ebook img

Analyses of Aristotle PDF

243 Pages·2004·1.27 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Analyses of Aristotle

ANALYSES OF ARISTOTLE JAAKKO HINTIKKA SELECTED PAPERS VOLUME6 1. Ludwig Wittgenstein. Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-4091-4 2. Lingua Universalis vs. Calculus Ratiocinator.An Ultimate Presupposition of Twentieth-Century Philosophy. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-4246-1 3. Language, Truth and Logic in Mathematics. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4766-8 4. Paradigms for Language Theory and Other Essays. 1997 ISBN0-7923-4780-3 5. Inquiry as Inquiry. A Logic of Scientific Discovery. 1999 ISBN 0-7923-5477-X 6. Analyses of Aristotle. 2004 ISBN 1-4020-2040-6 JAAKKO HINTIKKA Boston University, U.S.A. ANALYSES OF ARISTOTLE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS NEW YORK,BOSTON, DORDRECHT, LONDON, MOSCOW eBookISBN: 1-4020-2041-4 Print ISBN: 1-4020-2040-6 ©2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers NewYork, Boston, Dordrecht, London, Moscow Print ©2004Kluwer Academic Publishers Dordrecht All rights reserved No part of this eBook maybe reproducedor transmitted inanyform or byanymeans,electronic, mechanical, recording, or otherwise, without written consent from the Publisher Created in the United States of America Visit Kluwer Online at: http://kluweronline.com and Kluwer's eBookstoreat: http://ebooks.kluweronline.com TABLE OF CONTENTS Origin of the essays vii Introduction ix 1. On Aristotle’s notion of existence 1 2. Semantical games, the alleged ambiguity of ‘is’, and Aristotelian categories 23 3. Aristotle’s theory of thinking and its consequences for his methodology 45 4. On the role of modality in Aristotle’s metaphysics 77 5. On the ingredients of an Aristotelian science 87 6. Aristotelian axiomatics and geometrical axiomatics 101 7. Aristotelian induction 111 8. (with Ilpo Halonen) Aristotelian explanations 127 9. Aristotle’s incontinent logician 139 10. On the development of Aristotle’s ideas of scientific method and the structure of science 153 11. What was Aristotle doing in his early logic, anyway?: A reply to Woods and Hansen 175 12. Concepts of scientific method from Aristotle to Newton 183 13. The fallacy of fallacies 193 14. Socratic questioning, logic, and rhetoric 219 v ORIGIN OF THE ESSAYS All permissions granted for the previously published essays by their respective copyright holders are most gratefully acknowledged. Thanks are also due to the editors of the volumes in which these articles appeared previously and to the co-author of one of the articles. 1. ‘‘On Aristotle’s notion of existence’’, The Review of Metaphysics vol.52 (June, 1999), pp.779–805. Reprinted with permission. 2. ‘‘Semantical games, the alleged ambiguity of ‘is’ and Aristotelian cate- gories’’, Synthese vol.54 (1983), pp.443–468 (D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht). 3. ‘‘Aristotle’stheoryofthinkinganditsconsequencesforhismethodology’’, previously unpublished. 4. ‘‘On the role of modality in Aristotle’s metaphysics’’, in Of Scholars, Savants and Their Texts, ed. by Ruth Link-Salinger, Peter Lang Publishing, New York (1989), pp.123–134. Reprinted with permission. 5. ‘‘On the ingredients of an Aristotelian science’’, Nouˆs vol.6 (1972), pp.55–69.Reprintedwithpermissionfrom BlackwellPublishing,Oxford. 6. ‘‘Aristotelian axiomatics and geometrical axiomatics’’, in Theory Change, Ancient Axiomatics and Galilean Methodology, ed. by Jaakko Hintikka et al., D. Reidel Publishing, Dordrecht (1980), pp.133–144. 7. ‘‘Aristotelianinduction’’,RevuelnternationaledePhilosophievol.34(1980), pp.422–439. Reprinted with permission. 8. (with Ilpo Halonen) ‘‘Aristotelian explanations’’, Studies in the History of the Philosophy of Science vol.31, no.1 (2000), pp.125–136. Reprinted with permission from Elsevier. 9. ‘‘Aristotle’s incontinent logician’’, Ajatus vol.37 (1978), pp.48–63. Reprinted with permission. 10. ‘‘On the development of Aristotle’s ideas of scientific method and the structure of science’’, Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, ed. by William Wians, Lanham, Maryland, Rowman & Littlefield (1996), pp.83–104. Reprinted with permission. vii viii ORIGINOFTHEESSAYS 11. ‘‘What was Aristotle doing in his early logic, anyway?: A reply to Woods and Hanson’’, Synthese vol.113 (1997), pp.241–249 (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht). 12. ‘‘Concepts of scientific method from Aristotle to Newton’’, in Knowledge and the Sciences in Medieval Philosophy, Vol.I, ed. by Monica Asztalos, John E. Murdoch and Ilkka Niiniluoto, Helsinki, Acta Philosophica Fennica, vol.48 (1990), pp.72–84. Reprinted with permission. 13. ‘‘The fallacy of fallacies’’, Argumentation vol.1 (1987), pp.211–238 (D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht). 14. ‘‘Socratic questioning, logic, and rhetoric’’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie vol.47, no. 184 (1993), pp.5–30. Reprinted with permission. INTRODUCTION The purpose of the introduction to a book should be the same as that of the label on a medicine bottle. It should tell the reader how to use the text of the book. The present volume needs such instructions more than most books, including the earlier volumes of my selected papers. The main warning that the label on this product should proclaim is not to read the papers printed or reprinted here in the same way as fully polished contributions to scholarly journals on ancient philosophy. I have been, and I continue to be, fascinated byAristotle’sphilosophicalideas.Ihavethoughtaboutthem,andIhavecome up with a number of interpretations of them. The essays published or repub- lishedherearepresentationsoftheseinterpretations.Alas,theyareallsketches rather than fully argued and documented papers. The reason is obvious. My main lines of work in philosophy run elsewhere and have the first claim to my working time and energy. I fully admit this orientation of my philosophical interests does not excuse the sketchiness of my papers. Since I was aware of the situation for a long time, I hoped to rewrite some of the papers published hereandreplacesomeothersbynewonesinsuchawaythattheinterpretational argumentation and scholarly documentation would be on the same level as in specializedpublicationsonancientphilosophy.Reluctantly,Ihavereachedthe conclusion that I will never have a chance of doing so. Hence my only chance of bringing my interpretational ideas to the attention of a wider philosophical audience is to reprint the original papers as they are, with an explanation of their status. My main reason for doing so is a strong belief in the potential importance of the interpretations I outline in these papers. The first and foremost aspect of this importance is the giving of new general perspectives on Aristotle’s philosophy. It might seem overoptimistic, not to say pretentious, to think that after more than two millennia there could be unused clues to Aristotle’s thinking. The fact nevertheless is, I believe, that in some cases the progress of systematic conceptual analysis (and synthesis) puts what Aristotle is doing – or, rather, thinking – in a new light. Even the most central concept of all, ontology, the concept of being, bears witness to these opportunities. For a century and a half, the consensus of philosophers is that this concept is irreducibly ambiguous between being in the sense of identity, predication, existence and subsumption. This assumption may be called the Frege-Russell ambiguity thesis. But is the thesis true? Everybody admits that there are different uses of words for being, but the Frege-Russell thesis tries to explain ix x INTRODUCTION these differences by declaring a single verb to be ambiguous. This ambiguity thesisis evenbuilt intothestandard logicalnotation. Itistherefore littleshort of a shock to realize that nobody before the nineteenth century accepted the ambiguity thesis. Aristotle is a case in point, and this fact at once puts much of his thinking in a new light. Some of the consequences of this insight are explored in the essays below devoted to Aristotle’s treatment of the notions of existence and of category. For instance, when it is realized that the notion of being can be handled without assuming the Frege-Russell ambiguity, as it is handledinordinarylanguage,Aristotle’stheoryofcategoriessuddenlybecomes eminently easy to understand. At the same time, Aristotle’s treatment of exis- tenceinthecontextofasyllogisticscienceexplainssomeofthemostcharacteris- tic features of his doctrines about the structure of science and scientific explanation. For instance, the structure of an Aristotelian science becomes understandable in the light of these insights. This structure was first explored in the essay ‘On the ingredients of an Aristotelian science’’. Another important distinction between different kinds of being, orthogonal tothedistinctionbetweendifferentcategories,isthedistinctionbetweenpoten- tial being and actual being. The problem as to how this dimension of being is related to the rest of Aristotle’s metaphysics is briefly discussed in the essay ‘‘The role of modality in Aristotle’s metaphysics’’. Again, Aristotle’s logic is usually considered as a system on a par with our deductive systems. There is not necessarily anything wrong in doing so, but it does not help to understand how Aristotle came to develop his ideas about logic. An enhanced topical interest in question-answer dialogues and in their logic has led to the idea of considering the Socratic elenchus, his method of questioning, as Aristotle’s starting-point in his work in logic. Plato had been soimpressedbytheSocraticmethodthathehadsystematizedandinstitutional- ized