religions Article Future Perfect: Tolstoy and the Structures of Agrarian-Buddhist Utopianism in Taisho¯ Japan JamesMarkShields ID ComparativeHumanitiesProgram,BucknellUniversity,Lewisburg,PA17837,USA;[email protected] (cid:1)(cid:2)(cid:3)(cid:1)(cid:4)(cid:5)(cid:6)(cid:7)(cid:8)(cid:1) (cid:1)(cid:2)(cid:3)(cid:4)(cid:5)(cid:6)(cid:7) Received:22April2018;Accepted:13May2018;Published:16May2018 Abstract:ThisstudyfocusesontheroleplayedbytheworkofLeoTolstoy(1828–1910)inshaping socialismandagrarian-BuddhistutopianisminJapan.AsJapanesetranslationsofTolstoy’sfictionand philosophy,andaccountsofhislifebecamemoreavailableattheendofthe19thcentury,hisideason theindividual,religion,society,andpoliticshadatremendousimpactonthegenerationcomingof ageinthe1900sandhispopularitygrewamongyoungintellectuals. OneimportantlegacyofTolstoy inJapanishisparticularconcernwiththepeasantryandagriculturalreform. Amongthoseinspired byTolstoyandthenarodnikilifestyle,threeindividuals,TokutomiRoka,EtoTekirei,andMushako¯ji Saneatsuillustratehowprominentwritersandthinkersadoptedthemaster’slifestyleandattempted to put his ideas into practice. In the spirit of the New Buddhists of late Meiji, they envisioned a comprehensivelifestylestructure.AsEtoTekireimovedtothevillageofTakaidowiththeassistanceof TokutomiRoka,hecalledhisnewhomeHyakusho¯ Aido¯jo¯ (literally,FarmersLoveTrainingGround). HeandhisfamilyendeavoredtofollowaTolstoyanlife,whichincludedlabor,philosophy,art,religion, society,andpolitics,agrandprojectthathesawasa“non-religiousreligion.”Assuch,Tekirei’sutopian visionmightbeconceivedasanexperimentin“alter-modernity.” Keywords: violence; nonviolence; Leo Tolstoy (1828–1910); utopianism; Japanese Buddhism; TokutomiRoka(1868–1927);EtoTekirei(1880–1944);Mushako¯jiSaneatsu(1885–1976);nonresistance; agrarianwayoflife 1. Introduction TheprimaryforeigninfluenceonearlyJapanesesocialism—includingthetwomainformsof religioussocialism,ChristianandBuddhist—wastheworkofLeoTolstoy(1828–1910),Russianessayist, pacifist,Christiansocialistand,ofcourse,authorofsomeofthemostsignificantworksof19thcentury worldliterature.1 AlthoughportionsofWarandPeacehadbeenpublishedinJapanasearlyas1886, itwasin1889and1890—coincidingwiththeproclamationofboththeImperialConstitutionandthe RescriptonEducation—thatJapanesetranslationsofTolstoy’sfictionandphilosophy,andaccountsof hislife,begantoappearinjournalssuchasKokuminnotomo,Shinri,Tetsugakuzasshi,andRikugo¯zasshi. Theyear1890alsosawthepublicationinNihonhyo¯ronofareportonTolstoyanhumanismbythe ChristiantheologianandcriticUemuraMasahisa(1857–1925). Overthenextdecade,manyofTolstoy’s shorter works became available in Japan, including The Cossacks (1893) and Kreutzer Sonata (1894), bothofwhichhadasignificantinfluence. (SeeNobori1981,pp. 34–37;Shifman1966,pp. 59–64). NodoubtpartoftheattractionofTolstoyasawriteroffictionwashisblendofnaturalismand humanism,twosignificantliterarytrendsthatwerejustemerginginlateMeijiandearlyTaisho¯ Japan. 1 Several sections of this article have been adapted, with modifications and elisions, from (Shields 2017); see esp. pp.170–72;183–88. Religions2018,9,161;doi:10.3390/rel9050161 www.mdpi.com/journal/religions Religions2018,9,161 2of12 (SeeSibley1968,p. 162,n.15). Tolstoy’sideasontheindividual,religion,society,andpoliticswere ofimmenseinfluenceonthe“youngmenofMeiji,”thegenerationcomingofageinthelastdecade of the Meiji period.2 As the historian Steven Marks puts it: “His writings encapsulated in highly readableformtheRussianphilosophicalstressontheillusorynatureofWesternprogress,andthe virtuesofeitherbackwardnessordelayingtheonsetofWesternmodernization,ideasthatreverberated throughoutthenon-Westernworld.”(Marks2003,p. 123). Thisresonancewasparticularlystrongin Japan,anationstrugglingwithmanyofthesameissuesregardingmodernization,industrialization, anditsrelationshiptotheWestasTolstoy’sRussia. Tolstoy held a deep respect and appreciation for Asian culture, dabbled in Buddhism, and denounced Western imperialism and colonialism, urging non-Western peoples to resist (nonviolently)becomingslavesorpuppetstotheWestanditsideals.3 Hisoutspokenoppositiontothe Russo-JapaneseWar(1904–1905)wonhimmanyadherentsamongstudents,progressiveintellectuals, andtheJapaneseleft(includingmanyChristiansandBuddhists),whilerenderinghimapernicious influenceintheeyesofthelate-Meijiandearly-Taisho¯ administrations. Prominentleftistssuchas AbeIso’o(1865–1949),Ko¯tokuShu¯sui(1871–1911),KitamuraTokoku(1868–1894),andO¯sugiSakae (1885–1923) acknowledged Tolstoy as an influence and inspiration. As a result, combined with a moregeneralfearofthegrowthofradicalthoughtamongtheyoung, inthedecadebetween1905 and1915Tolstoywasamongthoseauthorswhoseworksweretargetedasbeingdetrimentaltopublic morals. To the chagrin of government