Alessandro Arbo | Michel Le Du | Sabine Plaud (Eds.) Wittgenstein and Aesthetics Perspectives and Debates APORIA Apori/a HRSG. VON / EDITED BY Jesús Padilla Gálvez (University of Castilla-La Mancha) ADVISORY BOARD Pavo Barišić (University of Split) Michel Le Du (University of Strasbourg) Miguel García-Baró (University of Comillas) Margit Gaffal (University of Castilla-La Mancha) Guillermo Hurtado (National Autonomous University of Mexico) Antonio Marques (New University of Lisbon) Lorenzo Peña (Spanish National Research Council) Nicanor Ursua Lezaun (University of the Basque Country) Nuno Venturinha (New University of Lisbon) Pablo Quintanilla (Pontifical Catholic University of Peru) Aporia is a new series devoted to studies in the field of philosophy. Aporia (Aπορία) means philosophical puzzle and the aim of the series is to present contributions by authors who systematically investigate current problems. Aporia (Aπορία) puts special emphasis on the publication of concise arguments on the topics studied. The publication has to contribute to the explanation of current philosophical problem, using a systematic or a historic approach. Contributions should concern relevant philosophical topics and should reflect the ongoing progress of scientific development. Volume 6 Alessandro Arbo | Michel Le Du Sabine Plaud (Eds.) Wittgenstein and Aesthetics Perspectives and Debates Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. North and South America by Transaction Books Rutgers University Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected] United Kingdom, Ireland, Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited White Cross Mills Hightown LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected] Livraison pour la France et la Belgique: Librairie Philosophique J.Vrin 6, place de la Sorbonne; F-75005 PARIS Tel. +33 (0)1 43 54 03 47; Fax +33 (0)1 43 54 48 18 www.vrin.fr 2012 ontos verlag P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com ISBN 978-3-86838-167-2 2012 No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use of the purchaser of the work Printed on acid-free paper FSC-certified (Forest Stewardship Council) This hardcover binding meets the International Library standard Printed in Germany by buch bücher.de CONTENTS Introduction 7 I. Aesthetic Investigations JOÃO VERGILIO GALLERANI CUTER Tractarian Aesthetics 15 CHIARA CAPPELLETTO Aesthetics as Methodology in Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Thought: The Operational Character of Family Resemblances 25 ANTONIA SOULEZ His (Freud) Explanation Does What Aesthetics Does: it Puts Two Factors Together 45 II. Aesthetic Grammar JESÚS PADILLA GÁLVEZ Visual Space as Aesthetic Problem 63 MICHEL LE DU Seeing as and Semantic Expansion 81 JULIA TANNEY Conceptual Cartography and Aesthetics – a Preliminary Study 97 III. Musical Understanding ALESSANDRO ARBO Typology and Functions of “Hearing-as” 117 LEONARDO DISTASO Notes on Aesthetic Comprehension: Sound beyond Image 129 MARIE-ANNE LESCOURRET Musical Analysis versus Grammatical Analysis: Saying, Whistling, Describing, Understanding 141 IV. Ethics and Aesthetics JERROLD LEVINSON Prolegomenon to a Morality of Music 161 SANDRINE DARSEL From Art to Ethics: Exemplary Nature of Art Works and Aspectual Perception 167 V. Theory of Art MAURIZIO FERRARIS Art as Document 183 SABINE PLAUD From Language Games to Analytic Iconography: a Comparison between Ludwig Wittgenstein and Daniel Arasse 195 Index nominum 213 Wittgenstein and Aesthetics: Perspectives and Debates Alessandro ARBO, Michel LE DU, Sabine PLAUD Strasbourg University The papers collected in this volume were all presented at a conference held at Strasbourg University in January 2011: “Les raisons de l’esthétique, à partir de Wittgenstein” (organized with the support of two research units: EA 3402 “Approches contemporaines de la création et de la réflexion artistiques,” and EA 2326 “Philosophie allemande”). The purpose was to reevaluate the epistemological status of aesthetics in the light of Wittgenstein’s conceptions. This conference sought, therefore, to continue in the same direction as other seminal contributions to the discipline: the conference on “Wittgenstein and Aesthetics” held in June 2010 in Southampton, and the book edited by Peter B. Lewis: Wittgenstein, Aesthetics and Philosophy (London, Ashgate Publishing, 2004). Wittgenstein’s writings have of course elicited a lot of debates and controversies, many of which are now commonplace topics in academic discussions. Yet, Wittgenstein’s considerations on aesthetics have raised fewer comments and debates than, for instance, his writings on language, mind, or mathematics. One aim of this volume is to reconsider this aspect: the contributors were invited to examine the notion of aesthetics in a broad sense, and to consider some of Wittgenstein’s concepts – such as aspectual perception, the criterion/symptom distinction, the opposition between grounds and causes – that may bring new theoretical material to contemporary aesthetic reflection. Another aim of this book is to tap these concepts in order to draw connections between aesthetic concerns and various areas of philosophical research: philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, theory of knowledge. Accordingly, the book tries both to deepen specific topics (such as musical understanding) and to encompass aesthetic issues in a broader perspective. By editing it, we thus sought to follow the advice given to us by this (anti-)philosopher when he invited his readers to throw away the ladder he had himself erected with his (pseudo-)propositions. In other words, the point of this book is not Wittgenstein and Aesthetics: Perspectives and Debates, eds. Alessandro ARBO, Michel LE DU, Sabine PLAUD, Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt a. M., 2012, 7-12. 8 Wittgenstein and Aesthetics: Perspectives and Debates exclusively to clarify what Wittgenstein said about art and aesthetics (and how he said it), but also to examine how these conceptions may be exploited nowadays in the field of aesthetics, and how we might proceed our own way on some of the paths Wittgenstein has started to open up. The book is divided into five sections: aesthetic investigations, aesthetic grammar, musical understanding, ethics aesthetics and art theory. I. Aesthetic Investigations In his paper entitled “Tractarian Aesthetics,” João Vergílio Gallerani Cuter tries to answer the following questions: Is it possible to speak about “Tractarian aesthetics”? Does it make any sense to look for aesthetic values “endorsed” (or even “implied”) by the Tractatus? In what sense, and to what extent, can we look for such values? Is it possible, for instance, to use “Tractarian principles” (or something of the sort) in order to assess a work of art? How should we interpret the statement that “ethics and aesthetics are one”? Are they strictly identical? Or do they simply share a common ground? In “Aesthetics as Methodology in Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Thought: The Operational Character of Family Resemblances,” Chiara Cappelletto underlines that, already in the Tractatus, Wittgenstein writes that “Belief in the causal nexus is superstition,” and she stresses how he maintains this conviction throughout his philosophical development. The point is then to find reasons allowing for a description of how what happens may happen. Such is the function of family resemblances: they connect different elements, each of which reveals its identity by means of a recognition of its relation with other elements of the same epistemological framework. Under the title “His [Freud’s] Explanation Does What Aesthetics Does: it Puts Two Factors Together” (taken from passages of Wittgenstein’s 1932-1935 Cambridge Lectures), Antonia Soulez claims that aesthetics, according to Wittgenstein, is descriptive, placing things side by side so as to exhibit characteristics conveyed by reasons, intended as “further descriptions,” or as justifying features in a work of art. It does not answer the question “why” by alleging causes: the description of a thing is opposed to causal connections. Aesthetics has nothing to do with psychology (or psychoanalysis), whose ambition is to become an empirical science based on experiments. Indeed, Freud confuses the two, treating psychological questions by means of representations mimicking those of science. His confusion unfortunately makes psychoanalysis appear as an Wittgenstein and Aesthetics: Perspectives and Debates 9 empirical science dealing with causes, according to a method relying on a hypothesis (the Unconscious). II. Aesthetic Grammar In the fourth chapter of this book, entitled “Visual Space as Aesthetic Problem,” Jesús Padilla Gálvez tries to reconstruct the contributions that Wittgenstein made to the field of aesthetics. He deals especially with the reconstruction of a theory of sensory perception, which is characterized by the program of “minima visibilia.” This program is analyzed by employing the phenomenological method. In the context of visual space, three problems are addressed, namely blurredness, indistinctness, and sensory impressions. A distinction between the visual space and the Euclidean space can only be achieved by comparing their respective typical structures. The text focuses especially on the relation between the seeing subject and the visual space. To get a deeper insight into this problem, the visual space is compared to a two-dimensional picture. In order to establish “minima visibilia,” the role of color has to be clarified. Michel Le Du, in “Seeing as and Semantic Expansion,” tries both to assess the enduring relevance of Wittgenstein’s remarks on aspect perception and family resemblances, and to connect these remarks to current issues in philosophy of language and epistemology. We build analogies as much as we discover them, and the outcomes of such building processes may have very different epistemic scopes. Numerous analogies are aspect-seeing; others have a deeper ontological significance. Some analogies are clearly fictional. They deserve to be called, following Max Black, “as-if” analogies. The scopes of many others (both in the human and in the natural sciences) remain controversial. Consequently, the purpose of his text is to sketch an overview of the various ways of making analogies and to analyze the role played by metaphors therein. Julia Tanney’s “Conceptual Cartography and Aesthetics” addresses the following questions: What happens to philosophical investigation if we relinquish the idea that the “elasticities of significance” of our expressions are discernible outside the contexts in which they are employed? What happens, thus, if we cannot presume to know in advance the function of an utterance, the dimensions along which it is to be evaluated – and so what is communicated and whether it is understood – in virtue of knowing its grammatical form and the words in which it consists? Whereas traditional conceptual analysis seeks to uncover a (partial) list of rules that articulate 10 Wittgenstein and Aesthetics: Perspectives and Debates our grasp of a concept – understood as something that exists independently of our practices – “naturalized” philosophy proposes theories about what are taken to be the genuine referents – the properties, states, relations and events – at which our linguistic expressions merely gesture. But if concept nouns such as “beauty,” “art,” “intention,” or “expression,” for example, refer neither to abstract objects nor to meaning rules, nor serve to indicate real properties or relations, but serve instead a different-order task, then both the traditional and the naturalist programs are threatened. Julia Tanney advances the revival of the argument for the cartographical approach and suggests very briefly how it might be applied to an investigation of aesthetic concepts. III. Musical Understanding Alessandro Arbo, in “Typology and Functions of ‘Hearing-as’” tries to broaden the perspective opened up by Wittgenstein’s remarks through an analysis of the phrase “hearing as.” Uses of this expression are tested in some standard situations, and discussed in order to highlight its key functions. Four main functions are identified: conceptual (it highlights the opportunity to conceive the perception of music in terms of aspectual perception), aesthetico-pragmatic (it solicits and makes easier the perception of aspects, inducing in this way a musical understanding), epistemological (it allows us to examine the musical understanding of which a listener is capable), and experimental (it helps us to test musical ambiguities). Some variations of its purpose are eventually examined, according to the nature of the object listened to: when such an object is recognized as a musical work, the device favors a specific grasp, involving a knowledge of the context of the composition and a recognition of the author’s intentions. Leonardo Distaso, in his paper “Notes on Aesthetic Comprehension: Sound Beyond Image,” starts from Wittgenstein’s concept of a derivation of aesthetic understanding, and tries to show what part is played by the sound (and sonority) of words in an understanding of language that may overcome the connections between picture and representation, in order to grasp the problem of art, and in particular music, with respect to language in general. Marie-Anne Lescourret, in her text “Musical Analysis versus Grammatical Analysis: Saying, Whistling, Describing, Understanding,” recalls that musicians and musicologists know that, as Wittgenstein writes,