ebook img

What is an institution PDF

19 Pages·2011·0.18 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview What is an institution

Kent Academic Repository Pina-Cabral, Joao (2011) Afterword: What is an institution? Social Anthropology (Journal of the European Association of Social Anthropologists), 19 (4). pp. 477-494. ISSN 0964-0282. Downloaded from https://kar.kent.ac.uk/31210/ The University of Kent's Academic Repository KAR The version of record is available from https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1469-8676.2011.00173.x This document version UNSPECIFIED DOI for this version Licence for this version UNSPECIFIED Additional information Versions of research works Versions of Record If this version is the version of record, it is the same as the published version available on the publisher's web site. Cite as the published version. Author Accepted Manuscripts If this document is identified as the Author Accepted Manuscript it is the version after peer review but before type setting, copy editing or publisher branding. Cite as Surname, Initial. (Year) 'Title of article'. To be published in Title of Journal , Volume and issue numbers peer-reviewed accepted version. Available at: DOI or URL (Accessed: date). Enquiries If you have questions about this document contact [email protected]. Please include the URL of the record in KAR. If you believe that your, or a third party's rights have been compromised through this document please see our Take Down policy (available from https://www.kent.ac.uk/guides/kar-the-kent-academic-repository#policies). JOA˜ O DE PINA-CABRAL Afterword: What is an institution? Whatisaninstitution?WesuccessivelyexaminedefinitionsprovidedbyDurkheim,Mauss,Parsons,Goffman andBerger,andLuckman.Whilstanthropologistsacknowledgethatthestuffofhumaninstitutionsis‘the combinationofmodesofactionwithmodesofthinking’,somehowtheyhaveseentheepitomeofthatembodied inthecompulsoryorganisationsofmodern,state-run,Westernsociety.Thepaperarguesfortheabandonment ofrepresentationalsolutions,whichoperatewithaCartesianviewofmind;sociocentricsolutions,which viewgroupnessasunitaryandteleological;andindividualistsolutionsthatfailtoseepeopleasconstituted inontogenythroughintersubjectiveattunement.Humansocialityandhumanunderstandingmustnotbe separatedfromtheworld,butpersonsdonotpre-existintersubjectiveattunementandthisoperatesthrougha processoftriangulationbetweenself,otherandworldwhereallelementsareintrinsicallyinvolved. Keywords institution,representation,sociocentrism,individualism,intersubjectivity Introduction Overacenturyago,SirJamesFrazerpresentedaconferenceataneveningmeetingof theRoyalInstitutionofLondoncalledPsyche’sTask(1909).Hisargumentwassimple: WhiletheinstitutionswithwhichIshalldealhaveallsurvivedintocivilisedsociety andcannodoubtbedefendedbysolidandweightyarguments,itispractically certainthatamongsavages,andevenamongpeoplesthathavereasonabovethe levelofsavagery,theseverysameinstitutionshavederivedmuchoftheirstrength frombeliefswhichnowadaysweshouldcondemnunreservedlyassuperstitious andabsurd.(1909:2) Hechoosestofocusonfourinstitutions–government,privateproperty,marriage andrespectforhumanlife–and,attheendoftheessay,hetellsusthatthischoiceis basedonhisconvictionthattheseinstitutions‘arethepillarsonwhichreststhewhole fabricofsociety’(1909:82).Thereis,therefore,amorallessoninhisargument:‘More and more, as times goes, morality shifts its ground from the sands of superstition to therockofreason,fromtheimaginarytothereal,fromthesupernaturaltothenatural’ (1909:81).InFrazer’sreadingofthemythologicaltale,thetaskimposedonPsycheby jealousAphroditeconsistedof‘sortingouttheseedsofgoodfromtheseedsofevil’.In thisway,theauthoriscommentingonthegrandtaskthatheimposeduponhimself,as SocialAnthropology/AnthropologieSociale(2011)19,4477–494.(cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. 477 doi:10.1111/j.1469-8676.2011.00173.x 478 JOA˜O DE PINA-CABRAL hesiftedthroughthemyriadexamplesofhumanbehaviourthathisvoluminousbooks itemiseinordertofindwithinthemtheseedsoftheinstitutionsuponwhichcivilisation, ashesawit,isfounded. Thisutopiandeclarationoffaithinmodernityandintheredeemingpowersofthe rationalindividualisverycharacteristicofhisimperialepoch.Tothatextent,itshould not surprise us. But it does help us to focus our mind on how distant we are from theassumptionsthatgrantcogencytoFrazer’sargument.Wordslike‘savage’,‘reason’, ‘morality’,‘superstition’,‘institution’nolongercarrythesameechoesforusthatthey carried in his day. They seem to have undergone a significant ‘change of aspect’ and that is why Frazer’s argument sounds so quaint to us today. The following essay is inspired by Rodney Needham’s methodological injunction that we should focus on such ‘changes of aspect’ of the analytical terms upon which our arguments depend. He claimed that identifying such ‘changes of aspect’ might help us detect both the ‘treacherousnessofwords’andthe‘secretsympathies’thattranspire(1983:esp.1–18). For Frazer, a word such as ‘institution’ required little exegesis for it to be understood – he never even bothers to define it. But we can legitimately ask: how hasthewordchangedduringtheinterveningcentury?Furthermore,ifweconcludeit has, what ‘secret sympathies’ does it still carry within its cavernous belly? How are weaffectedtoday–onewholecenturylater–bytheimplicitassumptionswritteninto Frazer’suseoftheword? If we are looking for a contemporary definition of ‘institution’ we can go, for example, to the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy: ‘Typically, contemporary sociologists use the term to refer to complex social forms that reproduce themselves such as governments, the family, human languages, universities, hospitals, business corporations,andlegalsystems’(s.v.‘socialinstitution’1). Thefirstthingtonotehereisthenotionof‘complexsocialforms’–complex,in relationtowhat?Contrarytomanyofmycolleagues,Iampronetofeeluncomfortable whenafeatureofsociallifeisdescribedinrelationtoanopposingattributethatisleft unspecified.Nothingiscomplexinandofitself withoutcomparisonwithsomeother thingthatis,somehow,lesscomplex.Weare,therefore,immediatelylefttowonderwhat othersocialformsmightnotbecomplex.Furthermore,wealwayshavetoaskinwhat capacityisthatthingcomplex–andagainthequestionseemssomehowtohavebeen elided.Weknowwhatcameofthelonghistoryofcategoricaloppositionssuchasthe onebetween‘complexsocieties’andthoseunnamed‘Other’societies.There,inthose days(notsolongago–TheSocialAnthropologyofComplexSocieties,Banton1966), theelidedtermwasactually‘primitive’,aconceptthatnoonecouldshedbutofwhich everyonewasfrightened.Whatistheelidedtermnow?Arewenotencounteringhere asetof‘secretsympathies’withFrazer’stracingoftheinevitablepathfromsavageryto civilisationasaprocessofrationalisation? Let us look a little more attentively at the list of examples provided in the StanfordEncyclopaediadefinition:thefamily,notfamilies;governments,nottheState; universities, not classrooms; legal systems, not practice of law business corporations, not voluntary associations; human languages, not sign systems... There is a strange coherence in the way these examples seem to line up and in what each one of them excludes by its very presence in the list. There is an unstated assumption here that institutionsarehierarchicalsystemsboundbyexplicit,rational,writtencodes. 1 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/social-institutions/ (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. WHAT IS AN INSTITUTION? 