officials and associated ideologues, however, the Russian writer’s influence continued to grow throughout the Taisho¯ era, so much so that a new term was coined—Torusutoishugi—todescribethepopularphenomenonofadoptinga“Tolstoyanlifestyle.” One important legacy of Tolstoy in Japan is his particular concern with the peasantry and agriculturalreform. Theso-called“rediscovery”oftheJapanesecountrysideinlateMeijiissometimes attributedtohisinfluence. Manyifnotmostagrarianreformmovementsoftheearlycenturywere directly inspired by Tolstoy’s work, often mixed with the writings of the Russian anarchist Peter Kropotkin (1842–1921). That is not to say that there were no indigenous roots to this turn to the countryside: Zen Buddhism (influenced by the primitivist stream within Chinese Daoism) has long held to the ideal of a simple, rustic existence, while the practices of folk Shinto are rooted invisitstoruralshrines. YetthecontrastonefindsinTolstoy—filteredthroughRousseauandthe Europeanromantics—betweenthe“countryside”asthelocusfortruehumanityandthe“city”as theemblemofstrife, unease, andsuffering, wasnewtoJapan, thoughitgraftedreadilyonto19th centurynativistappealstoagriculturalproductivityandpeasantlifeasasolutiontoJapan’sproblems. (SeeHarootunian1988,pp. 49–50,251;Tamamoi1998;Konishi2013,p. 23). Tolstoy and his followers have frequently been labeled “antimodern,” based on a simplistic conflationofmodernityandurbanculture. Indeed,whileJapaneseleftists(andsomerightists)were attractedtoTolstoy’sagrarianromanticismasaresponsetoWestern(bourgeois,urban)civilization, hisworkcontainselementsthataredistinctly“modern(ist),”includinghisrationalistinterpretationof religionandproto-existentialistfocusontheindividual. Anddespiteofficialdisapproval,bytheearly Taisho¯ therewasafeelingthatJapan’sadoptionofTolstoy(alongwiththemoreobviouslymodernist HenrikIbsen)wasasuresignthatthecountryhademergedintothe“modernworld”andtheearly Meijiimpulsehadpaidoff(Marks2003,p. 125). 2. TheNarodniki: Farmer’sInstitutesandNewVillages Inshort,theimpactofTolstoyamongyoungintellectualsinlateMeijiandTaisho¯ Japancanhardly beoverstated. YetTolstoywasnotsimplyareligiousreformerorsocialcritic;hewasalsorecognized 2 ForacomprehensivestudyofTolstoy’simpactinbothJapanandChina,see(Shifman1966). 3 Indeed,asMarksnotes,JapanesereadersofTolstoytendedtoseehimasfamiliarratherthanexoticormystical—thewayhe wasusuallyseenintheWest—andforvariousreasonstreatedhimas“oneoftheirown”(ibid.,p.124). Religions2018,9,161 3of12 asonethegreatwritersofthelate19thcentury—andassuch,hisinfluenceextendedtotheworldof letters. AmongtheearliestJapanesewritersinfluencedbyTolstoy,severalofthemostprominentwere TokutomiRoka(1868–1927),EtoTekirei(1880–1944),andMushako¯jiSaneatsu(1885–1976). Allthree menidentifiedstronglywithTolstoy,notonlyaswritersandthinkersbutalsointermsofadopting themaster’slifestyleandattemptingtoputhisideasintopractice. Inparticular,theywereattracted towhatAkamatsuKatsumaro(1894–1955)called“thepracticaleffectivenessofTolstoy’sdoctrinesof love,labor,nonresistance,andreverencefortheagrarianwayoflife.”(Akamatsu1981,p. 98). On the way back from a pilgrimage to Jerusalem, Roka—younger brother of the well-known historianandcriticTokutomiSoho¯ (1863–1957)—visitedTolstoy’svillainYasnayaPolyanain1906, andsoonbegantoinjecthisliteraryworkswithTolstoyanqualitiesofintrospectionandaresistanceto authoritarianism.4 In1908,asleftistactivismgrewinthewakeoftheRusso-JapaneseWar,hegave a controversial address to the Debating Society of the First Higher School of Tokyo entitled “The SadnessofVictory,”inwhichheevokedtheemptinessfeltbyeventhegreatestgeneralsupontheir so-calledvictoriesinbattle,concluding,inwordsthatevoketheBuddhistconversionofthelegendary KingAshoka(304–232BCE)afterthebattleofKalinga: “Ofwhatvalueisman’svictory? Thepeople searchafter‘success’or‘distinction,’offeringtheirverylivesinpayment. Butwhatissuccess,whatis distinction? Thesearenothingmorethanprettyreflectionsshiningforthfromthedreamofman’s aspirations” (cited in Akamatsu 1981, p. 99). Apparently, this speech hit a chord with a number of students in the audience, some of who promptly quit school to return to their native village as narodniki.5 RokahimselfwouldspendhisfinaltwodecadesensconcedwithhiswifeinaMusashino forestretreatcalledKo¯shun-en,livingthelifeofa“naturalman”(shizenjin). Eto Tekirei was another budding intellectual and writer who got caught up in the Tolstoyan currents of the early 20th century. Around 1906, inspired by Tolstoy and the narodniki lifestyle, heabandonedhisstudiesatTokyoImperialUniversityandtookupthelifeofafarmer. Yeteventhis wasnotenough,soin1910,withtheassistanceofTokutomiRoka,Tekireitookupresidenceinthe villageofTakaidointheMusashinoareajustoutsideofTokyo.6 Givinghisnewhomethegrandiose