ebook img

An Introduction to Kant's Aesthetics: Core Concepts and Problems PDF

199 Pages·2005·0.85 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview An Introduction to Kant's Aesthetics: Core Concepts and Problems

AN INTRODUCTION TO KANT’S AESTHETICS Core Concepts and Problems Christian Helmut Wenzel An Introduction to Kant’s Aesthetics An Introduction to Kant’s Aesthetics Core Concepts and Problems Christian Helmut Wenzel © 2005 by Christian Helmut Wenzel BLACKWELL PUBLISHING 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148-5020, USA 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK 550 Swanston Street, Carlton, Victoria 3053, Australia The right of Christian Helmut Wenzel to be identified as the Author of this Work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher. First published 2005 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd 1 2005 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Wenzel, Christian Helmut. An introduction to Kant’s aesthetics : core concepts and problems / Christian Helmut Wenzel. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-1-4051-3035-6 (hardcover : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 1-4051-3035-0 (hardcover : alk. paper) ISBN-13: 978-1-4051-3036-3 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 1-4051-3036-9 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Kant, Immanuel, 1724–1804—Aesthetics. 2. Kant, Immanuel, 1724–1804. Kritik der Urteilskraft. 3. Aesthetics. 4. Judgment (Logic) 5. Judgment (Aesthetics) 6. Teleology. 7. Aesthetics, Modern—18th century. I. Title. B2799.A4W46 2005 111¢.85—dc22 2005009258 A catalogue record for this title is available from the British Library. Set in 10 on 12.5 pt Dante by SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd, Hong Kong Printed and bound in India by Replika Press, Pvt Ltd, Kundli The publisher’s policy is to use permanent paper from mills that operate a sustainable forestry policy, and which has been manufactured from pulp processed using acid-free and elementary chlorine-free practices. Furthermore, the publisher ensures that the text paper and cover board used have met acceptable environmental accreditation standards. For further information on Blackwell Publishing, visit our website: www.blackwellpublishing.com Contents Foreword by Henry E. Allison viii Acknowledgments xi About This Book xii Note on the Translation xiv Introduction 1 The Aesthetic Dimension Between Subject and Object 1 The Meaning of “Aesthetic” 4 Categories as a Guide 8 The “Moments” of a Judgment of Taste 13 1 Disinterestedness: First Moment 19 Disinterestedness as a Subjective Criterion 19 Three Kinds of Satisfaction: Agreeable, Beautiful, Good 23 2 Universality: Second Moment 27 The Argument from Self-Reflection: Private, Public, Universal 27 Subjective Universality 31 A Case of Transcendental Logic 35 Singular “but” Universal 39 How to Read Section 9 46 3 Purposiveness: Third Moment 54 Purpose without Will, Purposiveness without Purpose 54 Purposiveness and Form: Charm versus Euler 60  vi Of “Greatest Importance”: Beauty and Perfection 65 Beauty: Free, Dependent, and Ideal 69 4 Necessity: Fourth Moment 77 Exemplary Necessity 77 Kant’s Interpretation of the sensus communis 81 The Deduction 86 5 Fine Art, Nature, and Genius 94 Fine Art and Why It Must Seem like Nature 94 Genius and Taste 98 Genius and Aesthetic Ideas 101 6 Beyond Beauty 106 The Sublime 106 Beauty as the Symbol of Morality 113 The Analytic, the Dialectic, and the Supersensible 120 7 Two Challenges 128 Can Kant’s Aesthetics Account for the Ugly? 128 Can there be Beauty and Genius in Mathematics? 133 Summary and Overview 141 Before Kant 141 Kant’s Aesthetics 142 After Kant 146 Glossary 149 Bibliography 157 Index 171 Correspondances La Nature est un temple où de vivants piliers Laissent parfois sortir de confuses paroles; L’homme y passe à travers des forêts de symboles Qui l’observent avec des regards familiers. Comme des longs échos qui de loin se confondent Dans une ténébreuse et profonde unité, Vaste comme la nuit et comme la clarté, Les parfums, les couleurs et les sons se répondent. Il est des parfums frais comme des chairs d’enfants, Doux comme les hautbois, verts comme les prairies, – Et d’autres, corrompus, riches et triomphants, Ayant l’expansion des choses infinies, Comme l’ambre, le musc, le benjoin et l’encens, Qui chantent les transports de l’esprit et des sens. Charles Baudelaire Correspondences Nature is a temple whose living pillars Utter at times confused words; Man passes there through forests of symbols That watch him with familiar eyes. Like long echoes confounding distantly Into oneness, unfathomable and dark, Vast as the night, vast as light, Scents, sounds and colors correspond. Scents fresh as babies’ skin, Soft as oboes, as meadows green – and others, broken, triumphant, rich, Expansive as infinite things, Amber, musk, incense and myrrh, That sing the ecstasies of spirit and of sense. (Translation by Joseph Swann and C. H. Wenzel) Foreword It has been said that Kant probably never saw a great painting or piece of sculp- ture; indeed, this is quite likely, inasmuch as he spent his entire life in and around Königsberg in East Prussia. It is also clear that he had no great appreciation of music and that the only art form with which he had an extensive familiarity was literature. Nevertheless, this did not prevent him from producing what is gener- ally regarded as one of the most important contributions to aesthetics in the history of modern thought. This is contained in the Critique of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment, which is the first part of the Critique of the Power of Judgment(or, in some English versions, the Critique of Judgment) of 1790. Unfortunately, however, this work is almost as forbidding to the uninitiated as it is rewarding to those able to penetrate its almost legendary obscurity. There are a number of reasons for this obscurity, not least of which are the inherent difficulty of the issues involved and the unfamiliar technical terminol- ogy in which Kant expresses his views. The main reason, however, which also largely explains the terminological difficulties is that the Critique of the Power of Judgment is the capstone of an all-encompassing “critical system,” which Kant developed in the 1780s. In fact, it is the third of three “Critiques,” the first two being the Critique of Pure Reason (1781, second edition 1787) and the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), which is why it is often referred to simply as the “third Critique.” Accordingly, much of what Kant has to say in this work cannot be understood without some grasp of the larger project of which it is an integral part. In addition to contributing to the difficulty in understanding Kant’s aesthetic theory, this theory’s tight connection with his overall critical project is also directly responsible for two of its most distinctive features. First, as the title of the third Critique suggests, Kant’s aesthetics is oriented more toward questions of aesthetic judgment, namely, the grounds and warrant for claiming that an object of nature or art is beautiful (or sublime), than toward questions of the  ix nature of art. Although Kant did deal with the latter and, in the process, pro- pounded a very influential theory of artistic creativity and genius, in his mind at least, this was secondary to the “critique of taste,” which was the original title that Kant assigned to the work that was eventually to become the third Critique. In short, Kant’s is more a “reception” than a “creation aesthetic.” Second, Kant’s overall aesthetic theory is embedded in a set of questions regarding knowledge, morality, and even metaphysics. And, to complicate matters even further, it is combined with the Critique of Teleological Power of Judg- ment, which is the second part of the third Critique. All of this adds immeasur- ably to the richness and importance of Kant’s account, but at the same time it reinforces the need for some guide to assist the reader who lacks sufficient knowl- edge of the intricacies of Kant’s thought. Although there has been no shortage of interpretive studies of Kant’s aes- thetics in the recent literature (including one by myself), there is really nothing of which I am aware that is both addressed to the reader with little or no prior knowledge of Kant’s thought and thoroughly grounded in the texts. These are the main virtues of Christian Wenzel’s brief work. His discussion is accessible, informed, and, given the modest size of the book, remarkably comprehensive. In fact, Wenzel has something useful to say about virtually every aspect of Kant’s aesthetic theory. To be sure, in no case does he provide the last word – nor does he pretend to do so – but he does supply an excellent overview of this theory, as it is presented in the third Critique. Particularly notable in this regard are the glos- sary in which the key technical terms are explained and the reference to “further reading” following each section. Whereas the former will be of benefit to the reader who is confronting Kant for the first time, the latter will be of value to those who wish to pursue a particular topic or issue in greater depth. Finally, it must be noted that, in spite of the modesty of its ambitions, Wenzel’s book makes a significant contribution to the literature at two points. One is the topic of ugliness. Like most writers on aesthetics, at least those of his time, Kant’s focus was on judgments of beauty (both natural and artistic) and he has very little to say about the ugly. The problem, however, is that it seems that a theory of aesthetic judgment oughtto account for the possibility of judgments of ugliness as well as beauty. Wenzel tackles this issue head on, arguing that Kant’s theory of taste can account for judgments of ugliness, as indeed it must. The second topic on which Wenzel has something interesting to say concerns Kant’s theory of genius. Notoriously, Kant claimed that genius is limited to the domain of art and, therefore, that great mathematicians and scientists – Leibniz and Newton are the paradigms – cannot truly be called geniuses because their discoveries were the result of the application of determinate rules, whereas the creation of a great work of art is not. Arguing as a mathematician (he has a doc- torate in mathematics as well as in philosophy), Wenzel points out that some-

Description:
I read this book for a graduate seminar on the philosophy of art. Kant is one of the major figures in expression theory. What we understand as aesthetics changed only recently. Wenzel's "Introduction to Kant's Critique of Judgment" is a great companion to "Critique of Judgment," which is supposed to
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.