Ways a World Might Be METAPHYSICAL AND ANTI-METAPHYSICAL ESSAYS C. RoBERT STALNAKER Clarendon Press · Oxford OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6DP Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship. and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Oar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Sao Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York (QRobert C. Stalnaker 2003 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2003 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department. Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available ISBN <H9-925t487 (hbk.) ISBN o-19-9251495 (pbk.) 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2 Typeset by Kolam Information Services Private Limited, Pondicherry, India. Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper by Biddies Ltd., Guildford & King's Lynn In memory of Louis 0. Mink Carl G. Hempel H. Paul Grice David K. Lewis Preface All but two of the papers included in this collection have been previously published. I thank the editors and publishers for permission to reprint them. Details of the sources are given on page xii. In most cases, the papers have been only lightly edited, but Chapter 3-a dialogue on impossible worlds-has been expanded in response to comments by David Lewis, and postscripts have been added to Chapters 5 and 8 on some technical issues discussed in those papers. Thanks to Andy Egan for invaluable editorial assistance in preparing the papers and updating the references, and for advice on matters of both substance and detail. Thanks to Peter Momtchiloff of Oxford University Press for his good advice about the selection of papers, among many other things, and for his support. I can't thank by name all of the many teachers, colleagues, and students who have helped me to get clearer about the issues discussed in these papers, so let me thank them collectively, and mention just a few who stand out. Saul Kripke must take some of the blame for the preoccupation with possibilities that is evident in the papers in this collection, since I was first brought to appreciate the clarifying power of the framework of possible worlds in his seminar at Princeton in 1964-5 (where ideas about Wittgen stein on following a rule mingled with the ideas that were later to take form in Naming and Necessity). The influence of his arguments in Naming and Necessity on my ideas about the relations between modal, semantic, and epistemological concepts will be evident throughout these papers, most explicitly in Part IV. Four of the papers were originally written for festschrifts, and I am in debted to the philosophers celebrated in those collections - Paul Benacerraf, Ed Gettier, Ruth Marcus, and Sydney Shoemaker - all people with remark able philosophical minds who have influenced my thinking on metaphysical matters through their work, their example, and philosophical discussion over the years. The paper on supervenience (Chapter 5) grew out of a metaphysics sem inar at MIT taught jointly with Judy Thomson, and my thoughts about this issue and others in metaphysics have benefitted from her incisive arguments and analyses. Ned Block's insights into questions about consciousness and concepts have helped me to see many things I hadn't seen before. Collabor ation with Ned, first on a seminar on consciousness, and then on a joint article (Block and Stalnaker 1999), was important to my understanding of issues both about metaphysical and conceptual possibility, and about viii Preface phenomenal consciousness. Some of the ideas in Chapters to, 11, 12, and 13 have their source in that collaboration. Anyone who spends his or her time thinking and writing about philo sophical problems develops, along the way, a duster of prejudices and pre occupations, methods and styles of argument that constitutes, one hopes, a general view of things. Where it comes from and how it develops is hard to say, but the examples provided by teachers and colleagues that we both follow and react against obviously play a crucial role in shaping our philo sophical personae. The four philosophers to whose memory this book is dedicated played a particularly important role in my own philosophical development, both through the substance of their ideas and arguments, and by the force of their personalities. Let me say a little about each of them. Louis Mink was my main undergraduate teacher of philosophy at Wes leyan University. He was at the center of the intellectual life of the univer sity, and had many students who went on to distinguished careers in philosophy. Louis had an insatiable intellectual curiosity, and showed us how to think philosophically about everything. With him I studied Kant and St Augustine, Collingwood and logical positivism, the philosophy of history and social science, among other things. He fed my ambivalence about metaphysics by getting me to appreciate both the richness of the philosophical tradition and the power of the logical empiricist critique. Louis has always been, for me, a model of what a philosopher should be. I first encountered the work of C. G. Hempel in high school, browsing in Tames R. Newman's anthology, The World of Mathematics. His essays re printed there, 'On the Nature of Mathematical Truth' and 'Geometry and Empirical Science' struck me as models of clarity and good sense, as they still do, and helped to draw me into philosophy. When I got to graduate school I benefitted from his lively seminars, patient and painstaking com ments on my work, his writings on explanation, confirmation and concept formation, and most of all from his example of clarity of mind, intellectual integrity, and generosity. I was fortunate to be his student and teaching assistant. Paul Grice was never my teacher or departmental colleague, but I got to know him when he made an extended visit to the University of Illinois, where I was teaching, in 1970, and during a memorable summer institute at Irvine in 1971. I had earlier been able to attend just one of his William lames Lectures, but I vividly remember the intellectual excitement of the occasion, the feeling that we were watching a great philosophical mind in action. Grice was an opportunistic and experimental thinker, eclectic in his methods and interests, following out lines of thought to see where they led him. But a coherent philosophical vision emerged - a view about the rela tions between language, thought, and action - that has greatly influenced my own way of thinking about these issues. Preface lX I began corresponding with David Lewis in 1968, when we discovered that we had developed, independently, similar theories of counterfactuals, and we had many fruitful and enjoyable discussions over the years from that time until just before his death in 2001. David was, of course, an unabashed metaphysician, and one might think that he was untroubled by the kind of mixed feelings about the subject that I have expressed, but he did say, in the introduction to his first collection of papers: 'I should have liked to be a piecemeal, unsystematic philosopher, offering independent proposals on a variety of topics. It was not to be' (Lewis 1983a: ix). In a sense, it was to be, for even though David's many philosophical contributions grew out of his metaphysical system, and fit together with remarkable coherence, he was careful to show us when an analysis or an argument was detachable by one who didn't buy into the whole system. His work was widely applied, both within and outside of philosophy, by researchers who would not have thought that metaphysics could be relevant to their work. The influence of David's work, and I hope of his example as well, will be seen in every paper in this collection. Those who knew these four philosophers will agree that they were radic ally different from each other in personal and intellectual style, but they are all paradigm cases of philosophers, and had much in common. They all had a passion for philosophy, and a focus on philosophical issues. Style and method emerged from grappling with them. While each had his own philo sophical agenda, they were all adept at seeing things from other points of view, and were generous and effective in showing others how to advance their own projects. They all had a sense of humor and a sense of fun: they knew how to take philosophy seriously without taking themselves too ser iously. They saw, and helped us to see, that philosophy is an activity that is both enjoyable and worthwhile. Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2003 Contents Details off irst publication xii Introduction 1 I. Ways and Worlds 23 1. Possible Worlds 25 2. On what Possible Worlds could not be 40 3· Impossibilities 55 11. Carving up Logical Space 4· Anti-essentialism 71 5· Varieties of Supervenience 86 Ill. Identity in and across Possible Worlds 109 6. Counterparts and Identity 111 J. Vague Identity 133 8. The Interaction of Modality with Quantification and Identity 144 IV. Semantics, Metasemantics, and Metaphysics t63 9. Reference and Necessity 165 10. On considering a Possible World as Actual 188 11. Conceptual Truth and Metaphysical Necessity 201 V. Subjective Possibilities 217 12. Comparing Qualia across Persons 219 13. What is it like to be a Zombie? 239 14. On Thomas Nagel's Objective Self 253 References 277 Index 283 Details of First Publication A preliminary version of 'Possible Worlds' was published in Nous, to (1976). The version reprinted here is chapter 3 of my Inquiry (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford Books, MIT Press, 1984), 43-58. Reprinted with the permission of Basil Blackwell Ltd and the MIT Press. 'On what Possible Worlds Could Not Be', in Adam Morton and Stephen Stich (eds.), Benacerraf and his Critics, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd., 1996). Reprinted with the permission of Basil Blackwell Ltd. 'Impossibilities', Philosophical Topics 24 (1996). Reprinted with the permis sion of the editor. 'Anti-essentialism', Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1979). Reprinted with the permission of the editor. 'Varieties of Supervenience', Philosophical Perspectives 10: Metaphysics (1996). Reprinted with the permission of Basil Blackwell Ltd 'Counterparts and Identity', Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 11, Studies in Essentialism (1987). Reprinted with the permission of the University of Min nesota Press. 'Vague Identity' in David Austin (ed.), Philosophical Analysis (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988). Reprinted with the kind permission of Kluwer Academic Publishers. 'The Interaction of Modality with Quantification and Identity', in W. Sinnott Armstrong, D. Raffman, and N. Asher (eds.), Modality, Morality and Belief: Essays in honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994). Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press. 'Reference and Necessity', in Crispin Wright and Bob Hale (eds.), Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd., 1997). Reprinted with the permission of Basil Blackwell Ltd. 'On considering a Possible World as Actual; Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (2001). Reprinted with the permission of the editor. 'Conceptual Truth and Metaphysical Necessity' is published here for the first time. 'Comparing Qualia across Persons', Philosophical Topics 26 (2ooo). Re printed with the permission of the editor. 'What is it Like to be a Zombie?', in John Hawthorne and Tamar Szabo Gandler (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002). Reprinted with the permission of Oxford University Press. 'On Thomas Nagel's Objective Self' is published here for the first time.
Description: