ebook img

Simplicius: On Aristotle Physics 8.1-5 PDF

257 Pages·2011·1.31 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Simplicius: On Aristotle Physics 8.1-5

SIMPLICIUS On Aristotle Physics 8.1-5 This page intentionally left blank SIMPLICIUS On Aristotle Physics 8.1-5 Translated by István Bodnár, Michael Chase and Michael Share LONDON • NEW DELHI • NEW YORK • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published in 2012 by Bristol Classical Press Paperback edition fi rst published 2014 © 2012 by István Bodnár, Michael Chase, and Michael Share István Bodnár, Michael Chase, and Michael Share have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identifi ed as Authors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the author. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN HB: 978-1-7809-3210-1 PB: 978-1-4725-3917-5 ePDF: 978-1-4725-0179-0 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. The present translations have been made possible by generous and imaginative funding from the following sources: the National Endowment for the Humanities, Division of Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the Leverhulme Trust; the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Council; Gresham College; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown Trust; Mr and Mrs N. Egon; the Netherlands Organisation for Scientifi c Research (NOW/GW); the Hungarian National Fund for Scientifi c Research (OTKA); the Ashdown Trust; Dr Victoria Solomonides, the Cultural Attaché of the Greek Embassy in London. The editor wishes to thank Peter Lautner, Barrie Fleet, James Wilberding, Pantelis Golitsis, Michael Griffi n, Donald Russell, Michael Share, Richard McKirahan, and Katharine O’Reilly for their comments, Annie Hewitt, David Robertson, Riin Sirkel and Ian Crystal for indexes. He is also grateful to Ian Crystal for preparing the volume for press and to Deborah Blake, the publisher responsible for every volume since the fi rst. Typeset by Ray Davies Printed and bound in Great Britain Contents Preface Richard Sorabji vii Conventions xi Abbreviations xii Departures from Diels’ Text xiii Simplicius’ response to Philoponus’ attack on Aristotle Physics 8.1 Michael Chase 1 Translation 8.1-2 Michael Chase 19 8.3 Michael Share 94 8.4 István Bodnár 112 8.5 Michael Share and Michael Chase 130 Notes 169 Bibliography 197 English-Greek Glossary 199 Greek-English Index 207 Subject Index 232 This page intentionally left blank Preface Richard Sorabji In these chapters of Book 8 of the Physics, Aristotle (384-322 BC) paves the way for introducing, at the end of Book 8, the Prime Mover of the heavens, which along with most Greeks Aristotle took to rotate around the earth. In Chapter 1, he urges against Democritus that an explana- tion of motion is needed, even if, as he argues in Chapter 2, motion is eternal, despite (Chapter 3) some non-motion. In Chapter 4,1 he argues that a body’s movement must be caused by something distinct from itself, contrary to Plato’s view that soul is self-moving. Taking the particular case of animals, which are popularly thought of as self- moving, Aristotle says that it is really the soul that moves an animal’s body (8.4, 254b27-33, developed in 8.6, 258a1-b9), along with stimuli from the environment (to periekhon, 8.2, 253a7-20; 8.6, 259b1-20). But what about the natural motion of air and fire upwards and of earth or water downwards? In Physics 2.1, he had distinguished natural motion from the motion of artefacts, by saying that natural objects have an internal source of movement, their nature, whereas artefacts have to be propelled from outside. But in Physics 8.4, a body’s inner nature seems insufficiently distinct from it to satisfy the requirement that what is moved should be moved by something other than itself. So he introduces a point not made explicit before, that the inner nature of earth, air, fire and water is a source not of causing motion, but of undergoing it (paskhein, 255b30-1) at the hands of some further agent. To serve as this further agent, he introduces two low-grade causes which do not maintain continuing contact with what they move. To take steam rising from a kettle as an example of rising air, the low-grade agent could be either the person who boils the water in the kettle, or the person who releases the obstacle to its rising by taking the lid off the kettle (256a1-2). The obstacle remover, however, is an agent only accidentally, like the wall off which a ball ricochets. This second agent does not interest Alexander, and Philoponus was later to rule out the obstacle- remover altogether (in Phys. 195,24-32). The inner nature still answers the question why (dia ti) light and heavy natural objects move to their natural places. But the further agents answer the question by what the movement is initiated. If in all motion, even that of animals and of viii Preface natural rise and fall, a body is moved by something distinct from itself, then the way has been paved for inferring by induction that the heavens too must be moved by something distinct from themselves. The induc- tion is not required to show that that something acts in the same way as the celestial mover. In 8.5, Aristotle argues that, on pain of an infinite regress, we must avoid saying that everything moved is moved by something that is moved in its turn. But he still regards Plato’s idea of self-motion as not yet ruled out, and offers a more general argument that in so-called self-movers, we have to find a part that causes and a part that under- goes motion. Hence the prime mover that stops the regress needs to be unmoved. Rather unexpectedly, he urges that the soul itself is un- moved, a view that he will defend in his later On the Soul 2.5, by saying that when the capacities that in his view constitute the soul are actualised, such actualisation is not to be thought of as an ordinary case of being moved or affected. The reference to soul as unmoved may seem risky, because he does not want the conclusion that the heavenly bodies are moved simply by their own souls as unmoved movers. But eventu- ally in 8.10, without mentioning the issue, Aristotle will argue that the unmoved mover required cannot be a capacity housed in or possessed by the finite body of his universe (as the souls of the heavenly bodies would need to be), because a finite body could not accommodate the infinite power needed for the eternal rotation of the heavens. The commentary on Aristotle’s Physics 8.1-5 written by the Neo- platonist Simplicius some time after AD 529 is particularly interesting for two reasons. First, it contains a substantial excursus attacking Philoponus, and this is the subject of Michael Chase’s Introduction to Simplicius’ response to Philoponus’ attack on Aristotle Physics 8.1. Simplicius’ excursus includes precious fragments of Book 6 of Philoponus’ Against Aristotle. These fragments, numbered 121-33, have already been included in fourteen pages of Christian Wildberg’s 1987 translation of Philoponus’ attack on Aristotle in the series Ancient Commentators on Aristotle, and have been further discussed by him elsewhere.2 Philoponus’ attack includes the famous arguments that, on principles accepted ever since Aristotle, the universe cannot have finished going right through a more than finite number of days, much less be going to exceed a more than finite number. These arguments by Philoponus have drawn attention repeatedly and were highlighted again in 1983.3 The present translation makes more accessible Sim- plicius’ side of the case. This was examined in the first of several writings by Philippe Hoffman, in a collection of 1987.4 The collection’s second edition of 2010 provides a survey and bibliography of writing on Philoponus since 1987, including writing on this subject,5 and Michael Chase below takes the discussion of Simplicius further. Secondly, Simplicius reports and quotes extensively the lost com- mentary of Alexander, holder of the Aristotelian chair in Athens at or Preface ix soon after AD 200. This is an ideal time to consider Simplicius’ use of Alexander,6 because Marwan Rashed has at this moment published and discussed his newly discovered fragments of Alexander’s lost commen- tary on Books 4 to 8, more on Book 8 than on any other book.7 In an earlier article, he found Simplicius ascribing to Alexander the opposite of his real view by leaving out of his quotation six words that survive in the newly recovered text.8 But the overall picture that emerges from comparing the new fragments as a whole is that Simplicius tends to report or quote Alexander accurately and to respect his judgement, even though on certain types of issue he goes on to disagree. The subjects on which Simplicius disagrees suggest to Rashed Simplicius’ purposes in writing a commentary.9 Simplicius saw some Presocratic philosophers, along with Plato, Aristotle and the Chaldaean Oracles as constituting a coherent and eternal philosophy, in which Aristotle legitimately discussed the perceptible world, but Plato above all and others emphasised its dependence on a higher intelligible world. Sim- plicius disagrees with Alexander when the latter interprets Aristotle in a way that rules out the higher causes and that turns merely perspec- tival differences among the authorities into doctrinal differences. Alexander, he thinks, is of much value because of his mastery of Aristotle’s text, but because of these other tendencies, his is the last interpretation of Aristotle outside pagan Neoplatonism that Simplicius can tolerate. Christianity, on this view, is the foe, represented at its worst in Simplicius’ Christian contemporary Philoponus. The latter has no understanding of perspectival differences, but seeks to show dissen- sion and error in the eternal philosophy. If this is right, it is no accident that the two most distinctive aspects of the present text are its attack on Philoponus, and its intensive use, with caveats, of Alexander. For these will have been the two issues which most exercised Simplicius. Notes 1. This account of Chapters 4 and 5 is chiefly based on that in my Matter, Space and Motion, London 1988, Chicago 2006, ch. 13. 2. Christian Wildberg, ‘Prolegomena to the study of Philoponus’ contra Aristotelem’ in Richard Sorabji (ed.), Philoponus and the Rejection of Aristote- lian Science, London 1983, 2nd edn, Supplement 103 to the Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, London 2010, and in John Philoponus’ Criticism of Aristotle’s Theory of Aether, Berlin 1968. 3. Richard Sorabji, Time, Creation and the Continuum, London 1983, Chi- cago 2006, ch. 14, ‘Infinity arguments in favour of a beginning’. 4. Philippe Hoffmann, ‘Simplicius’ polemics’, in Richard Sorabji (ed.), Phi- loponus and the Rejection of Aristotelian Science, London 1983, 2nd edn, Supplement 103 to the Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, London 2010. 5. The second edition edition adds, besides the survey and bibliography of the literature on Philoponus since 1987, an interpretation of the excavated

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.