479 Thisassumption,infact,ispartofourcommonuseoftheword.Forinstance,ifI saythat‘inPortugal,cousinsareaninstitution’,IaminthelimitsofwhatIcanexpecta commonspeakerofEnglishtounderstandandevensocialscientistsareboundtofind myuseoftheexpressionsomewhatcontrivedormetaphoric.However,ifIthengoon tosaythatbeingthegodfatherofmycousin’schildisaninstitutionalaspectofmylife, noonewilltakemeseriously. Asimilarsortoffailureinsemanticextensioncanbedetectedintheusethatthe capitalised word ‘Institute’ has been given over the past decades to name all sorts of modern, purpose-geared, formal organisations with a hierarchical structure. My employer, for example, is an Institute of Social Sciences. But here too, there seem to be limits to the word’s relevance. For example, if I worked for an organisation that had nothing to do with the State, it would more likely be called an ‘association’ or a ‘foundation’thananinstitute.AnNGOisnotlikelytobecalledaninstitute,afactoryis notlikelytobecalledaninstitute,ouruniversitychoirwillnotbecalledaninstitute.All ofthesearemodern,purpose-geared,formalorganisationswithahierarchicalstructure. The matter has its legal implications, of course, in the sense that our codes of lawandourestablishedadministrativepracticesenshrinecertainusagesofwordssuch as institute, foundation and corporation, limiting their applicability. One might have searchedthereforexamples.Butitdoesnotseemnecessary,asIbelieveitissufficiently clear by now that the notion of institution fits some contexts better than it does otherswhilst,atthesametime,neverlosingitsoriginalbroadsense.Itisasifcertain typesoforganisedformsofbehaviourtypifiedbetterthanothersthatbroadestofall characteristicsofsocieties:theconstitutionofinstitutions.Bycomparingitsdifferent contexts of use we get a sense of how it changes its aspect and how that reveals the sympathiesitcarrieswithinitself. Written into the way in which we have come to use the word ‘institution’, there is a modernist disposition to see society as a formally coherent system that imposes itself upon individuals. We acknowledge that the stuff of human institutions is the recurrentcombinationofmodesofactionwithmodesofthinkingbut,somehow,we see the epitome of that principle embodied in what Weber called the ‘compulsory organizations’ of modern, State-run, Western society. The imperial narrative about world history – to which Frazer adhered with the full force of ‘reason’ – seems to still explain the sympathies that ground the word’s application today, much as, for anthropologists like us at the beginning of the 21st century, that imperial narrative is littlemorethana‘superstition’. Ultimately, in this paper, I aim to contribute to a view of sociality as ‘being in company’.Asthepaperconcludes,Iwillproposeaneurophenomenologicallyredefined conceptofmutuality,where(i)thoughtisconceivedofasaformofactionandwhere (ii) persons are understood not to pre-exist intersubjective attunement. Therefore, I argue against the utopia of the rationalist individual that has dominated the social sciences throughout the 20th century with its representationalist and logocentric conceptionsofmind. Inmanyways,thepaperisconceivedasanalternativeapproachtoinstitutionality to that recently proposed by Pascal Boyer and Michael Bang Petersen (2011).2 As 2 Tomymind,theauthorsdonotquestionsufficientlytheimplicationsoftheconceptualtoolsthey use: individual, marriage, law, reason, etc. For example, the statement that ‘institutional designs aredirectlyfacilitatedbythestructureofhumancognition’(BoyerandPetersen2011:12)turns (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. 480 JOA˜O DE PINA-CABRAL I see it, there is little to doubt in the observation that processes of human physical development impose marginal constraints to all historically evolved forms of human sociation.Howthisoccurredinhistory,however,iswhatweneedtotraceout.Boyer andPetersenassumetheoriesofcausalitythatimplicitlytreatthesortofinformation thatprofessionalhistoriansandethnographershavebeengatheringoverthepastcentury aslargelysecondaryinthefaceof‘real/natural’(biological,economic,material)causes. Now,Darwin’stheoryofevolutionisahistoricistformofexplanationparexcellence. Suchtreatments,therefore,aredeeplycontrarytotheveryspiritofthegeneraltheory theyaimtouphold. Searle and the teleology of institutions Let me start with another recent example that shows how little we have learnt from ourmistakesoverthepastcenturyofsocialscientificthinking.In2010,JohnSearle,the well-known American philosopher, published a small but extremely ambitious book calledMakingtheSocialWorld,wherehebelieveshesucceedsinunearthingnothingless than‘thestructureofhumancivilization’.Intypicalfashion,hestartsfromdisembodied semantics–hiscriticismofCartesianthinkingdoesnotseemtogoasfarastoquestion arepresentationalmodelofmind(cf.Edelman1992).So,hetellsusthat Aninstitutionisasystemofconstitutiverules,andsuchasystemautomatically createsthepossibilityofinstitutionalfacts.ThusthefactthatObamaispresident orthefactthatIamalicenseddriverorthefactthatachessmatchwaswonbya certainpersonandlostbyacertainotherpersonareallinstitutionalfactsbecause theyexistwithinsystemsofconstitutiverules.(2010:10–11) Youwillnoticetheinterestingwayinwhich,muchliketheearlierlisttakenfromthe StanfordEncyclopaediaofPhilosophy,thereisastrangeconsistencyinhisexamples.His examplesaresolidlyrootedinhisownuppermiddle-classAmericanlifeexperience:all of his three cases involve explicit legislation and literate rule making applied to fully individualpersonswhoseengagementinsocietyismadebyrationalcontract. Constitutiverules,Searleargues,aresystemsthatnotonlyregulatewhatisdone, but‘createthepossibilityoftheverybehaviourthattheyregulate’;forexample,when Isay,‘youaremyboss’,Iinstituteinthatwayapreviouslyinexistenthierarchy(2010: 10). According to him, then, institutional reality is created out of such declarations, thatis,speechactsthatchangetheworldbydeclaringthatacertainstateofaffairsis thecase.Whilst,inactualfact,onemightnotneedtoutterthecorrespondingwords, hetellsus,onedoesuselanguageinsuchawayastoassumethestatusfunctionsthat createinstitutions.Thus,heconcludes,‘allofhumaninstitutionalrealityiscreatedand maintainedinexistenceby(representationsthathavethesamelogicalformas)Status Function Declarations’ (2010: 13). His representational institutions are best typified bythelegalistideologythatpervadescontemporarymiddle-classAmericanmodesof thinking. outtobeatruismfor,whilstitisboundtoseemreasonabletomostcontemporaryreaders,the subsequentstructuresofdeterminationthataremadetohangonitare(i)exceedinglysimplisticand (ii)formulatedinahistoricalterms. (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. WHAT IS AN INSTITUTION? 481 The lessons of over 100 years of anthropological research do not seem to have penetratedProf.Searle’sworldview.Contemporaryphilosophicaldebatesconcerning representation(cf.Needham1983;Brooks1991;Clark1997;Chemero2009),anthro- pologicaldebatesconcerningdividuality(cf.Strathern1988;Mosko2010;Pina-Cabral 2010a and 2011) or concerning the argumentative nature of human reasoning (cf. MercierandSperber2011),andpsychologicaldebatesconcerningontogeny(cf.Bra˚ten 2006; Toren 2011) have caused no ‘change of aspect’ in Searle’s use of the notions of ‘institution’,of‘group’,orof‘individual’. Yetwecannotblamehimtoomuch,forthetrapwassetforusfromthestart.This strangewayinwhichtheconceptofinstitutionisfoundatthelogicalrootofallsocial phenomenabutthenisinstantiatedbymodernist,State-associated,legalisticformsof behaviour has a long history in social thinking. Much like Searle’s ‘status function declarations’,thereisateleologicalaspecttotheword‘institution’inpracticallyallof itsuses.Isayteleologicaltomeanthatinstitutionsaresupposedtohaveapurpose,to serveafinality,andtoexistbecauseofthatfinality. The idea is enshrined in the word’s very history. It derives from the Latin word institutum, which means ‘purpose, design, plan, ordinance, instruction, precept’. It originatedintheverbstatuere,meaning‘toestablish,ortocausetostand’.Accordingto theOxfordEnglishDictionary,theword‘institute’hasbeenusedsincetheRenaissance in English and French and it bears four main meanings: firstly, to mean purpose (as in the English expression ‘Satan’s institute’); secondly, to mean something instituted like an established law, a custom, a usage or an organisation; thirdly, a principle or elementofinstruction;andfourthly,asocietyororganisedgroupinstitutedtopromote something of public relevance as well as the house wherein it is based. See how the meaning moves from functional relevance (‘Satan’s institute’), to formalised rules of behaviouransweringthatfunction(aprincipleofinstruction),toapublicorganisation (theInstituteofSocialSciences),tothebuildingwherethatorganisationisbased(Av. An´ıbalBettencourt9,CampoGrande,Lisbon). Embedded in the meanings carried by the word institution, therefore, there is decidedlyanimplicationoffunctionalrelevance:aninstitutionisanorganisationthat servesapurpose.Inshort,ifinstitutionsaretheverybasisofallsociality,asmostsocial thinkers seem to have agreed over the past 100 years, then the foundational fact of society involves finality, an act of will. Society seeking its own existence! This is the essenceofwhatwecallsociocentrism,followinginthisDurkheimandMauss’s(1963) ownexplicitformulationintheiressayonprimitiveclassifications. Institutions exist because of the functions they perform for society; that much seemstobeconsensualeversincethesocialsciencescastawaythedivinenarrativeat thetimeofDarwin.Theyemergefromthedepthsofirrationalityduetotheveryforce of their rational purpose, which imposes itself with its purifying power. But how do thesepurposesimposethemselves?Whatisthesecrethandthatprintsthem?Therewas atimeinwhichitwaspossibletonarrateexplicitlyhowthisworkedoutinhistory. Forexample,thisishowWestermarcktoldthestoryin1908: The original character of the taboo must be looked for not in its civil but in its religious element. It was not the creation of a legislator, but the gradual outgrowthofanimistic beliefs,to which theambition andavariceofchiefsand priestsafterwardsgaveanartificialextension.Butinservingthecauseofavarice andambitionitsubservedthecauseofcivilization,byfosteringtheconceptions (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. 482 JOA˜O DE PINA-CABRAL oftherightsofpropertyandthesanctityofthemarriagetie,–conceptionswhich intimegrewstrongenoughtostandbythemselvesandtoflingawaythecrutch of superstition which in earlier days had been their sole support. For we shall scarcely err in believing that even in advanced societies the moral sentiments, insofarastheyaremerelysentimentsandarenotbasedonaninductionfrom experience,derivemuchoftheirforcefromanoriginalsystemoftaboo.Thuson thetabooweregraftedthegoldenfruitsoflawandmorality,whiletheparentstem dwindledslowlyintothesourcrabsandemptyhusksofpopularsuperstitionon whichtheswineofmodernsocietyarestillcontenttofeed.3(inFrazer1909:27, myemphasis) Wedohaveataleofsociogenesis,then,butithascometoconflictwiththeworld asweexperienceitsincetheendofthecolonialeraandweprefertoelideit.Eversince thelate1960s,weprefertosayofthosewecondonethattheyare‘complex’,elidingthe factthatthisimpliesthattheremainderare‘primitive’.Weallowthesecretsympathies constituted by the imperial narrative to operate unquestioned. Having no other, we allowtheimperialnarrativeofsociogenesistopassinsilencebymeansofwhatFrazer wouldhavecalledsmallactsofsympatheticlogic.Afterall,wetooseemtobefeeding on‘sourcrabsandemptyhusks’. Mauss’ minimalist definition Letusfollowsomeoftheprincipleturningpointsinthehistoryofthewordinstitution. Inanessayon‘religiousfacts’,writtenin1906,Durkheim’sprincipaldisciples,Hubert andMaussdefinetheconceptofinstitutionas‘publicrulesofactionandthought’(in Mauss1968/1969:25).4Theyarguethatbothsacrificeandmagicare,indeed,institutions inthissense:thefirst[sacrifice]inapublicfashion,asthenatureoftherepresentations atstakeareopentoall;thesecond[magic]inalesspublicbutnonethelessstillcollective fashion. For them, as indeed for Durkheim (and it would seem for Searle as well), societyiscomposedoforganicallyseparateindividualswho,inasense,abdicateoftheir independence in the name of the collective: ‘We believe we have (...) demonstrated how,inmagic,theindividualonlythinks,onlyactsundertheguidanceoftraditionor pressedbyacollectivesuggestion,oratleastbyasuggestionthatheprovidestohimself underthepressureofthecollectivity’(1968[1906],I:25). In fact, they explicitly want to defend themselves against the attack by certain colleagueswhohadaccusedthemofhavingoverextendedtheirexpertiseassociologists becausetheymadeastudyofcategories,whilstsociologistsshouldlimitthemselvesto institutions.Buttheyexplicitlyrefusetoseparateactingfromthinking: Sociologists,itwouldseem,mustlimitthemselvestogroupsandtheirtraditional practices. But these people seem to forget that there are ways of thinking in commonaswellaswaysofactingincommon.Calendars[forexample]aresocial thingsaswellasfeasts,signs,ortelepathicphenomena,justasmuchasexpiations 3 Thissimileofhislesscivilisedcoevalsto‘swine’mightbesoftenedifweconcedethatheisassuming thatpigsarefedoncrabapplesandacorns,aswasperhapsthecaseinhisday. 4 InOeuvres(1967,I),HubertandMauss(inMauss1968/1969)‘L’analysedesfaitsre´ligieux’.All translationsoftextsreferencedinFrencheditionsaremyownresponsibility. (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. WHAT IS AN INSTITUTION? 483 forbadluck.Alloftheseareinstitutions.Thenotionsofsacred,soul,time,etc., are all equally institutions because, as a matter of fact, they do not exist in the mindoftheindividualotherwisethandressedintheformsthattheytookfrom specificsocieties.Theindividualreceivesthem,througheducation,intraditional formulae.Theyare,therefore,theobjectsofsociology.(1968[1906],I:36) Notethefascinatingwayinwhichtheauthorsareexplicitabouttheepistemology of their undertaking: they explain, in a frank manner, that later social theorists are pronetoabandon,thatideasassuchactuallyoccurintheheadsofindividualpersonsas representationsandthatthecollectivenatureoftheseisconstitutedbythewaytheyare ‘dressed’–‘reveˆtuesdeformesqu’ellesontprisesdansdessocie´tesde´termine´es’,thatis theiractualformulation(1968[1906],I:36).Wefindhereechoesofthewayinwhich, forMauss,inhisessayontheperson,individualsinprimitivesocietyare‘masked’by therolestheyaresupposedtoassumeinordertobecomelegitimatesocialagents. Inatextabouttheobjectsandmethodsofsociology,nowinco-authorshipwithPaul Falconnet,5 Maussexplainsthat‘eachindividualencounters[thesehabitsorcustoms] already formed, so to speak instituted, since he is not their author, since he receives themfromtheoutside,theyarethuspreexisting’(hisemphasis,1969[1901],III:149). Theword‘institution’,therefore,isbestusedtodescribe‘analreadyinstitutedsetof actionsandideasthatindividualsfindbeforethemandthatimposethemselvesonthem to a greater or lesser extent’ (1969 [1901], III: 150). And, they proceed: ‘Institution, therefore, in the social order, plays the same role as function in the biological order; andinthesamewaythatlifescienceisthescienceofvitalfunctions,sothescienceof societyisthescienceofinstitutionsthusdescribed’(1969[1901],III:150). ThereisacuriousinconsistencyinMauss’swritingsovertheyearssince,whilsthe insists on the way in which institutions include both actions and thoughts, he never abandons the separation between what he and Durkheim called the ‘physiology of practice’definedas‘socialactions,socialpracticesandinstitutions’andthe‘physiology ofrepresentation’definedas‘ideasandcollectivefeelings’(1969[1901],III:208).Theirs isadecidedlyneo-Kantiananthropology. In Durkheim’s earlier work De la division du travail social, written in 1893, the conceptofinstitutionisintroducedbymeansofadiscussionofmedievalcorporations, whichareseenasthebasisofthemodernstate.Theyareinstitutionsinsofarasthey persistthroughtimeindependentlyoftheirparticularmanifestations(1967[1897],I:21) andtotheextentthattheyfulfilthepurposesforwhichtheywerecreated(1967[1897], I:25).Hereagainwewitnessthetendencytojumpfrom(i)aminimalistprincipleof socialityto(ii)itssupposedlyperfectinstantiationinformalmodernorganisations:‘For aprofessionalmoralityandlawtoestablishitselfinthedifferenteconomicprofessions itwasnecessaryforthecorporation,insteadofremainingaconfusedaggregatewithout unity, to become (or rather to become again) a defined, organised group; in a word, a public institution’ (1967 [1897], I: 19). So, we conclude that, for the old master, a public institution is ‘a defined, organised group’. This tendency to associate (i) with (ii) constitutes a semantic slippage6 that runs through the whole history of the word ‘institution’ in the 20th century, as it is what allows it to carry the meanings that we haveallbecomeusedtoattributetoit. 5 InOeuvres(1967,III),FalconnetandMauss‘LaSociologie.ObjetetMe´thode’. 6 Iusetheexpressionhereinthesenseofdoublereadingandverbalassociation. (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. 484 JOA˜O DE PINA-CABRAL In fact, in Durkheim, the evolutionary nature of the association is quite explicit eventhoughitsformulationsoundslessimperialtoourearsthantheformulationsby FrazerandWestermarckpresentedabove.Hedescribesforusaprocesswhereby,inthe historyofhumanity,basicinstitutionsareprogressivelyoverlaidbyotherinstitutions without fully disappearing. Thus, ‘for the division of labour to be able to develop, it wasnecessaryformentocastofftheyokeofheredity,forprogresstobreakcastesand classes.Theprogressivedisappearanceofthelattertends,infact,toprovetherealityof thatemancipation;sinceonecannotverywellseehow,ifheredityhadnotlostitsrights overtheindividual,itmighthavebeenweakenedasaninstitution’(1967[1897],II:71). Buttheseancientinstitutionsremain astheground,so to speak,uponwhich the othermoreperfectinstitutionsareseated. Ancient institutions never fully disappear before new institutions, to the point of leaving no trace of themselves. They persist, not only as survivals, but also because something of the needs to which they responded continues to persist. Effective neighbourhood will ever constitute a link among men; therefore, the politicalandsocialorganizationonaterritorialbasewillcertainlysurvive.Only, itwillnothaveanylongeractualpreponderance,preciselybecausethatlinkhas lostsomeofitsforce.(1967[1897],I:37) Weber’s compulsory organisations The Durkheimian formulation is arguably the most influential use of the word ‘institution’ in sociological and anthropological theory over the 20th century. For example,inanextremelyinfluentialessay,theHuxleyMemorialLectureof1951,called ‘The Comparative Method in Social Anthropology’ (1952: 15–22), Radcliffe-Brown againusesthewordinstitutioninthisbroadDurkheimiansensebyreferringtojoking relationshipsandtomoietyexogamyasinstitutions.Thisminimalistsenseoftheword, best suited to Mauss’s definition of ‘public rules of action and thought’ might have wontheday.Still,aswesawinSearle,andasweseeineverydaysocioscientificlingo all around us, the other meaning enshrined in the Stanford Encyclopaedia definition (‘complexsocialformsthatreproducethemselves...’)isequallyimportant.Forclarity sake,wewillrefertothissecondmeaningasthe‘complexdefinition’. IstronglysuspectthatthisdefinitionisonthewholeduetotheinfluenceofMax Weber’sworkwhich,whilstroughlycontemporarywiththatofDurkheimandMauss, onlycametohaveanimpactonthesocialsciencesoutsideGermanophonecirclesafter the1930sand,mostdecidedly,throughtheagencyofTalcottParsons,aftertheSecond World War. Certainly, in anthropology, as Marshall Sahlins has recently reminded us (2011:6–7),CliffordGeertzandDavidSchneider,studentsofParsonsatHarvard,went ontobecomeextremelyinfluentialworld-wide.Surelytheyhadaninfluenceinthis.7 Theneoinstitutionalistschoolineconomyisespeciallyresponsiblefordeveloping the line of interpretation of the word that is more associated with Weber’s complex definitionandlesswithMauss’minimalistdefinition.Iwouldbetotallyoutofmydepth, 7 Itisinterestinghowthismodifiesthemorecommon‘Boas,Benedict,Mead’pedigreeof‘culture’ thathereproducedearlieronintheintroductiontohisinfluentialshortbookHistoricalMetaphors (Sahlins1981). (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists. WHAT IS AN INSTITUTION? 485 however,ifIevenpretendedlightlytopresenthereeconomicneoinstitutionalism.8So IwilllimitmyselftocallingyourattentiontothefactthattheactualwordthatWeber usedwasnot‘institution’butAnstalten–atermthathardlybearstheimplicationsthat characterisetheLatinwordthatcametotranslateitinFrenchandEnglishafterWeber’s impactonsocialthinkinginthesecondhalfofthe20thcentury. In Weber’s Economy and Society (1968 [1956]), the translators9 decided that the concept of Anstalten should be translated as ‘institutions’, even although for Weber the proper definition of the term would have been closer to ‘compulsory organizations’. The term Anstalt (feminine noun) means roughly ‘establishment’. It comesfromAnstellenmeaning‘toengage,tohire,toemploy,tostaff’which,inturn, isverycloselylinkedtoEinstallenmeaning‘toadjust,tohire,toengage,toconfigure’. Thus, the German word – meaning ‘to make arrangements for’ or ‘to get ready to’ – alsobearsthepurpose-geared(teleological)implicationsimplicitintheLatintermbut, insteadofthearchitecturalmetaphor,itseemstofocusmoreonhumanengagement. In order to define Anstalten, Weber starts with the notion of ‘organization’, that is, as he puts it, ‘a social relationship which is either closed or limits the admission of outsiders (and whose) regulations are enforced by specific individuals (...) with representativepowers’.Anstaltenare‘compulsoryorganizations’,thatis,‘organizations wherethereisapersonorpersonsinauthoritycarryingintoeffecttheordergoverning theorganization’(1968[1956],I:48). Forhim,acompulsoryorganisationmustbea‘formalorganization’,thatis,itmust possess‘acontinuouslyandrationallyoperatingstaff’(1968[1956],I:52).Finally,heis specific:‘anorganizationwhichimposes,withinaspecifiablesphereofoperations,its order(withrelativesuccess)onallactionconformingwithcertaincriteriawillbecalled a compulsory organization or association (Anstalt)’ (1968 [1956], I: 52). Note that, here, ‘compulsory organization’, ‘association’, and in English translation ‘institution’ areheldtobesynonyms.Infact,thewordinstitution,whichdoesexistinGermanand isgiveninmostGermandictionariesasasynonymofAnstalt,onlyappearsinWeber’s workpassingly. For Weber, the compulsory organisations par excellence are the State, ‘with its subsidiaryheterocephalousorganizations’,andtheChurch,andwhethertheindividual joins these institutions voluntarily or not does not change the situation. Note the differenceofimplicationsfromtheDurkheimianuseoftheword,whereindividualsare mouldedbyinstitutionsandyetcannotbutjointhem,sincethatistheverycondition ofsociality. Elsewhere Weber gives us a more complete definition of Anstalten which fully confirmsthisreading(andheretheeditors,RothandWittich,actuallyalertustothe factthatthewordhastwomeanings:institutionandcompulsoryorganisation):‘groups inwhich(i)membershipdependsonobjectivecriteriaregardlessofthedeclaredwillof thoseincluded(incontrasttothe‘voluntaryassociation’)and(ii)rationallyestablished rules and an enforcement apparatus codetermine individual action (in contrast to amorphousconsensualgroupingwhichlackarationallyestablishedorder)’(1968[1956], II:1380).Evidently,suchadescriptionfailstoapplytoMauss’minimalistinstitutions suchascalendars,marriages,magicbeliefs,etc. 8 TheirsistheinspirationofBoyerandPeteresen(2011). 9 AmongwhomTalcottParsons. (cid:2)C 2011EuropeanAssociationofSocialAnthropologists.

Description:
to that recently proposed by Pascal Boyer and Michael Bang Petersen are directly facilitated by the structure of human cognition' (Boyer and University of Lisbon and Socius-ISEG, on 2/3 December 2010, convened by Susana.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.