ebook img

An Introduction to Political Philosophy PDF

171 Pages·2010·17.799 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview An Introduction to Political Philosophy

An Introduction to Political Philosophy A.R.M.Murray ) i Routledge V* m m gj Taylor & Francis Group AN INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY by A.R.M.MURRAY, M.A., PH.D. Extension Lecturer in Social Philosophy in the University of London COHEN & WEST LTD 30 PERCY STREET, LONDON, W. I First published in 1953 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd This edition firstp ublished in 2010 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX 14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 270 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor <fe Francis Group, an informa business This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2010. To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge's collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Publisher's Note The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but points out that some imperfections in the original copies may be apparent Disclaimer The publisher has made every effort to trace copyright holders and welcomes correspondence from those they have been unable to contact ISBN 0-203-85168-4 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 13:978-0-415-57921-6 (hbk) ISBN 13:978-0-203-85168-5 (ebk) ISBN 10:0-415-57921-X(hbk) ISBN 10:0-203-85168-4 (ebk) Routledge Revivals An Introduction to Political Philosophy First published in 1953, this seminal introduction to political philosophy is intended for both the student of political theory and for the general reader. After an introduction which explains the nature and purpose of philosophy, Dr Murray provides a critical examination of the principle theories advanced by political philosophers from Plato to Marx, paying special attention to contemporary issues. The book also makes an attempt to define the essential issues of philosophical significance in contemporary politics, with special reference to the conflict between political authority and individual rights, and to show how the different moral assumptions underlying authori tarian and democratic systems of government are ultimately based upon different theories of logic. PREFACE There are, no doubt, a variety of ways in which political philosophy can be introduced to those who are assumed to have made no study of philosophy at all, and there may well be differences of opinion as to which of these methods is the best In the present volume I have attempted to define what seem to me the fundamental issues of the subject by giving some account of the historical theories which discuss them, but the list of those selected is far from exhaustive, and other authors might well have made a different selection. It is, of course, impossible to embody a comprehensive survey of the history of political thought in a book of modest compass, and there are already larger works, such as Professor G.H.Sabine's History of Political Theory, which have already done this with conspicuous success. Moreover, the present volume is intended to be, not primarily a history of political thought, but a critical examination of it with a view to defining the basic assumptions which have been made by the great political thinkers of the past, and the fundamental issues about which controversy still continues. My selection of the theories for discussion has therefore been determined by the conclusions which I have reached about the nature of those issues and the theories which define them most effectively. The first chapter, in which I attempt to define the nature and scope of philosophy gen erally, and its application in the field of politics, is inevitably somewhat abstract, and any reader who finds it difficult should omit it on a first reading, and proceed straight to Chap ter II, where some of the main issues of moral and political philosophy are defined in the simple terms employed by the early thinkers of Ancient Greece. But the study of the first chapter is essential at some stage if the logical foundations of political philosophy are to be appreciated, and only so can political philosophy in the proper sense be understood. For unless an examination of these logical foundations is undertaken, political philosophy reduces, in effect, to political science, and never raises the essentially philosophical ques tion of the extent to which the moral assumptions made by political theories can be ratio nally justified. The final chapter on The Justification of Government' attempts to define the basic issues which have emerged in the historical chapters, and to relate them to the logical alternatives set forth in Chapter I. As the book is based on the lectures which I have been delivering during the past seven years to London University Extension Classes in Social Philosophy, it will, I hope, prove of special assistance to future classes in this subject But I hope that it will also be of value to University students elsewhere, and that it may help to enlighten the general reader who wishes to acquire some knowledge of what philosophy has to say about the main issues of contemporary politics. I wish to take this opportunity of acknowledging the great help which I have received in the preparation of the book from my friends. Professor H.B.Acton, D.Phil., of the Chair of Philosophy in Bedford College, London, and Mr. E.W.Jones, M.A., Barrister-at-Law and one of my colleagues on the Panel of Extension Lecturers in Social Philosophy. Both were good enough to read the entire typescript and to make many valuable suggestions. While they must not, of course, be held in any way responsible for what I have written. Preface vii I am deeply conscious of the way in which their criticisms have helped me to work out my own position. I must also acknowledge the debt which I owe to the excellent classes which I have had the good fortune to teach, for the searching questions which I have been asked during the discussion hour which follows every lecture have helped me, in no small measure, to develop and clarify my views. Finally, I must thank the Clarendon Press for kindly allowing me to quote a number of passages from the late Professor F.MCornford's translation of Plato's Republic. A.R.M.M. CONTENTS PAGE PREFACE vi I THE NATURE AND SCOPE OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 1 II THE POLITICAL THEORIES OF THE SOPHISTS 17 III PLATO'S THEORY OF THE IDEAL STATE 24 IV ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF THE BEST POSSIBLE STATE 37 V POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE AND MACHIAVELLI 47 VI MACHIAVELLI ON THE SCIENCE OF GOVERNMENT 54 VII HOBBES'S THEORY OF THE RATIONAL STATE 61 VIII LOCKE'S THEORY OF THE MORAL STATE 73 IX ROUSSEAU'S THEORY OF THE GENERAL WILL 82 X HUME AND BURKE ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF CONSERVATISM 92 XI HEGEL'S IDEALIST THEORY OF THE STATE 100 XII THE UTILITARIAN THEORIES OF BENTHAM AND MILL 109 XIII MARXISM, COMMUNISM AND SOCIALISM 123 XIV POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY IN CONTEMPORARY POLITICS 140 XV THE JUSTIFICATION OF GOVERNMENT 151 INDEX 161 CHAPTER I The Nature and Scope of Political Philosophy Until the beginning of the present century philosophy was generally regarded as a source of knowledge which transcended, both in scope and certainty, the discoveries of natural science. Science, it was agreed, marked an advance on the uncritical and often unrelated beliefs of ordinary life, yet it was itself based on the observations of the senses and con sisted of the uncertain generalizations based upon them; whereas philosophy was assumed to answer questions about such subjects as the existence of God, the nature of knowledge, and the authority of the moral law upon which sense-experience, from its very nature, could throw no light. On such subjects, it was believed, reason was alone competent to pronounce and, when it did so, its conclusions were characterized by a logical and universal certainty which the generalizations of natural science could never claim. That philosophical knowledge is certain and indubitable is a claim which, in a broad sense, all philosophers have made, or at least implied; and if a short and simple definition of philosophy were sought the title of the late Professor Dewey ^ GirTord Lectures—The Quest for Certainty'—might serve as a starting point at least For all philosophers have claimed, or at least implied, that philosophical knowledge not only is, but must be, true. But this general agreement has not prevented fundamental differences of opinion regarding the nature and scope of such knowledge; and since these differences are reflected in the application of philosophy to the problems of political theory it is important to be aware, however generally, of their nature. The different conceptions of philosophy ultimately depend upon different conceptions of the nature of indubitable knowledge. The propositions of mathematics are usually cited as typical illustrations of such knowledge. For example, the proposition "Two plus two 1 equals four is said to be necessarily and universally true on the ground that, once we have grasped its meaning, we recognize that it must be necessarily and universally true, and because further instances of its truth do not increase our certainty that it must always be true. Its falsity, in other words, is inconceivable. On the other hand, there are numerous propositions of which the falsity is perfectly conceivable. It may be true that The cat is black* or that "Poliomyelitis is caused by a vims', but these propositions are not necessarily true. On the contrary, their falsity is perfectly conceivable, even if observation appears to confirm their truth. Analytic and Synthetic Propositions The distinction just illustrated is variously referred to as the distinction between rational and empirical knowledge, or between a priori and a posteriori knowledge, or between truths of reason and truths of fact And it is generally true to say that all philosophers have claimed, or at least implied, that their theories are rational and a priori. Where they have differed is in their view of the scope of such knowledge. And the main difference has been that some have held that rational knowledge is always analytic, while others have held that it is sometimes synthetic. 2 An Introduction to Political Philosophy The difference between analytic and synthetic propositions was defined by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) as follows: Analytic propositions, he said, 'add nothing through the predicate to the concept of the subject, but merely break it up into those constituent concepts that have all along been thought in it, although confusedly', while syn thetic judgments 'add to the concept of the subject a predicate which has not been in any 1 wise thought in it, and which no analysis could possibly extract from it'. The difference is, in short, that the predicate in an analytic proposition is contained within the meaning of the subject, while in a synthetic proposition the predicate is not contained within the meaning of the subject but adds something related to it. Kant illustrated the difference by the two propositions 'All bodies are extended' and 'All bodies are heavy'. The former, he thought, is analytic, because the concept of 'extension' is part of the meaning of 'body', while the latter is synthetic because the concept of 'heaviness' is not part of the meaning of 'body', but only a quality which it acquires when it is placed in a gravitational field. Kant's definition drew attention to an important difference between analytic and syn thetic propositions, although not all analytic propositions naturally fall into the simple sub ject-predicate form which his examples illustrate. The essential characteristic of an analytic proposition is that it defines the meaning, or part of the meaning, of its subject and does not describe unessential features which may, or may not, belong to it A cube of iron has a certain weight at sea level, a smaller weight at the top of a high mountain, and no weight at all at a certain point between the earth and the moon; but these differences are not essential elements in the meaning of the description 'cube of iron'. It is clear, on the other hand, that if the cube of iron had no extension it would not be a cube of iron, since extension is an essential part of the meaning of the phrase 'cube of iron'. In other words, to deny an analytic proposition is self-contradictory since that is simultaneously asserting and deny ing the same thing. It is, to borrow Bertrand Russell's example, like saying 'A bald man is 1 not bald'. Modern philosophers have devoted much attention to the study of analytic propositions, and many would agree with Professor Ayer that 'a proposition is analytic when its validity 2 depends solely on the definitions of the symbols it contains', and that this is so because analytic propositions 'do not make any assertion about the empirical world They simply 3 record our determination to use words in a certain fashion.' They are, in other words, tau tologies; and the reason why we think it worth while to assert them and sometimes, as in mathematics, to draw elaborate deductions from them, is that our reason is too limited to recognize their full significance without going through these complex verbal processes. These considerations may appear to be extremely abstract and their connection with what is commonly understood as 'political philosophy' far from obvious; but in fact this connection is both simple and fundamental. For philosophy is the 'quest for certainty', and if certainty is a characteristic of propositions, then an inquiry into the nature and scope of 1 Critique of Pure Reason, Second Edition, Introduction. 1 The Problems of Philosophy, p. 129. 2 Language, Truth, and Logic, Second Edition, p. 78. J op. cit, p. 84.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.