titleHyakusho¯ Aido¯jo¯ (literally,FarmersLoveTrainingGround),heandhisfamilyattemptedtofollow aTolstoyanlifetothefullest,whileincorporating—likesomanyotherJapanesenarodniki—Buddhist andChristianelementsintohisthought,includingtheworkofChristiansocialistUchimuraKanzo¯ (1861–1930). Aneclecticthinker,TekireialsoborrowedheavilyfromtheworkofRussiananarchist Kropotkin, whose Fields, Factories, and Workshops “really taught [him] how to live a life of labor,” (Akamatsu 1981, p. 100; see also Eto 1925; Nishimura 1992, p. 170; Nakao 1996, p. 174). He was amongthefirstJapanesescholarsto“rediscover”theworkofAndo¯ Sho¯eki(1703–1762),theEdo-period agrarianthinkerandproto-communistvisionary.7 In1922,TekireipublishedhisAruhyakusho¯ noie (Thehouseholdofacertainfarmer),which,togetherwithTsuchitokokorootagayashitsutsu(Tillingthe soilandtheheart,1924),servesasbothmemoirandjustificationforhisagrariansocio-religiousvision. Eto’sagrarian-Buddhistvisionisencapsulatedinhis“wheelofhouseholdgrainfarming”(Figure1). 4 SeeShizentojinsei(Natureandhumanlife,1900)forRoka’sreflectionsonnature,andMimizunotawagoto(Gibberishofan earthworm,1913)forhisadoptionoftheTolstoyanpeasantlifestyle.See(Shifman1966,pp.68–76),forthecorrespondence betweenRokaandTolstoy. 5 Ibid.;seealsoMoiwa1981.TheRussianwordnarodnikireferstoapersonassociatedwithalooselydefinedprogressive socialmovementthatfirstaroseinRussiainthe1860sand1870s,inresponsetothepovertyandsocialproblemsunleashed byofTsarAlexanderII’s“emancipation”oftheserfs. Theideologydevelopedandpromotedbythenarodnikiwasa formofpopulism,focusedespeciallyonaddressingthegrievancesofruralpeasants—stillthevastmajorityofordinary Russians—ratherthanurbanworkers.FormoreontheRussiannarodniki,see(Kołakowski2008,pp.609–12). 6 MusashinowouldbecomethecenteroftheJapanesenarodnikimovement,withTokutomiRoka,IkedaTaneo(1897–1974), andO¯nishiGoichi(1898–1992)allspendingsometimeintheKamitakaidoareaduringtheTaisho¯period.See(Nishimura 1992,p.151). 7 See(Nishimura1992,pp.173–74).TekireireferredtohisutopianexperimentasTenshinkei,whichisborrowedfromSho¯eki’s tropeofthenaturalorderas“movement,”“truthfulness,”and“reverence”;see(Tetsuo2002,“Ando¯Sho¯eki,”pp.75–76). Religions2018,9,161 4of12 Figure1.EtoTekirei’s“Wheelofhouseholdgrainfarming”(Wada2012,p.78). CitingMaruyamaMasao’sremarksonthetendencytowardsideologicalpolarizationduringthis period,NishimuraShun’ichiarguesthatthistendencyextendedtolateMeijiandTaisho¯ denenshugi (agrarianism)aswell,suchthatthereemergeda“rightwing”factionofthinkersdedicatedtono¯honshugi (literally,agriculture-essence-ism)anda“leftwing”orprogressivefactionespousingno¯minjichishugi (farmer-autonomy-ism)(Nishimura1992,p. 88;alsoseeNakao1996). NishimuraplacesTekireiinthe lattergroup,alongwithIshikawaSanshiro¯ (1876–1956),ShimonakaYasaburo¯ (1878–1961),andO¯nishi Goichi(1898–1992),asopposedto“rightists”suchasGondo¯ Seikyo¯ (1868–1937),TachibanaKo¯zaburo¯ (1893–1974),YamazakiNobuyoshi(1873–1954),andKato¯ Kanji(1884–1967).8 GivenTekirei’sprimary inspirations—Tolstoy, Kropotkin, and Sho¯eki—his radically “horizontal” focus and concomitant rejectionofhierarchy,thisisnotadifficultcasetomake. Andyetitisworthasking: justhowreliant wasTekireionBuddhistideasandprinciplesforhisprogressive,naturalistvision? Afterafewyearsoflifeasafarmer,TekireibegantohaveseriousdoubtsaboutTolstoy’sidealized viewsofpeasantlife,andresolvedtoestablishanewsystemforlivingwithnature,whichhecalled kashokuno¯jo¯(Wheelofhouseholdgrainfarming). Infact,thefirsthalfofthisfour-characterset,kashoku, is borrowed directly—and effectively set in ironic contrast to—the traditional term shashoku, used torefertothestateasatutelarydeityofgrain. Here,inTekirei’sreformulation,itisthehousehold (ie)that becomesthelocusof livelihood, rather thanthestate. In addition, thefinalcharacter jo¯ is clearlyborrowedfromBuddhisttradition,whereitreferstoaparticular“vehicle”orbranchofthe Dharma, one that leads effectively to nirvana—as in the Great Vehicle (Mahayana; Daijo¯). Tekirei goesontodividethisgeneralconceptintoeightcategories: (1)agrarianmethods(no¯ho¯);(2)agrarian organization(no¯sei),(3)agrarianassociation(no¯so),(4)agrarian“path,”includingsocialandeconomic standpoints(no¯do¯),(5)agrarianthought,includingphilosophyandart(no¯so¯),(6)agrariandoctrine, 8 (Nishimura1992,pp.88–89);forananalysisofthelifeandworkofKato¯Kanjivis-à-vistheemergenceofno¯honshugi,see (Havens1970). Religions2018,9,161 5of12 includingculture(no¯kyo¯),(7)agrarianspirit,includingspiritualityandreligion(no¯kon),(8)agrarian practice(no¯gyo¯)(Nishimura1992,p. 171). Clearly,inthespiritoftheNewBuddhistsoflateMeiji,Tekireiisaimingforacomprehensive lifestylestructure—onethatstretches(orbetter,softens)theboundariesbetweenlabor,philosophy,art, religion,society,andpolitics. Indeed,duetoitsapplicationtoallfacetsofordinarylife,hewouldgo