ebook img

TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 1. In Proslogium II, St. Anselm argues as follows PDF

60 Pages·2011·4.71 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 1. In Proslogium II, St. Anselm argues as follows

APPENDIX TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 1. In Proslogium II, St. Anselm argues as follows: And assuredly that than which no greater being can be conceived, cannot exist in the understanding alone. For suppose it exists in the understanding alone: then it can be conceived to exist in reality; which is greater. Therefore, if that than which nothing greater can be conceived exists in the understanding alone, the very being than which nothing greater can be conceived, is one, than which a greater can be conceived. But obviously this is impossible. Hence, there is no doubt that there exists a being, than which nothing greater can be conceived, and it exists both in the understanding and in reality. 1 I shall take "exists in the understanding alone" to mean "is logically possible but not actual", and I shall take "a being than which no greater can be conceived" to mean "a being than which no greater being is logically possible", i.e., "a maximally great being". Moreover, I shall take "[If X] exists in the understanding alone, [then] it can be conceived to exist in reality, which is greater" to mean "If X is merely logically possible, then it would be greater if it were actual"; and I shall take it that the bearer of the predicate "would be greater if it were actual" is, at least, a logically possible object. Given these interpretations, Anselm's argument can be restated as follows: (1) If there were a logically possible object which is a maximally great being and it were merely logically possible (rather than both logically possible and actual), then it would be greater if it were actual. But (2) "X is a logically possible object which is maximally great" entails "X could not (and would not) be greater under any conditions, including its actuality". 141 142 APPENDIX So (3) there is no logically possible object which is both maximally great and merely logically possible. But (4) there is in fact a logically possible object which is maximally great (namely, God). Hence (5) there is a logically possible object (i.e., God) who is not merely logically possible but both logically possible and actual as well. 2. Premisses (1) and (4) of this argument are, of course, contro versial. Premiss (4) is false unless (a) there are logically possible objects and (b) God is among their number. However, I have defended the thesis that there are logically possible objects in 7.5, and I have discussed the question whether God is logically possible in Chapters 6 and 9; so I shall say no more about premiss (4) here. But now what are we to make of premiss (1) - the claim that if there were a merely logically possible object which is maximally great, then it would be greater if it were actual? Isn't that claim suspiciously similar to the claim that, e.g., a merely logically possible glass of beer would, ceteris paribus, contain more beer if it were actual? Reflection will show that the answer is "No". Qua glass of beer, the only difference between a merely logically possible glass of beer and an actual one is just that the former is merely logically possible and the latter is actual. Actuality is not a beer-increasing property and being merely logically possible is not a beer-diminishing property. However, things are otherwise with respect to greatness. Actuality is a greatness-increasing property relative to God, as the following will show. We can say with perfect propriety about some individuals (e.g., St. Francis) that it is better than not that they are (or were) actual. And it is even clearer that it is better than not that God, a maximally great being, be actual. But maximal greatness entails having every property TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 143 which is such that it is better than not that an omnipotent, omniscient and perfectly good being have it. Hence, even though, for most predicates, it is false that the actuality of the object which bears them increases the amount or degree in which they are possessed, actuality is a greatness-increasing property relative to God (though not relative to, say, Hitler). But now it is surely a necessary truth that if an individual, X, lacks a given greatness-increasing property, G, then, ceteris paribus, it would be greater if it possessed G. It follows that if God is merely logically possible, then he would be greater if he were actual. It is of note that, even if we subscribe to a relativistic interpretation of actuality - even if we hold that "X is actual" always expands into "X is actual relative to a given possible world, W' and that, hence, the possible world, which is actual from our point of view, has no privileged status with respect to actuality, my argument will still hold. For, whatever may be thought of other possible worlds, it is plainly better than not that God exist in the world which is actual from our point of view. And, again, it is a necessary truth that a maximally great being would have every property which is such that it is better than not that he possesses it. But, finally, does God exist, not only in our world, but in every possible world? Anselm's Proslogium II argument does not require this to be the case; but if it is not the case, then God does not exist with SS necessity. And it is not, perhaps, just intuitive that God occupies every possible world. (Aren't there possible worlds in which, e.g., the only non-divine things are mud and rain? And if so, is it really better than not that God occupy those worlds?) But fortunately we need not simply rely on our intuitions here, since Chapter 5 provides us with a demonstration that if God exists in one possible world, then he exists, with SS necessity and qua maximally great, in all possible worlds, including our own. (If it is clear that God would not inhabit worlds in which the only non-divine things were, e.g., mud and rain, then, if God exists in some possible world, so much the worse for 144 APPENDIX mud-and-rain 'worlds'. They are demonstrably not possible.) 3. In Responsio I, Anselm presents the following argument: Furthermore, ifit can be conceived at all, it must exist. For no one who denies or doubts the existence of a being than which a greater is inconceivable [i.e., God] denies or doubts that if it did exist, its non-existence would be impossible. For otherwise it would not be a being than which a greater cannot be conceived. But as to whatever can be conceived but does not exist - if there were such a being, its non-existence ... would be possible. Therefore if a being than which a greater is inconceivable can even be conceived, it cannot be non-existent.2 Norman Malcolm has written as follows about this argument: Let me summarize the proof. If God, a being greater than which cannot be conceived, does not exist then He cannot come into existence. For if He did He would either have been caused to come into existence or have happened to come into existence, and in either case He would be a limited being, which by our conception of Him He is not. Since He cannot come into existence, if He does not exist His existence is impossible .... Thus God's existence is either impossible or necessary. It can be the former only if the concept of such a being is se1f contradictory or in some way logically absurd. Assuming that this is not so, it follows that He necessarily exists.3 What Malcolm writes here is a considerable departure from what Anselm actually says. Anselm does not claim, in the envisaged argument, that if God does not exist, then his existence is impossible. This is in fact demonstrable. (One way of demonstrating it is to point out that (1) the denial of the conclusion of modal argument M (Chapter 5), namely, that God exists, entails the denial of one of M's premisses and (2) the premiss which affIrms God's logical possibility is the best candidate for being rejected.) But Anselm does not demonstrate it - at least not in connexion with the present proof.4 Another defect in Malcolm's interpretation is that Anselm evidently intends to reach his conclusion via modus tollens, but there is no hint of this in Malcolm's interpretation.5 4. Let me say more about the modus tollens character of Anselm's proof. One not implausible interpretation of the proof is as follows: TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 145 (1) If God does not exist, then if God existed, his non-existence would be possible. But (2) if God existed, then his non-existence would not be possible. So (3) the antecedent of (1) is false, i.e., God exists. (From (1) and (2) by modus tollens.) On this interpretation, Anselm holds that "If God existed, his non existence would be possible" is contradicted by "If God existed, his non-existence would not be possible". But in fact it is doubtful that these are contradictories. For, again, it is demonstrable that if God does not exist, then it is logically impossible that he exists. So if God does not exist, the antecedents of the allegedly contradictory condi tionals are neessary falsehoods. But then, if we treat them as counterfactual conditionals, they are, if David K. Lewis is right,6 both vacuously true and, hence, not contradictories. And, of course, the same is true of them if we take them to be material conditionals. But Anselm cannot presuppose that it is false that God does not exist without begging the question. So, on the present interpretation, Anselm's argument is a spectacular failure. But there is another, more charitable interpretation of Anselm, on which it turns out to be true that if God does not exist, then it is possible that his non-existence is both possible and not possible. And the (necessarily true) denial of this consequent entails, by modus tollens, the denial of the antecedent, i.e., it entails that God exists. On this interpretation, we capture the modus tolle ns character of Anselm's argument, while avoiding the mistake which is embodied in the first interpretation. In presenting the new interpretation, I shall avoid using counterfactual conditionals, since the argument really does not need them. I have the following interpretation in mind: (1) It is necessarily true that if God exists, then his non existence is logically impossible. 