it into questioning games which served as the method of philosophical argumentation and philosophical training in his Academy. Aristotle was the first to develop a systematic theory of such dialectical games, as he himself confidently states at the end of De Sophisticis Elenchis. But it is important to realizethatthenewtheoryhehaddevelopedisnotalogicaltheoryofdeductive reasoning in our sense, but a theory of the Socratic questioning games. But Aristotle did not stop here. He was as competitive as the next Greek. He wanted to know how to play these games so as to win in them. Now any trial lawyer can tell you what is crucial in successful cross-examination: predicting the interlocutor’s answers. Now Aristotle realized that some answers can be predictedwithcompletecertainty.Theyweretheanswerswhichinourterminol- ogy are logically implied by the interlocutor’s earlier answers. Aristotle began to study and to systematize them and – presto! – deductive logic was born. Thisideaanditsconsequencesarestudiedinseveraloftheessays,including the essay on the development of his methodology and the note on his early logic.ItisaconsequenceofthisinsightthatAristotle’sentirelogicandmethod- ology were thought of by him as being conducted within an interrogative framework. This puts into a new light also Aristotle’s theory of fallacies, some INTRODUCTION xi aspects of his rhetoric and the subsequent history of his methodological ideas. An explanation why Aristotle’s logic turned out to be syllogistic is proposed in my joint paper with Ilpo Halonen entitled ‘‘Aristotelian explanations’’. YetanotherperspectiveisobtainedbyunderstandingAristotleliterallywhen he says that thinking of anything – say X – means realizing the form of X in one’ssoul.FromthisitfollowsthatwhatnecessarilyaccompaniesXmustalso be present in one’s mind. To put it bluntly, all logical consequences present themselves to one’s mind necessarily, and all necessary connections between forms–allnaturallaws–canbediscoveredbymeansofthought-experiments. This line of thought is presented in the essay on Aristotle’s theory of thinking. It follows that Aristotelian methodology did not consist in collecting evidence and then drawing inferences from it. Scientific method consisted for Aristotle in building the relevant forms in one’s mind. It was concept formation, not unlike searching for a definition. This puts into a new light Aristotle’s entire methodology, including his notion of induction, to which an early essay is devoted. It also provides a new perspective on Aristotle’s views on both theoretical and practical syllogisms, and thereby on both Aristotle’s syllogistic theory and on his strange views on the weakness of will. The parallelism betweenthesetwosubjectsishighlightedbythetitleofthepaperon‘‘Aristotle’s incontinent logician’’. Since part of the interest of a volume like the present one is that of a historical record, I have not revised them so as to bring them to a complete conformity with each other or to with my present views. Likewise, I have not tried to eliminate overlap between the different essays. This reappearance of thesamethemesindifferentessaysisonlypartlyexplainablebytheinterrelated- ness of Aristotle’s different ideas with each other. For technical reasons, it has beenimpossibletomakethemodesofsourcereferencesuniformfromessayto essay. I realized the magnitude of this problem too late, and as a result I can only hope that it bothers my readers less than it bothers me. In spiteof theseimperfections, Ihope thatthese essayswill inspireothers to explore further the possibilities that they open of understanding better Aristotle’s thought. I also have to hope that others will also marshal more evidence and perhaps even better evidence for the interpretations in the essays printed or reprinted in this volume. MysinceregratitudeisduetoalltheSocraticandnon-Socraticinterlocutors with whom I have discussed the themes of these essays over a period of forty- some years. I am afraid that I cannot even recall all of them nor therefore individuatemythanks.PerhapsthankingRussDancywillsymbolizemythank- ing of all of these colleagues. Likewise, I owe thanks to all of the secretaries and assistants who have on differentoccasionshelpedmewiththeessaysprintedorrepresentedhere.They are the ones who literally write one’s papers, as we all know. Perhaps warm thanks to my present secretary, Lynne Sullivan, will serve as an expression of my appreciation of what they all have done.

Description:
Aristotle thought of his logic and methodology as applications of the Socratic questioning method. In particular, logic was originally a study of answers necessitated by earlier answers. For Aristotle, thought-experiments were real experiments in the sense that by realizing forms in one's mind, one
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.