ontocallhisvisiona“non-religiousreligion”(mushu¯kyo¯noshu¯kyo¯).9 Moreover,Tekireiseemstohave followedSho¯eki’sunderstandingoftheintrinsicrelationofnature,labor,andknowledge.Whilenature cannotbeknowninitsentirety,itcan(andshould)be“practiced”throughagriculturallabor. Labor alsobringsknowledge—includingknowledgeofthelimitsofpracticeitself,andoutofthisemerges“a naturalcommunity[resting]... onoverflowingsurplusenergiesandinteractivenaturalpractices.”10 We find a remarkably similar vision in the following declaration of principles in the journal Aozora(Bluesky),foundedin1925byO¯nishiGoichiandIkedaTaneo(1897–1974): 1 Aschildrenbornwiththegreatearthasourmotherandthevastskyasourfather,webelievethat wemustfindthefoundationforourdailylivesinthespiritofthepurefarmer,andthatmoreover thisistheveryrootofhumanexistence. 2 Werepudiatetheurban-basedcivilization,whichcontinuestooppressandtrampledownthe peoplebothspirituallyandeconomically,andpledgeinsteadtoestablishanagriculturallybased civilizationthatconformstotheland. 3 This creed is not meant to give birth to yet another fixed doctrine; rather, we simply look to reconnectwithourinnatedispositiontotillthegreatearthandleadthenaturallifeofthefarmer.11 Whilethesoil-peasantfixationisstrongerherethanwiththemainlyurbanNewBuddhistsoflate Meiji,therearepalpableaffinitiestosomeearlierBuddhistprogressiveswithregardtotheemphasison reachingbeyond“civilization”towardsomedeeperfoundationforhumanexistenceandthedesireto be“nonpartisan”and“post-ideological”—withouttherebylosingthecapacitytoengageinforthright criticism.Andwhilewemightfindparallelswithright-leaningevocationsofa“returntothesoil”inthe workofKato¯Kanjiandotheradvocatesofno¯honshugi,here—aswiththeNewBuddhistFellowship(Shin Bukkyo¯ Do¯shikai)—thereisanoticeablelackofmentionofthestateorkokutai(nationalpolity). Inshort, atissueistheindividual’srelationswith(a)nature,(b)themselves,and(c)theirsocietyorcommunity. Insimilarfashion,EtoTekireiwasfiercelyresistanttothenotion—promotedby,forinstance,no¯honshugi activistYamazakiNobuyoshi(1873–1954),that“goingbacktotheland”mustbecomecodifiedasa matterof“nationalpolicy”(seeNishimura1992,p. 171). TekireialsoborrowedheavilyfromtheworkofDo¯gen(1200–1253),takingparticularnoteofthe SotoZenmaster’semphasisonthebodilybasisofawakening. AsWadaKo¯sakuexplains,thisbecame thebasisofTekirei’sideaof“practice”(gyo¯)(Wada2012,pp. 12–14). Elsewherehewritesthatwhilehe neverpracticedshikantazainameditationhall,hedidsointhe“heavenandearthmeditationhall” (tenchizendo¯)—whileengagedinthe“practice”offarming(seeSaito¯ etal.2001,p. 232). Andwith regardtothematterofworkandnature,herelieduponthefollowingpassagefromtheDevadatta chapteroftheLotusSutra,describingtheBuddha’sreminiscencesofhispastlifeasakingwhohas renounced his throne to follow a teacher of the “wonderful law”: “Picking fruit, drawing water, gatheringfirewood,andpreparingfood,evenofferingmyownbodyasacouchforhim,feelingno wearinessinbodyormind. Iservedhimforathousandyears,forthesakeoftheDharma,diligently waitinguponhimsohelackednothing.”12 9 TekireiwritesaboutthisinhiscorrespondencewithAkegarasuHayaintheBuddhistjournalChugaiNippo¯(March–April 1916);see(Wada2012,pp.293–94). 10 (Tetsuo2002,p.70).FormoreonTekirei’suseofShoeki,see(Kinji1974). 11 Citedin(Nishimura1992,p.150);mytranslation. 12 Citedin(Wada2012,p.20);LotusSutra,chap.12“Devadatta.” Religions2018,9,161 6of12 Whilethetropeofthe“suffering”or“self-sacrificial”servantwasalsoputtogoodusebykokutai ideologues,Tekireiresistedtheself-denyingemphasisofno¯honshugiinfavorofwhatcanonlybecalled an “individualist” quest for existential truth. In this respect, his critique of Marx is worth noting, in that—again like his New Buddhist predecessors—he accepts the basic premises of the Marxist (aswellastheDarwinian)critiqueoftraditional“idealist”philosophiesandreligionswhileresisting theharder-edgedimplicationsofakindofmaterialism(anddeterminism)thattreatshumanbeings simplyas“matter”oras“animals”(seeWada2012,pp. 59–64). Inmanyrespects,Tekirei’seclectic philosophyisrootedinprinciplessimilartotheseishinshugiofKiyozawaManshi(1863–1903),soit comesasnosurprisetolearnthatinearly1902theyoungTekireivisitedtheKo¯ko¯do¯ tohearKiyozawa lectureonShinran(1173–1263)andwasfavorablyimpressedbytheolderman. Twodecadeslater hewouldwritethatitwasduetoKiyozawa(inparticularhisreadingofShinran),thatTekireifirst trulydiscoveredthe“self”(shi).13 HewouldlaterhavecontactwithtwoofKiyozawa’schiefstudents: AkegarasuHaya(1877–1954)andChikazumiJo¯kan(1870–1941). Finally,weturntothethirdandmostinfluentialofourTolstoyannarodniki: Mushako¯jiSaneatsu. As the son of a viscount descended from the highest ranks of nobility (kuge), Mushako¯ji received an elite—and cosmopolitan—education at Gakushu¯in (Peers’ School) in Tokyo, coming into early contactwiththeworkofTolstoyaswellastheBible.14 Fromhisschoolyears,hewouldlaterrecount, his“utmostdesirewastobecomeachampionofhumanitarianism,agreatmanoflettersandagreat thinker... ajustman,andtoleadalifesoholythathemightpassforaparagonofvirtueintheeyes ofGod... ”15ThoughinitiallyenrolledintheDepartmentofPhilosophyatTokyoImperialUniversity, hisinterestssoonturnedtowardliterature,and,likeEtoTekirei,hedroppedoutpriortograduation. Bythistime, Mushako¯jihadcomeintocontactwithanumberoftalentedandlike-mindedyoung writers,withwhomhewouldfoundtheShirakaba-ha(WhiteBirchSchool)in1910(seeMortimer2000, pp. ix–x). AlongwiththeothermembersoftheWhiteBirchSchool,throughthepagesoftheirpublication Shirakaba,Mushako¯jipromotedaformofidealisthumanismthatwentagainstthepopularliterarytrend ofnaturalism,whichtendedtowardafatalisticandpessimisticviewofhumanlifecaughtupinforces beyonditscontrol. Incontrast,Mushako¯jiandtheotherwritersoftheWhiteBirchSchoolembracedan optimisticviewofhumanpotential,inwhichtheindividualwaslargelyincontrolofhisowndestiny viathepowerofthewill.16 YetMushako¯ji—likeTolstoyandthenarodnikidiscussedabove—wasnot contenttobesimplyawriter;helongedtoputhisideasintopractice,anopportunitythatpresented itselfin1918,withthefoundingoftheutopiancommunityAtarashikimura(NewVillage)atKijo¯mura, anisolatedspotinthemountainsofMiyazakiprefecture,Kyushu. Despitetheinevitabletroubles (bothfinancialandpersonal),Atarashikimuraseemstohaveflourishedforitsfirstdecade—reachinga peakaround1929. Thesitewascondemnedin1938toallowfortheconstructionofanelectricalpower plant. AsecondNewVillagewasthenestablishedinSaitamaprefecture,andseveralbranchesarose elsewhere,afewofwhichcontinuetothisday. To some extent, Musahako¯ji struggled with the same problem as the New Buddhists and the othernarodniki: howtoreconcileself-discoveryandindividualfreedomwithsocialresponsibilitiesand politicalobligations(see,e.g.,Epp1996,p.17).IntheimmediateaftermathoftheHighTreasonIncident (Taigyakujiken)of1910–11,andwithmorefocusonthe“self”inTaisho¯ intellectualandliterarycircles, theproblemhadbecomeevenmoreacute—andsignificantlymorepoliticallysensitive. Giventhis 13 Ibid.,pp.285–86. 14 AttendingGakushu¯inthroughvirtuallytheentirefourthdecadeofMeiji(1898–1906),Mushako¯jiandhisShirakabapeers wereexposedtoanimpressivearrayoflecturers,includingNatsumeSo¯seki(1867–1916),UchimuraKanzo¯,MiyakeSetsurei (1860–1945),ShimazakiTo¯son(1872–1943),andTokutomiRoka. 15 FromMushako¯ji’sautobiographicalnovelAruotoko(1921–1923);translatedin(Mortimer2000,p.19). 16 ThisrelentlessoptimismcanbeseeninthetitlesofanumberofMushako¯ji’sworksfromthisperiod:thenovelsKo¯fukumono (Ahappyman,1919)andYu¯jo¯(Friendship,1920),andtheplayNingenbanzai(Threecheersformankind,1922);alsoseehis autobiographicalnovelAruotoko(Acertainman,1923). Religions2018,9,161 7of12 context,itishardlysurprisingthat,takenasawhole,whatwemightcallTaisho¯ “humanism”—whether fortuitouslyorasaformofself-censorshipinthewakeoftheHighTreasonIncident—wasnotoverly concernedwithsocialproblems. Indeed,ithasbecomesomethingofascholarlyconsensusthatTaisho¯ literature,inparticular,representsan“inwardturning”awayfromthesocialconsciousnessexpressed intheworksoflateMeiji“naturalism(see,e.g.,Kohl1990,p. 9). “[I]fonecharacteristicofthisearly phaseoftheTaisho¯ discoveryoftheselfliesinconfession,anotherseemstobeablockingoutofsocial concern,atleastinananalyticsense”(Rimer1990,p. 35;Mortimer2000,p. 146). In this regard, the Shirakaba writers—and Mushako¯ji in particular—appear to have a mixed record. MayaMortimerarguesthat,despitetheir“reverenceforTolstoy”—whichwouldseemtogain themacertainprogressivecredibility—the“Shirakabaconcernforthevisualarts... andtheemphasis, throughMushanoko¯ji,onself-fulfillment,seemeddesignedtoreassuretheauthoritiesthatthegroup hadeffectivelywithdrawnfromthepoliticalarena,”andthateventhefoundingofAtarashikimurain 1918wasnota“returntopolitics”butratheraformofescapism: “basedonpastoralnostalgiaand exploitingtheethicalandquietistaspectsofTolstoyanismasadefenseagainstthosewhoreproached thegroup’slackofpoliticalinvolvement.”17Ontheotherhand,StephenKohlcontraststheworkof Mushako¯jiandfellowShirakabamemberArishimaTakeo(1878–1923)withthatofAbeJiro¯ (1883–1959), authorofthehugelypopularSantaro¯ nonikki(DiaryofSantaro¯,1914): “WhenMushanoko¯jispokeof theself,hewascallingfortheimprovementofboththeselfandsocietyatlarge. Abe’sconcernfor theselfissoinward-lookingthathisvisionrarelygoesbeyondtheidentificationandedificationof theindividualself”(Kohl1990,p. 9). IfweassumethatKohliscorrecttoemphasizea“social”aspect toMushako¯ji’sfocusontheself—distinctfrommanyTaisho¯ “humanists”—thenwhat,ifanything, precludesthisfrombeing“political”? The founding of Atarashikimura in the summer and fall of 1918 was the culmination of Mushako¯ji’slong-standingutopiandream—andrepresentstheconcreteembodimentofhisdeepest personalvaluesandideals. Thecommunewasborninthemidstoftwoeventsofbothglobaland localresonance: theRussianRevolutionofOctober1917andtheendoftheGreatWarthefollowing autumn. Asurgeinsocialunrestwithinthecountry—exemplifiedbytheRiceRiotsinTokyo,Osaka, andKobe—compoundedthefearsoftheTaisho¯ administration,showingthattheMeijiexperiments with nation building and the attempt to create a harmonious social order had not yet achieved resolution (see Smith 1970, p. 91; Ohnuki-Tierney 1994, pp. 38–39). Very much in the Tolstoyan anti-authoritarianspirit,Mushako¯ji’sintentionalcommunitypledgeditselftoanidealof“harmony withouthierarchy.”18 Yearsearlier,Mushako¯jihadwrittenofanidealfuturesociety,inwhich: “no temptationwhatsoeverwilldisturbthepeace,andpeoplewillloveoneanotheruntroubledbyanger, deceit,rivalry,coercion,moralobligations,orcensorship. Sincerity,joy,andsolidaritywillsufficeto dispelallanxietyaboutclothing,food,andshelter.”19 Inwhatsoundsironicbutisinfactaserious attempttobringaboutsuchanidealcommunity,thefirstandonly“commandment”inAtarashikimura isaprohibitionagainstmakingorfollowing“commandments”: Hitonimeireisurunakare;matahito nimeireisarerunakare(citedinMortimer2000, p. 29). Indeed, thestatutesofthecommunitywere remarkably“liberal”inemphasis:individuallibertyoverauthority,personalinitiativeovercompulsion, and“work”asanatural,pleasurableactivityratherthananobligation(thesefeaturesalsoalignwith some anarchist and syndicalist visions of the ideal society). In short, the village was more of a “co-operative”thana“commune.” 17 (Mortimer2000,pp.x–xi).Admittedly,itisunclearwhetherthesepointsrepresentMortimer’sownscholarlyopinionorare meanttoreflectthe“standardreading”oftheShirakabawritersbypostwar(Marxist-inclined)criticssuchasHondaShu¯go. WhileatGakushu¯in,Mushako¯jinotesthatheandhispeerswereexposedtotheearlywritingsofKotokuShu¯suiandSakai Toshihiko(1871–1933),andthathehimselffeltaparticularaffinitytoShu¯sui’sideas,“nevermiss[ing]asingleissueofthe HeiminShimbun”(MSZ). 18 InAruotoko,Mushako¯jinoteshisdistrustofcharismaticrevolutionaryleaderssuchasLeninandTrotsky,whohadbecome “cult-figures”and“idols”(MSZ). 19 Mushako¯ji,“Gendainobunmei”;citedandtranslatedin(Mortimer2000,p.29). Religions2018,9,161 8of12 Ofallthenarodnikiandutopiansdiscussedinthischapter,Mushako¯jiappearstobetheoneleast influenced by Buddhist ideas or practices. In this passage of his autobiographical novel Aru otoko (Acertainman,1923)herecountsthedreamsofhisearlyschoolyears: Whynotbecomeabonze?—heevenwentsofartothink;butthen,topicturehimselfbusy at chanting sutras was just too ridiculous. A beggar, then? But he did not believe that a beggar’sjobwouldhelptorevivehisselfhood. Whateverhechosetodo,hewouldnever settleforhalf-waysolutions. Hehadtobecomeafullymatureindependentmanofnothing atall. Butagain,evenifhesucceededinbringingtolifeonesideoftheself,hethoughthe wouldnotbeabletorevivethewhole. (citedinandtranslatedinMortimer2000,p. 20) Thesereminiscencesareinterestinginseveralrespects. First,thoughMushako¯jiisreflectingfromthe ageoffortybackuponaperiodthirtyyearsprevious(aroundthetimeoftheRusso-JapaneseWar), thesedreamsanddoubtswouldstaywithhimthroughouthislife. Second,whileheclearlyrejects thetraditional,stereotypicallifeoftheBuddhist“bonze,”hisaspirationsforan“independent”and comprehensive“revival”oftheselfcoincidesperfectlywithseveralstreamsofBuddhistmodernism emerging in late Meiji, including New Buddhism and, perhaps even more so, the seishinshugi of KiyozawaManshi. Moreover,thereareZeninflectionstoMushako¯ji’sconvictionthat: “Oneendeavors toworknotsimplytogainalivelihood,butasawayofenrichingone’slife”(Shigotonihagemuno wa,seikatsunotamedakedenaku,jibunnojinseiju¯jitsusurukotodesu)(citedinMatsubara1994,p. 58). Indeed,morethanonescholarhasnotedthe“DaoistZen”aspectsofhispoetry.20 Finally,evenwhileMushako¯ji’syouthfulardorforChristianity—stokedbyreadingTolstoyand hearinglecturesbyChristiansocialistsUchimuraKanzo¯ andKinoshitaNaoe(1869–1937)—wouldcool undertheinfluenceofBelgianplaywrightMauriceMaeterlinck(1862–1949),hewouldconfessin1911 thatheretainedsomethinglikea“religiousvocation.”Indeed,thispassagefromhisessay“Jikono tamenogeijutsu”(Artfortheself)bearsquotinginfull,asitpointstoaconceptionofselfandsociety thatwaswidespreadamongTaisho¯ intellectuals,especiallythoseunderTolstoy’sinfluence: IfIhappenedtobecarriedawaybymysocialinstinct,Imightevenbereadytodieformy society. ButifIamnotandampushedbysocietytoexposemyselfagainstmywill,Iwill hatetodosorightaway. BeforeIknowwhetheritisgoodorbadtofollowmysocialinstinct, Imustfirstlistentomyindividual,human,animal,terrestrial,DinganSichandallother instinctswithinme(Ialsoperceiveinmyselfsomethinglikeareligiousvocation;Tolstoy callsit“reason,”butIthinkitcorrespondstosomethingdeeperthanthat).21 Inthisrespect,itisusefultobrieflyexamineMushako¯ji’sLifeofShakyamuniBuddha,a1934publication that,duetopositivecriticalreceptionandbrisksales,helpedhimtorecoverfromtheseriousfinancial straitstowhichhehadfallenbythelate1920s. Inanafterwordinwhichheexplainshisreasonsfor writing this work, Mushakoji notes that, while not intending to bring forth a “new Shakyamuni,” hewantstoemphasizethe“human”Sakyamuni,anidealfigurelaudedforhiscombinationofinsight andcompassion,yetonewhopossessedanaturalinnocence: “theheartofachild”(akagonokokoro). Inshort,likeChrist—also“amanwithapure,pureheart”22—SakyamuniBuddharepresentsone ofthegreatsagesofthepast;thatis,hisstoryisusefulasareferenceforidealhumanbehavior,butbereft ofanytranscendentalormysticalgloss(seeMortimer2000,p. 93,n. 4). Aswithmanyprogressive BuddhistsfromlateMeiji,includingtheNewBuddhistFellowship,Mushako¯jicreatedapantheonof 20 See,e.g.,(Epp1996,pp.18–22).AccordingtoEpp,“TaoistequanimityliesattheheartofMushako¯ji’spoetic”(18). 21 “Jikonotamenogeijutsu,”Shirakaba1911(MSZ);translatedinMortimer2000,91.MortimernotestheKantianandespecially Freudianringofthese“instincts”(honno¯). 22 MSZ.InhisKofukumono(1919),publishedsoonafterthebirthofAtarashikimura,Mushako¯jiwouldemploytheterm magokoro—literally,pure,openmind/heart—torefertothischaracteristicsharedbyalltrue“masters.”Mortimer2000, p.180,184,connectsmagokorotoaconceptof“divinenakedness,”aswellastoan“immanentistandpantheistic”energy thatexistswithinnature. Religions2018,9,161 9of12 “masters,”includingreligiousfigures,philosophers,andwriters(andevenliterarycharacters),who serveasmodelsofhuman“liberation.”23Thus“theBuddha”functionsasarepresentativeofacomplex ofhumanistideals,includingareligiousunderstandingrootedincommonsenseandcompatiblewith modernscience,onethatrejectssocialdiscriminationandinstitutionalhypocrisy,andlookstonature itselfasasourceforliberation.24 InhismuchearlierplayWashimoshiranai(Idon’tknow,either,1910), Mushako¯jipresentsaconversationbetweenGod,Jesus,andSakyamuniinwhichtheyalladmittheir inability to save mankind—indicating, once again, a modernist perspective on spiritual liberation rootedintheindividualaswellasnature,butnot“thegods.”25 3. IdeologyandUtopiaintheTaisho¯ Period In order to theorize further about the various Tolstoyan-Buddhistic utopias described in this chapter,Iturnnowtoabriefdiscussionofthedistinctionbetween“ideology”and“utopia”inthework of20thcenturyGermansocialtheoristKarlMannheim(1893–1947). Inhisclassic1929work,Ideologie undUtopia(Ideologyandutopia),Mannheimfirstdelineatesthe“utopianmentality”asthatwhichis alwaysincongruentwiththeworld—thatis,“orientedtowardobjectswhichdonotexistintheactual situation.”Hethenproceedstodistinguishutopianincongruityfromideologicalincongruity. Whereas thelattermayalso“departfromreality”inthought,itdoesnotgosofarastoeffectchangeonsociety; rather,ideologiesareeventuallyadoptedorassimilatedinsupportofthestatusquo. Thus,“[o]nly thoseorientationstranscendingrealitywillbereferredtobyusasutopianwhich,whentheypass over into conduct, tend to shatter, either partially or wholly, the order of things prevailing at the time”(Mannheim1936,p. 192)Inshort,forMannheim,trueutopiasarealwayscriticalinthemost fundamentalsenseoftheterm. Mannheimgoesontocontrastchiliasticformsofutopia—andtheassociated“mentality”—with liberal-humanitarianones,whicharerootedlessin“ecstatic-orgiasticenergies”thanin“ideas.”Inthe liberalconception,a“formalgoalprojectedintotheinfinitefuture”functionsasa“regulativedevicein mundaneaffairs.”Inotherwords,utopiaisquiteliterallyanidealized“otherrealm”thatinspiresus byworkingonortransformingourmoralconscience. Thisgeneralunderstandingunderliesmuchof whatwenowcall“modernphilosophy,”andassuch,wasdeeplyintertwinedwiththepoliticalideas ofaparticularclass: thebourgeoisie,whoconsciouslyemployeditagainstthe“clerical-theological” view of the world.26 “This outlook, in accordance with the structural relationship of the groups representingit,pursuedadynamicmiddlecoursebetweenthevitality,ecstasy,andvindictivenessof oppressedstrata,andtheimmediateconcretenessofafeudalrulingclasswhoseaspirationswerein completecongruencewiththethenexistingreality.”27 Significantly,however,thisliberal-bourgeoisdrivetowardthe“middleway”ispursuedthrough a privileging of ideas above the vulgar materiality of “existing reality.” As a result, according to Mannheim: “Elevated and detached, and at the same time sublime, it lost all sense for material things, as well as every real relationship with nature.”28 In short, however utopian, a “moderate” path that ultimately privileges ideas over material reality contains a real danger of falling into a formofidealismthatconformsto,ratherthanchallenges,thematerial—andthusideological—status quo. Again,astrongcasecouldbemadethatmodernBuddhism,alongwithmostmajorreligious traditions,hasgenerallytakenthispath,eitherbydesignor,Iwouldsuggest,outofcertainideological 23 FortheShirakabawriters,theseincludedChrist,S´a¯kyamuniBuddha,Confucius,St.Francis,Rousseau,Carlyle,Whitman, andWilliamJames;see(Mortimer2000,p.119). 24 Seeibid.,p. 120. MortimerarguesthatbecausetheShirakaba“master”ultimatelyrejectsall“isms,”themethodofthe masterinvolvesa(Zen?)“wayofunlearning.” 25 HereagainweseeaparallelwithAndo¯ Sho¯eki’sradically“horizontal”perspectiveonliberation;i.e.,onethatrejects “authority”inanyverticalform,relyingratheronthe“movement”oftheindividualwithinnatureandcommunity. 26 Ibid.,p.221. 27 Ibid.,myemphasis. 28 Ibid.,p.222. Religions2018,9,161 10of12 tendenciesinherentininterpretationsofspecificBuddhistteachings. Infact,thisispreciselythecentral argumentoftheCriticalBuddhist(hihanbukkyo¯)movementofthe1990sledbyHakayamaNoriakiand MatsumotoShiro¯,scholarsaffiliatedwithSotoZen,thoughtheCriticalBuddhistsdidnotextendtheir critiquetoapervasive“liberal”mentalityrootedinadiscourseofmodernity.29 As we have seen in the above discussion of various utopian experiments in the late Meiji and Taisho¯ period, despite real differences, they are tied together by an overwhelming focus on self-discoveryorself-awakening—understoodlessinrelationtotheroleoftheindividualinsociety andpoliticsthanwithrespecttoabroaderand“aesthetic”conceptofculture. Thisisnottosaythat all of these figures did not, to some degree, struggle with the “problem” of the self in relation to othersandthelargercommunity—indeed,theattempttocreatesustainableintentionalcommunities implies some degree of social concern. And yet, ultimately, resistance to the dangers of “vulgar materialism”—no doubt enhanced by legitimate fear of reprisal from authorities in the wake of the High Treason Incident—led to the search for, in Mushako¯ji’s phrase, “safe havens” (nigeba) in art, literature, and utopian communities, from the storms of politics and social conflict. Indeed, forMushako¯ji,atleast,theselfbecomesasortofnigeba;asheexplainsin“Jikonotamenogeijitsu” (Artfortheself,1911): Our present generation can no longer be satisfied with what is called “objectivism” in naturalistideology. Wearetooindividualisticforthat... Ihave,therefore,taughtmyself toplaceentiretrustintheSelf. Tome,nothinghasmoreauthoritythantheSelf. Ifathing appearswhitetome,whiteitis.IfonedayIseeitasblack,blackiswhatitwillbe.Ifsomeone triestoconvincemethatwhatIseeaswhiteisblack,Iwilljustthinkthatpersoniswrong. Accordingly,ifthe“self”iswhitetome,nobodywillmakemesayitisblack.30 Granted, Mushako¯ji is here expressing an extreme standpoint, a hyper-subjectivism that has no regard whatsoever for “objective truth”—or even, for that matter, reasoned discussion or debate. Andyet,itspeakstoamoregeneralissueorproblemwithTaisho¯ “progressivism,”andis preciselythereasonthat, afterhisinitialexcitement, progressivewriterandeconomistKawakami Hajime(1879–1946)leftIto¯ Sho¯shin’s(1876–1963)utopianMuga-en(GardenofSelflessness)in1906. AlthoughneitherSho¯shinnorNishidaTenko¯ (1872–1968)wereartistsorliteraryfigures,bothoftheir Tolstoyan-inspiredintentionalcommunities,Muga-enandItto¯en,canbeclassifiedas“liberal-humanist” inMannheim’sschema. Extendingthistocontemporarycriticism,thebulkoftheseTaisho¯ progressive canbejustlyaccusedasrelyingonwhatKaratani(2005)Ko¯jincallsan“aesthetic”perspective,inwhich “actual contradictions” are surmounted and unified “at an imaginary level.” In Karatani’s sense, aestheticsismuchmorethansimplyawayofspeakingaboutartandbeauty;itisamodeofdiscourse that seeks to establish a reformed existence or “sensibility”—an understanding that dates back to RomanticwriterssuchasSchiller,andfindsexpressionwithinGermanIdealismfollowingHegel.31 For Karatani, the attempt by Japanese thinkers and utopians to “overcome modernity” inevitably endedinfailure,sinceitisimpossibletoovercomethelarge-scalesocialcontradictionsandtensionsof modernitybyappealingtoanabstractidealof“culture.”Withthehindsightofhistory,itbecomesless surprisingtonotethatmanyofthese“progressive”experimentswereeasilyco-optedbytheemerging ultra-nationalismoftheSho¯waperiod. The“resistance”thatMannheimseesascrucialtotrueutopian thoughtandpracticethusslidesinto“ideology”—ajustificationandperpetuationofthestatusquo. 29 ForanextendedtreatmentofCriticalBuddhism,see(Shields2011). 30 Shirakaba,July1911(MSZ). 31 ThisisnottosaythatKaratani’sdefinitionisequivalenttothatofSchillerorHegel,butratherthat,liketheirs,itlookstothe originalmeaningoftheGreekrootaisthesis(aisthe¯sis),i.e.,“perception.”See(Calichman2005,p.27).
Description: