TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE AS NEOLIBERAL APPARATUS: POWER, SUBJECTIVITY AND SACRIFICIAL VIOLENCE Josh Bowsher Thesis submitted to the University of Nottingham for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy 2015 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am grateful to many people, without whom this thesis would not have been possible. First and foremost, I would like to thank my supervisors, Dr. Colin Wright and Dr. Tracey Potts, who have been extremely supportive of this project and whose knowledge and experience have shaped my thinking in innumerable ways. I also thank the School of Cultures, Languages and Area Studies at the University of Nottingham for supporting my research with funding that has allowed me to complete the project. I would also like to extend my gratitude to the staff and students at the Centre for Critical Theory at the University of Nottingham. Since I arrived there in 2010 to begin my MA, the Centre has always felt a little bit like home. Thanks to all for a warm, friendly environment where it has been possible to think creatively and, above all, to share in our thinking. In particular, I’d like to thank Stefanie Petschick, Tom Harding, Joe Willis, and David Eckersley. Quite apart from them all being a lot of fun, it has been wonderful to learn in the company of such talented critical thinkers. I’d also like to thank my family: my parents, Andii and Tracy, my brother Ben, and my sister Bekih, for their support, without which I would have surely given up a long time before now. Thank you. Finally, I’d like to thank my partner in crime, Georgie, whose support, kindness and, above all, patience has helped me along the way, but particularly during the final months. Thanks to you for listening to me ramble with a smile, and always seeming to know precisely what to say. [i] ABSTRACT This thesis aims to critically conceptualise the relationship between transitional justice and the project of neoliberal globalisation, which, since the end of the Cold War, has sought to transform post-conflict societies according to economic logics that emphasise individualism, enterprise and competition. In the last 25 years, Transitional justice has risen to the forefront of the human rights movement, and is now firmly embedded in the institutions of global neoliberal governance such as the UN, the International Monetary Fund (IMF), and the World Bank. Normatively conceived as an ‘apolitical’ set of technocratic mechanisms, the relationship between transitional justice and processes of ‘neoliberalisation’, which are often a significant part of post-conflict transitions, remains largely undertheorised by scholars and practitioners. Addressing this problem, the thesis follows two interrelated lines of enquiry. First, with reference to the work of Michel Foucault, the thesis conceptualises transitional justice as an apparatus (dispositif) with a set of practices that support the process of neoliberal transition. Secondly, by drawing on René Girard’s theory of sacrifice, the thesis shows that the central mechanisms of the apparatus, that is, trials and truth commissions, are practices of ‘sacrificial violence’ designed to expel the ‘evil’ of the past and lay a foundation for the neoliberal society that comes after. Using the transitions of Rwanda, South Africa, and Sierra Leone as case studies, the thesis demonstrates that these practices of sacrificial violence produce narratives and engender subjectivities that support and prefigure neoliberal transitions designed to reconstitute war-torn states as market societies. [ii] CONTENTS INTRODUCTION |Transitional justice and Critique| ...................................................... 1 SECTION 1 01 |A Theory of Transitional Justice | ...................................................23 02 |Transitional Justice as Apparatus | ................................................63 03 |Transitional Justice as Apparatus II | ............................................103 SECTION 2 (CASE STUDIES) 04 |Rwanda, the ICTR and Retributive Expulsion |.............................143 05 |Neoliberal South Africa and the TRC | .........................................187 06 |Truth AND Justice in Sierra Leone| ..............................................233 CONCLUSION |Another Transitional Justice? | ....................................................288 BIBLIOGRAPHY| ......................................................................................................314 [iii] INTRODUCTION |TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE AND CRITIQUE| Since the mid-Eighties, transitional justice has risen to the forefront of the human rights movement, attending to post-conflict or ‘transitional’ societies through legal and quasi-legal institutions. The term ‘transitional justice’ has come to denote the use of criminal trials and truth commissions, as well as a range of other measures including lustration, and reparations, all designed to assist transitional societies to deal with past human rights abuses and to aid processes of liberal democratisation. Starting life as the work of Non-Governmental Organisations (NGOs) and human rights lawyers, transitional justice is now favoured by an array of international institutions such as the UN, the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and the World Bank. These institutions all advocate – and are involved in – the use of transitional justice practices, as a means of ameliorating the ‘traumatic’ pasts of transitional societies and reconstructing them in the image of a liberal, democratic, rights-respecting nation-state. Transitional justice has thus become increasingly ubiquitous. To date transitional justice has been deployed in numerous contexts including in Latin America (Argentina, Chile, Columbia, and Guatemala, for example), Eastern Europe (notably the former Yugoslavia but also post-Communist countries like Romania, Poland, and others), Africa (South Africa, Rwanda, Sierra Leone, Sudan, Uganda, and so on) and South-East Asia (Cambodia). It is little wonder then, that in reflecting on the current state of [1] transitional justice, Rosemary Nagy (2008, p. 276) was inclined to declare that ‘the question today is not whether something should be done after atrocity but how it should be done.’ With refracted but perhaps inadvertent echoes of the title to Vladimir Lenin’s famous essay ‘What is to be done?’, the phrase captures both the revolutionary march that transitional justice has made on human rights, peacebuilding, and systems of global governance, and the urgent speed at which it has been incorporated into them as a body of theory and practice that is now understood as ‘common sense’. In the wake of this rise, transitional justice is now represented by a burgeoning academic field, which includes its own journal, the International Journal of Transitional Justice, as well as several research centres including the Transitional Justice Institute at Ulster University, the Essex Transitional Justice Network at the University of Essex, and the Oxford Transitional Justice Research network based at the University of Oxford. Academic work has done much to bring together the normative conceptual terrain of transitional justice, and to refine the central tenets of its approach. Ruti Teitel (2000), for example, has sought to theorise how various forms of transitional justice might serve a profound normative role in the transition from conflicts and/or authoritarian rule to liberal democracy. Similarly, an edited volume by Neil Kritz (1995) brought various authors – including leading academics such as José Zalaquett, Jon Elster and Naomi Roht-Arriaza – to outline the theoretical scope of transitional justice. Other authors have considered how certain mechanisms support transitions in different ways. For example, Martha Minow (2000), Teresa Godwin Phelps (2004), and Priscilla Hayner (2010) have sought to outline the philosophical, ethical and practical reasons for using truth commissions to address transitional justice issues over other mechanisms like trials. In a similar vein, Roht-Arriaza and Javier Mariezcurrena (2006) edited a volume, which addressed how various transitional [2] justice mechanisms might coexist and complement each other in practice. The reader will be given a more detailed treatment of this work in chapter 2, and the theoretical support for various approaches will be examined thoroughly in the case studies (chapters 4, 5, and 6). Nevertheless, there are relatively few critiques of transitional justice, which challenge the normative assumptions that constitute it. Lamenting this problem, Catherine Turner (2013, p. 194) argues that ‘while there has been significant critical engagement with the requirements of transition […] this critique has focused on the need to ensure a more broadly defined and nuanced definition of transitional justice.’ Critiques of transitional justice have focused on the theorised needs of transitions without a significant engagement with the theoretical and normative assumptions that constitute those needs. For example, some academic work has addressed the difficulties with ‘top-down’ transitional justice, and advocated a variety of grassroots approaches as a remedy (see: McEvoy and McGregor, 2008). While this work locates a failure to meet transitional justice’s normative criteria, it does not question the assumptions that underpin them. In particular, the assumed relationship between transitional justice and the political (and economic) project of liberalism has often avoided substantive criticism. This could well be attributed to the context of transitional justice’s rise following the end of the Cold War, when a triumphant liberalism sought to universalise itself in a putatively ‘post-ideological’ area conceived as ‘the end of history’ (Fukuyama, 1989). But more than that, with a grounding in human rights law, the broadly legalistic approach1 of transitional justice is often presented as a technocratic exercise deployed to overcome 1 Used hereafter to denote the ‘legal’ nature of transitional justice, rather than referring only to criminal justice. [3] the political context of conflict and mass violence. Indeed, as Turner (2013, p. 201) argues, ‘the application of legal form is seen as a means of transcending existing political conflict and allowing a society to move towards a new form of governance, shielded by the formality of law and legal procedure.’ The result is that the assumed ‘goods’ of transitional justice - that is, dealing with the legacy of human rights abuse and supporting a nascent liberal democracy – are not subjected to much interrogation. Indeed, following the assimilation of transitional justice by international financial institutions, there has been no penetrating critical analysis of the relationship between transitional justice, human rights and the globalisation of neoliberalism, which these institutions are implicated in. Moreover, there is very little questioning of the practices used to deliver transitional justice, particularly its central mechanisms: criminal trials and truth commissions. While their effectiveness as legal and quasi-legal institutions is often critiqued (Gibson, 2002; Hamber & Wilson, 2002; Olsen, Payne, & Reiter, 2010), the idea that their legalism might obfuscate their political purposes and effects is rarely brought into question. Little time is given to the notion that the purpose of these mechanisms might be conceptualised very differently from (and very critically of) the normative function that they are given by academics and practitioners. There have been some exceptions to this lack of critique. In her aforementioned article, Turner (2013) responds to the problem by forwarding a Derridean deconstruction of the binaries of war/peace and law/politics that seem to lie at the heart of transitional justice. Nagy (2008), on the other hand, has taken issue with the field on a number of fronts by exploring transitional justice as a global project. Noting the privileging of legal responses to conflict and violence, Nagy argues that transitional justice often favours an approach that imagines the future singularly in the image of a [4] liberal democracy. Its liberal legalism, she shows, means that it is often ‘blind to gender and social injustice,’ (ibid., p. 276). Finally, Zinaida Miller (2008, p. 268) has noted the potential problems caused by transitional justice mechanisms which serve to ‘define key issues related to the past which must be resolved.’ By ignoring questions of structural violence and inequality, Miller argues, transitional justice renders them ‘invisible’ and fails to grapple with a number of questions pertaining directly to the conflict. Most recently, critical research has featured in a special issue of the International Journal of Transitional Justice edited by Makua Mutua. The special issue offers a platform for some of the latest normative critiques, from the negative effects of the monolithic use of the International Criminal Court (ICC) in Africa (Okafor & Ngwaba, 2015) to the need to incorporate issues around corruption into the practice of truth commissions (Robinson, 2015). Such contributions might be accused of falling into Turner’s trap of further elaborating a definition of transitional justice, rather than questioning the assumptions upon which any definition might be built. Nevertheless, others articles have pressed to alter the normative framework of transitional justice by encouraging the inclusion of socio-economic rights in its processes, as well as proposing to rethink its relationship with liberal peacebuilding (Fourlas, 2015; Bundschuh, 2015). This nascent body of work is a promising starting point, and suggests that there is an appetite to address transitional justice more critically. That being said, this thesis proposes that more can be gained by subjecting transitional justice to a sustained engagement with critical theory. Critical theory has been influential in academic approaches to law and legal studies. It has become a mainstay in the field of critical legal studies where poststructuralist thought and continental [5] philosophy have often provided a framework for theoretical approaches to law.2 Crucial insights have also been gained from critical theory’s interaction with human rights (see: Agamben, 2008 [1993]; Badiou, 2001; Brown, 2004; Rancière, 2004; Spivak, 2005; Odysseos 2010). It is odd then, that critical theory has thus far failed to find a foothold in transitional justice research, with theoretical works like Turner’s occupying a relatively marginal position within the field. As such, transitional justice could benefit from a set of new and productive engagements with critical theory. Doing so may provide a critical reconceptualisation of transitional justice that enables academics and practitioners to further reimagine the field beyond the normative liberal concepts by which it is defined. Building on some of the insights brought by Nagy, Miller and others, this thesis offers such engagement. It aims to provide a critical theory of transitional justice that questions how transitional justice mechanisms operate, bringing its political functions and effects into sharper focus. In particular, I hope to provide a theory of transitional justice that can more critically locate the relationship between transitional justice, questions of socioeconomic violence and inequality, and the systems of global neoliberal governance implied by international institutions like the IMF and the World Bank. In doing so, it is hoped that the thesis will provide a new critical perspective in the study of transitional justice that may be useful for transitional justice researchers and practitioners. Grasping precisely what is to be gained from this critical theory of transitional justice will be better understood by introducing the general trajectory of my approach. 2 For example, the edited volume by Matthew Stone, Illan rua Wall, & Costas Douzinas (2012). [6]
Description: