesensitiveasopposedtotheintellectualap- 42 petite because they involve “corporeal transmutation” in ST I-II, Q. 22, A. 3, responsio. 43 Nonetheless,thepassionisnotmerelythisfeltbodilychange. 10Amorefruitfulwaytounderstand“will”inAquinas’sthoughtwouldbetoequate 44 it, in modern moral psychology, with the capacity to form what Harry Frankfurt calls 45 “second-ordervolitions.”SeeFrankfurt’s“Freedomofthewillandtheconceptofaperson” 46 and“Identificationandexternality”(1988),especiallyhiscommentsontheverb,“towant” BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 408 JournalofReligiousEthics 2 3 choosestoactonpassion-motivateddesiresbeyondthecounselsofpru- 4 dence,thenthiswouldbeaninstanceofincontinenceormalice.11 5 In Aquinas’s refinement of a basic Aristotelian psychology of the 6 sensible appetite, he identifies two “powers” (ST I-I, Q. 80, A. 3, sed 7 contra and responsio): a “concupiscible” power wherein “corruptible 8 things” need and have an inclination to acquire what is required for 9 survivalandflourishing,“accordingtothesenses,andasitsnaturepre- 10 disposesit”;andan“irascible”onewheretheyresistthatwhichinflicts 11 harm and hinders acquisition of what is needed (“suitable”). In ST I-II, 12 Q.23,A.1,2,Aquinasdiscusseshowitisthatintherationalpsycheof 13 humans,passionslikeallformsofloveandhatred,desire,sexualdesire, 14 hunger,andthirstareformsofthefirstpower—beingmovedtoattach- 15 ment. Anger, courage, shame, grief, and other psychologically natural 16 and fundamental emotions are, however, forms of the second power— 17 beingmovedtoresistimpedimentstoattachment.Specificpassions,fur- 18 thermore,are(accordingtoSTI-II,Q.23,A.4,responsio)differentiated 19 “inaccordancewiththeiractivecauses,whichinthecasesofthepassions 20 ofthesoul,aretheirobjects,”andnotby“howtheyfeel”tothesubject.12 21 According to Aquinas, any token experience of any specific passion is 22 what contemporary philosophers of mind would call a “complex mental 23 episode.” Any such experience involves a three-stage movement: (i) an 24 “aptitude to tend” toward or away from the mover or intentional object 25 (love and hatred); (ii) depending upon whether the loved or hated ob- 26 jectisnotyetpossessedorextirpated,amovementtowardorawayfrom 27 the object (desire or aversion); and (iii) the stage when the subject be- 28 lieves either that the object is possessed (or the subject “rests” in it) or 29 thatshewillneverpossessit(joyorsorrow).13Hatredatthislevelmoves 30 31 32 (13–14),hisdefinitionsof“second-ordervolition”(16),andhisdiscussionofwhena“pas- 33 sion” may be said to be “external” to “self ” or “internal” to the degree that an agent “identifies” with it through the formation of a second-order volition to “endorse” or fail 34 to“endorse”apassionvolitionally(62–63).Theonesense,however,inwhichFrankfurt’s 35 viewmustnotbeassimilatedtoAquinas’sisthatthephenomenaFrankfurtdescribeshe 36 takesasanegotiationoftheboundariesofthe“self,”whereforAquinas,itdescribesthe 37 dynamicinterrelationshipoftwodimensionsof“self”—passionandwill.SeealsoBowlin’s Q4 38 discussionofspeciesofinconstancyinAquinas(1999,42–46) 11Bowlin’sdiscussionofthedifferentformsofincontinence,thevirtues,and“steadfast- 39 ness”isextremelyhelpfulhere(1999,28,45).SeealsoYearley’sremarksaboutreason’s 40 controlofthevirtuesas“political”(1990,82–83).Onmalice,seeYearley1990,86–87,but 41 alsoBowlin1999,49n.33. 42 12ST I-II, Q. 23, A. 4, responsio: Different passions “differ in accordance with their 43 activecauses,whichinthecaseofthepassionsofthesoul,aretheirobjects.”Thispassage andoneother(STI-II,Q.60,A.5,responsio)identifywhatindividuatesspecificpassions 44 ofthesoul—activecausesandobjects. 45 13The movement of the irascible passions presupposes their objects already being 46 “found”goodorevil(beinglovedorhated).The“aptitude”to“seekgood”or“shunevil,” BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 AquinasonAttachment,Envy,andHatred 409 2 3 beyondbeingmerelyanaturalrepulsionfromthatwhichharmstobeing 4 a passion that presupposes beliefs about the relation of certain objects 5 ofconsciousnesstoagoodalreadyloved.14 6 In rationally willful animals, the concupiscible and irascible powers 7 “obey” reason both in its “estimative” and calculating (means to ends) 8 function (Yearley 1990, 75). The sensible appetite does not apprehend 9 “the universal”; it does not in itself encounter objects as particular ex- 10 amplesofkindsorclassesofobjectsthatmayhavearelativelyconsistent 11 relationtofulfillingorimpedingdesireandneed,ortocausingpleasure 12 andpain.Thoughthesensibleappetiteapprehendsobjectsasdesirable 13 or undesirable, and as painful or pleasurable, having beliefs about the 14 goodness or evil of anything represents a further abstract function of 15 reasonbeyondthesensitiveappetite.Aquinassaysthatitisthroughthe 16 intellectual appetite, “through which the animal is able to desire what 17 it apprehends, and not only that to which it is inclined by its natural 18 form”(STI-I,Q.80,A.1,2,sedcontraandresponsioofboth).“Havinga 19 feeling”aboutsomethingpresupposesimplicitlyseeingitasaninstance 20 of a particular kind of thing; and this “seeing as” is reason functioning 21 inwhatAquinascallsreason’s“estimative”role. 22 23 wheretheobjectisnotyetenjoyedorextirpated,motivateshopeordespair(iftheobject 24 isloved),fearordaring(iftheobjectishatedorregardedwithaversion),oranger(ifpos- 25 session or enjoyment of a good already possessed is disregarded and threatened by the 26 intentionalactionsofanagent).SeeSTI-II,Q.23,A.4,responsio.Thisthree-stagetax- 27 onomyofthepassionsAquinastakesfromAugustine’sCityofGodXIV.7.Goodintuitive 28 discussionsofthedistinctionbetweentheconcupiscentandresistive(irascible)passions, andassociatedvirtuesarefoundinBowlin1999,33–35andHarak1993,75,76. 29 14ItremainsanopenquestionwhetherAquinasregardsallformsofloveandhatred 30 aspassions.OneanonymousreaderarguesthatAquinasadmitsinSTI-II,Q.26,A.2, 31 3thatnotallformsorinstancesoflove(and,therefore,ofhatred)areformsofpassion. 32 Idonotfindthisreadingconvincing.ThisreadingmayrefertoAquinas’sclaim(Q.26, 33 A.2,endofresponsio)that“loveisapassion,properlysocalled,accordingasitisinthe concupisciblefaculty;inawiderandextendedsenseasitisinthewill.”This“widerand 34 extendedsense”isevidentlythatcapturedinthenotionof“dilection”(diligere),which(in 35 Q.26,A.3,responsio)Aquinassays“implies,inadditiontolove,achoice(electionem)made 36 beforehand,astheveryworddenotes:andthereforeisnotintheconcupisciblepowerbut 37 inthewill,andonlyintherationalnature.”Yetintherepliestoobjections3and4(Q.26, 38 A.3),hestatesthatloveisintheconcupisciblepassionandthatit“denotesapassion.”In repliestoobjections1,2,and3,itisbecausedilection(regard)involveschoiceandisin 39 theintellectualappetite,thatloveanddilectionare“thesame”intheintellectualappetite. 40 Aquinas’sownlanguageheresuggests,however,thatlovecanrefertoastateofthewill 41 becausethewillchoosespassion’sobject,orviceversa.Ineithercase,theconcupiscible 42 facultyis“moved,”andmaybe“endorsed”bythewillwithoutits“overpowering”thewill. 43 See ST I-II, Q. 10, responsio. To insist that because “diligere” is a form of love and is notinthesensitiveappetite,itisaspeciesoflovethatisnotpassional,however,reifies 44 thedistinctionbetweensensitiveandintellectualappetiteintotwofacultiesinawaythat 45 conflictswiththekindsofmetaphors(restandmotion)thatsuggestAquinasregardsthese 46 astwo“moments”ofasingle“power.”SeeJordan1986,88. BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 410 JournalofReligiousEthics 2 3 Hatred,likeloveasdesire,issubsequentlyshapedbythefunctioning 4 of reason in its apprehension of the “universal,” as it grasps abstract 5 properties that give classes of objects a more or less consistent rela- 6 tionship over time to human desires and interests. So, beyond and out 7 of the spontaneous aversive responses of “natural hatred” arise a vari- 8 etyofgeneralizedhatreds.Theseformsofhatredpresupposearational 9 “estimate”ofwholeclassesandcategoriesofobjects,relativetotheways 10 inwhichtheytendtoeffectpain,pleasure,thefulfillmentofdesire,and, 11 more generally, to effect realization of human interests. Hatred in this 12 senseisthecontraryofloveasamor,orasdesireforwhatisapprehended 13 aspleasurableandultimatelybelievedinsomesensetobe“good.”Fur- 14 thermore, the hating and loving response becomes predispositional as 15 agents form more or less settled conceptions of what is good or evil, 16 and affective response becomes attuned through habituation to objects 17 encounteredunderreason’sapprehension.Overtime,agentscometore- 18 spondwithmoreorlessspontaneoushatred(orlove,oranger,orshame, 19 orfear,orgrief,andthelike)toobjectsasinstancesofclassesandkinds 20 about which they have already formed beliefs. Habituation also shapes 21 theabilityofagentstoexercisevoluntaryendorsementorrestraint(will) 22 with respect to desire motivated by passion. Habituated and intersub- 23 jective ways of perceiving (seeing as) are reflected in the formation of 24 more or less settled evaluative beliefs about what is good and evil; and 25 thestrengthorweaknessofwillandhabituatedcapacitytochoosewith 26 respect to desires motivated by passion determine the degree to which, 27 andwaysinwhich,passionisreflectedinaction.15 28 Aquinas’s remarks about hatred in ST I-II, Q. 29, A. 2 foreground 29 five critical implications of his overarching, Aristotelian psychology of 30 the appetites and passions. (1) “Natural hatred” is a prereflective, and 31 evenpreconscious“naturaldissonance.”Itsimplynamesthefundamen- 32 talaversionorrepellingmovementofanythingawayfromthatwhichis 33 inimicaltoitsgood.Atthisontologicallevel,hatredandlovearesymmet- 34 ricalopposites;thoughwewillseethatthisdoesnotimplyany“higher” 35 symmetry of value or etiology between them. (2) For all animals, in- 36 cluding rational animals, natural hatred takes the form of a primitive, 37 prerational feature of the psyche, and is an ingredient in all specific, 38 sensible appetites that avert from that which is inimical to its good. 39 (3) In rational animals, “passional hatred” is intentional and cognitive. 40 Itisaboutanintentionalobjectpresentintheconsciousnessofthesub- 41 ject who feels hatred. To feel it is necessarily to be in a cognitive state 42 involvingbothperceptionandbeliefformation.(4)Inanimals,rationalor 43 otherwise,hatredisaformofconcupiscence.Insomefundamentalsense, 44 45 15I am indebted here, and commend the reader to, the discussion of habituation in 46 Nelson1992,72–73. BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 AquinasonAttachment,Envy,andHatred 411 2 3 itisthesamekindofthingthatloveis,andislogicallyandphenomeno- 4 logicallyanecessaryconcomitantofloveatthelevelofamorordesire.At 5 this level, it follows natural hatred in that it is a directionally opposite 6 concupiscent “movement” from love as such. (5) Its presence precedes, 7 andisanecessaryconditionfor,theformationofconceptionsofgoodand 8 evil,aswellasallhabitsthatpredisposeaffect,andthedegreetowhich 9 it is acted upon. For humans, immediate and nonreflective aversions 10 are shaped through experience and reflection into phenomenologically 11 diverseformsofpassionalhatred. 12 Inamorecontemporaryphilosophicalidiom,Aquinasbroadlyunder- 13 standshatred,likeotherpassionssuchasanger,fear,shame,grief,and 14 the like to presuppose intentionality and cognition as necessary condi- 15 tions for “feeling” passion. The identity of any passion to which one is 16 subjectisaninstanceofatypeidentifiedbyaprototypicallinkingofspe- 17 cificbeliefsaboutaspecificobjecthavingcertainpropertiesinvirtueof 18 whichcertainmotivateddesiresoccur.Aquinas’saccountofhatred,and 19 ofpassioningeneral,however,isnotapurelycognitivetheory.16Passions 20 are not merely cognitions; that is to say, they are not fundamentally to 21 beequatedwiththeevaluativejudgmentstheypresupposeasnecessary 22 conditionsanddefinitivecomponents.Theyarecognitivelydefinedand 23 directed forms of deeper ontological and psychic “drives.” We may ex- 24 trapolate from Aquinas’s remarks about emotions such as anger, fear, 25 and love among others, that “feeling” may characterize the subjective 26 experienceofsomeemotions,andthatitcanonlybedischargedandas- 27 suagedthroughspecificcoursesofaction,achievingspecificintentional 28 ends.17 Hatred is identified in the experience of subjects phenomeno- 29 logically, and defined logically, by what Ronald de Sousa calls a formal 30 object and by an immanent teleology.18 Feeling a specific passion im- 31 plicitly attributes some property to its objective target, and motivates 32 aconsistentlyidentifiablearrayofdesires.Thoughthesedesiresdonot 33 have to be acted upon, as will typically be the case with nonrational 34 35 16Cognitive theories of the emotions consider emotions to be a certain kind of judg- 36 mentwithpropositionalcontent,andnotmerelytobedifferentiatedinexperiencebythat 37 content.Solomon1976andNussbaum2001arenotableexamplesofsuchviews.Seespecif- 38 icallyNussbaum’sargumentthatemotionsessentiallyare“judgmentsofvalue.” 17ForindirectevidencethatAquinasregardsakindofsubjective,experiencedinternal 39 sensation as at least a defining characteristic of some passions in experience, note his 40 remarkabouthatredbeing“morekeenlyfelt”thanloveinSTI-II,Q.29,A.3,sedcontra 41 andhisremarkinSTI-II,Q.46,A.6(“OnAnger,”andspecifically,“WhetherAngerisMore 42 GrievousthanHatred”)that,“Astotheintensityofthedesire,angerexcludesmercymore 43 thanhatreddoes;becausethemovementofangerismoreimpetuous,throughtheheating ofthebile.” 44 18RonalddeSousa1987,TheRationalityofEmotion.Seeforbrevity’ssaketheappendix 45 oflabeledsentencesandprinciples,335–37.IamalsotakingforgranteddeSousa’stypology 46 ofphilosophicaltheoriesoftheemotions,36–46. BL063/JORE jore˙313 June10,2007 16:42 1 412 JournalofReligiousEthics 2 3 animals(andare,therefore,no“partof”thepassion),actingsuccessfully 4 upon them typically “discharges” and assuages the feeling as a bodily 5 condition. 6 Hatred’s target also has to be perceived as having some property in 7 orderforthefeelingofhatredtoariseasaresponse,andforthefeeling 8 response to be identified as hatred. That response will have to be one 9 thatcanonlybeassuagedbythedestructionorannihilationofthetarget 10 towardwhichonefeelsit.Aquinas’stheoryofhatredrequires,therefore, 11 a further account of its defining formal objects. What kinds of things 12 are hated? What beliefs about those things lead one to feel hatred for 13 them? How is feeling hatred different in experience from feeling anger 14 or jealousy, which also motivates one to cause harm to another? When, 15 ifever,isonejustifiedinfeelinghatred,orinbeingpredisposedtofeelit 16 spontaneously? Answers to each of these questions are presupposed in 17 Aquinas’ssubsequentaccountofwhathatredisvicious,andhowvicious 18 itis(orisnot). 19 20 3. Passional Hatred 21 22 Four entailments of Aquinas’s placing of natural hatred in ontology 23 andmoralpsychologywillhaveparticularforceinhisaccountofhatred 24 ofpersonsanditsmoralstatus.AfirstcriticalaspectofAquinas’sviewis 25 thathatredassuchis“natural”andcannotbeintrinsicallyevil.Indeed, 26 it is a necessary condition for survival and flourishing in the lives and 27 experienceoffinitecreatureswhoarevulnerabletopotentialharmfrom 28 wholeclassesofthings.However,whetherhatredperformsthisnatural 29 function will depend upon how prereflective aversions are attuned and 30 proportionedtoappropriatecircumstancesbyhabituationandlearning. 31 AsecondcriticalaspectofAquinas’smoralpsychologyofhatredisthe 32 locationofhatredwithintheconcupiscibleratherthantheirascibleside 33 of sensible appetite. Since anger is a form of the latter, hatred, even as 34 a more complexly developed part of character, is not a form of anger. 35 Here,AquinassideswithAristotleandhisperipateticheirsagainstthe 36 impressionoftheStoicsandtheirmodernheirsthathatredismerelya 37 developedfinalstageandformofanger. 38 InSTI-II,Q.29,A.6,AquinasendorsesAristotle’sview(Rhetoricii.4) 39 that anger is always directed to “something singular” whereas hatred 40 can be directed to a thing in general. The context of this endorsement 41 suggests that Aquinas thinks that anger is felt toward specific actions 42 ofspecificagents—actionsencounteredasslightingsofone’sexcellence. 43 However,preciselybecausewholeclassesofobjectsandpersonscanhave 44 aconsistentrelationshiptospecificwantsandinterests,hatred,bycon- 45 trast, may have whole classes or general kinds as its object. Aquinas’s 46 example is the enmity felt by sheep for wolves. In ST II-II, Q. 34, A. 6,

Description:
KEY WORDS: Attachment, envy, hatred, bigotry, passions, emotion, love,. Aquinas .. He sides with the Aristotelian-Peripatetic that passion is an in- terruption .. In a more contemporary philosophical idiom, Aquinas broadly under-.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.