146 APPENDIX Hence (2) if God does not exist, then it is necessarily true that if God exists, then his non-existence is logically impossible. (Since the consequent of the conditional is necessarily true, it is entailed by every proposition, including the antecedent.) So (3) if God does not exist, then each possible world is such that if God exists there, then his non-existence is logically impossible there. (4) There is a possible world in which God exists. So (5) if God does not exist, then there is a possible world in which his non-existence is logically impossible. (From (3) and (4) by modus ponens.) But now assume that (6) God does not exist. Then (7) there is a possible world in which God does not exist and, hence, in which God's non-existence is logically possible. But (8) what is logically possible in one possible world is logically possible in all possible worlds: every possible world is such that God's non-existence is logically possible there. Hence (9) if God does not exist, then there is a possible world in which God's non-existence is both logically impossible and logically possible. (From (5) and (8).) But (10) the consequent of (9) is false. So (11) the antecedent of (9) is false, i.e., God exists. (From (9) and (10) by modus tollens.) 5. So goes the charitable interpretation of Anselm's argument. The TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 147 only controversial premisses are (1), (4), and (8). (1) and (4) have been defended in Chapters 5, 6, and 9; and the following is a proof of (8): If a philosopher claims that some proposition, p, which is possibly true in the actual world is necessarily false in another possible world, then he owes us an example of such a proposition; and it is very unlikely that such an example can be cited. So what is possibly true in the actual world is possibly true in all other possible worlds. And if someone claims that our world is special in that respect, then he owes us an explanation of why that should be so; and it is very doubtful that he can produce such an explanation. Actually, as we saw in Chapter 5, premisses (1) and (4) alone entail that God exists: Anselm's argument is unnecessarily complicated. But the surprising thing is not Anselm's lack of elegance, but the essential soundness of his 11th century modal intuitions. NOTES PREFACE 1 Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1974). 2 See, for example, Plantinga, 'Is Belief in God Properly Basic?', Nous XV (March, 1981), and 'Is Belief in God Rational?' in Rationality and Religious Belief, ed. C. Delaney (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1979). CHAPTER 1 1 I have discussed this topic in detail in 'An Examination of the 'Soul-Making' Theodicy', Amercan Philosophical Quarterly 7 (1970) and 'Do Theodicists Mean What They Say?' Philosophy 49 (1974). 2 Another way of meeting the objection is just to affirm that all that God has brought about with respect to nature is the 'singularity' which gave rise to the big bang, and that it is doubtful that any scientific laws were in effect at that time and afortiori doubtful that God's actions violated any scientific laws. However, I prefer the approach which I present in the text, since (1) it is unwise for religionists to commit themselves to scientific hypotheses which are far from certain and, indeed, in a state of flux, and (2) my approach in the text explains how God could have sometimes intervened in nature after the big bang; and this will be welcomed by the many theists who believe, or would like to believe, that he has done so. 3 Someone may wish to say here that God's not making us clairvoyant is itself logically necessary for E. But the person who makes this claim in effect abandons the envisaged attempt to specify Es nature. I shall, for simplicity, henceforth ignore this complication. 4 See W. V. Quine, The Ways of Paradox, (New York: Random House, 1966), p.4. CHAPTER 2 1 William L. Rowe, The Cosmological Argument (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton Univer sity Press, 1975). All Chapter 2 references to Rowe's writing but one will be to this book. 2 It should be pointed out that Clarke would not be satisfied with the thesis that, since, e.g., sets are logically necessary beings, all of reality does not consist merely 148 NOTES 149 of contingent things. For Clarke wants to establish the conclusion, not just that there is a logically necessary being, but a logically necessary being who is a cause of contingent things. 3 See Rowe, pp. 222-269. 4 For simplicity, I am assuming, throughout my discussion of Clarke's argument, that all contingent things are subject to causal explanation, i.e., I am ignoring, for the time being, the exceptions which are found in quantum mechanics. 5 Rather than states of affairs. The reason for this qualifier can be found on pp. 97-114. See also pp. 149-151. See note 5. 6 7 William L. Rowe, Philosophy of Religion, An Introduo::tion (Belmont, California: Dickenson, 1978), p. 57. 8 There is a question which even more obviously does not have a true answer, given that the only true answer would refer to a cause outside the envisaged set, viz., "Why are there any causes at all?" 9 Actually, however, Clarke's subsequent argument for the infinity of the logically necessary cause (pp. 227-233), which is in essence an argument of St. Anselm which I shall discuss in Chapter 6, should, for a reason I shall present there, be taken as an argument that God is in fact essentially disembodied. 10 Perhaps it would be better to say that there is a prima facie case against the existence ofthe envisaged series, but one which can, in the end, be overthrown by science. CHAPTER 3 Though, instead of considering the more specific claim that the eye is camera-like, I Plantinga considers the claim that the universe resembles "the productions of human contrivance" (p. 97), inasmuch as "it exhibits curious adaptation of means to ends" (p. 101). See Alvin Plantinga, God and Other Minds (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1967), Chapters 4 and 10. 2 David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion in The Empiricists (Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1974), pp. 466-469. 3 Ibid., pp. 459-461. 4 God and Other Minds, p. 104. 5 Ibid., pp. 104-106. 6 Ibid., p. 102. Another pseudo-argument which this description fits (which is cited by Plantinga on pp. 101-102) is: (1) Every member of the class ofChevrolets plus the universe, of which we know whether or not it is the product of intelligent design, is indeed the product of intelligent design. 150 NOTES (2) The universe is a member of the class of Chevrolets plus the universe. So (3) probably the universe is the product of intelligent design. 7 A similar argument shows that what is wrong with the pseudo-argument cited in note 6 is that there are some members of the class of Chevrolets plus the universe (namely, the random configurations cited above) about which we know that they are not the products of design; so we know that there is no nomic connexion between being a member of that class and being designed. CHAPTER 4 I Kurt Baier, The Moral Point of View, abridged edition (New York: Random House, 1965), p. 150. 2 Ibid., p. 156. 3 Actually, things are a bit more complicated. The suicidally depressed patient harms himself by committing suicide if, even though he does not desire continued life at the time of his suicide, he would, in the normal course of events, have come to desire (and acquire) continued life in the future. Hence the reader should add to my subsequent definition of 'hedonist', "a person about whom it is false that he would have come to desire (and acquire) moral innocence, were it not for his present misdeeds". Whether there are in fact such people is not crucial to my central argument, for a reason which will shortly emerge. 4 The entailment does not go the other way. A child is not harmed by the boredom which sometimes accompanies his piano practice, even though he strongly desires its absence as an end-in-itseIf. 5 See David K. Lewis, Counterfactuals (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1973), pp. 24-26. I have in mind Lewis's possible world analysis of counterfactuals. See the book 6 referred to in the preceding note. 7 According to The Compact Edition of the Oxford English Dictionary (p. 1964), 'oblige' means "to bind by ... a moral ... tie, to render liable ... ". According to The Random House Dictionary oft he English Language (p. 917), 'oblige' means (1) "to require or constrain" and (2) "to bind morally ... ". There are, of course, other senses of 'oblige'. The latter dictionary gives these alternative senses: "(a) to make (an action, policy, etc.) necessary ... : 'Your recalcitrance obliges firmness on my part'; (b) to place under a debt of gratitude: obligate; (c) to favor or accommodate: 'Mr. Weems will oblige us with a song'; (d) to be kindly accommodating; help out). It is plain, however, that none of these alternative senses is at all a plausible candidate for the meaning of 'morally oblige(d)'. A review of various major dictionaries reveals no ambiguity in the term 'morally obliged' which is analogous

Description:
the time being, the exceptions which are found in quantum mechanics And, though that is compatible with the main thrust of my argument, I think it . 1 Haldane and Ross, The Philosophical Works of Descartes, Vol. Swinburne, Richard: Chapter II, The Problem of Evil', The Existence of God.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.