ebook img

Time's Arrow in a Quantum Universe I PDF

31 Pages·2017·0.26 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Time's Arrow in a Quantum Universe I

Time’s Arrow in a Quantum Universe I: On the Simplicity and Uniqueness of the Initial Quantum State ddy eming hen E K C * December 4, 2017 Abstract In a quantum universe with a strong arrow of time, we postulate a low- entropyboundarycondition(thePastHypothesis)toaccountforthetemporal asymmetry. Inthispaper,IshowthatthePastHypothesisalsocontainsenough information to significantly simplify the quantum ontology and clearly define auniqueinitialconditioninsuchaworld. First,IintroduceDensityMatrixRealism,thethesisthatthequantumuniverse is described by a fundamental density matrix (a mixed state) that corresponds tosomephysicaldegreesoffreedomintheworld. Thisstandsincontrastwith Wave Function Realism, the thesis that the quantum universe is described by a wavefunction(apurestate)thatrepresentssomethingphysical. ffi Second,IsuggestthatthePastHypothesisissu cienttodetermineaunique and simple density matrix. This is achieved by what I call the Initial Projection Hypothesis: the initial density matrix of the universe is the projection onto the speciallow-dimensionalHilbertspace. Third, because the initial quantum state is unique and simple, we have a strongcasefortheNomologicalThesis: theinitialquantumstateoftheuniverse iscompletelyspecifiedbyalawofnature. Thisnewpackageofideashasseveralinterestingimplications,includingon thedynamicunityoftheuniverseandthe subsystems, thetheoreticalunityof statisticalmechanicsandquantummechanics,andtheallegedconflictbetween Humeansupervenienceandquantumentanglement. Keywords: time’s arrow, Past Hypothesis, Statistical Postulate, reduction, typicality, foundationsofprobability,quantumstatisticalmechanics,wavefunctionrealism,quantum ontology,densitymatrix,WeylCurvatureHypothesis,HumeanSupervenience *DepartmentofPhilosophy,106SomersetStreet,RutgersUniversity,NewBrunswick,NJ08901, USA.Email: [email protected] 1 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 FoundationsofQuantumMechanicsandStatisticalMechanics 4 2.1 QuantumMechanics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4 2.2 StatisticalMechanics. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 2.2.1 ElementsofClassicalStatisticalMechanics . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 2.2.2 ElementsofQuantumStatisticalMechanics . . . . . . . . . . . . 8 2.2.3 CSM,QSM,andMicrostateDispensability . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11 3 DensityMatrixRealism 11 3.1 Example: W-BohmianMechanics. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12 3.2 OtherExamples: EverettianandGRWTheories . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 3.3 SomeIntepretationsofW . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14 4 TheInitialProjectionHypothesis 15 4.1 StandardVersionsofthePastHypothesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 4.2 IntroducingtheInitialProjectionHypothesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 4.3 ConnectionstotheWeylCurvatureHypothesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 5 Unification 19 5.1 DynamicUnityoftheUniverseandtheSubsystems . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 5.2 UnificationofStatisticalMechanicsandQuantumMechanics . . . . . . 21 6 TheNomologicalThesis 22 6.1 TheHumeanConflictwithQuantumEntanglement . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 6.2 ANewVersionofQuantumHumeanism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 6.3 OtherVersionsofQuantumHumeanism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 7 Conclusion 27 1 Introduction In recent debates about the metaphysics of the wave function, it is standard to assume that the universal wave function represents something physical. It may be interpreted as a field on the configuration space, a multi-field on physical space, something like a physical law, or an entity of a completely novel kind. Let us call thisviewWaveFunctionRealism.1 1SeeAlbert(1996),Loewer(1996),WallaceandTimpson(2010),Ney(2012),North(2013),Maudlin (2013),GoldsteinandZanghì(2013),Miller(2014),Esfeld(2014),BhogalandPerry(2015),Esfeldand 2 However, we may reject the assumption that there is a universal wave function that represents something physical. Indeed, it has been rejected by many people, notablybyquantumBayesians,andvariousanti-realistsandinstrumentalists. Asa scientificrealist,Idonotfindtheirargumentsconvincing. Inpreviouspapers,Ihave assumed and defended Wave Function Realism. However, in this paper I want to ff argueforadi erentperspective,forreasonsrelatedtotheoriginoftime-asymmetry inaquantumuniverse. Tobesure,realismabouttheuniversalwavefunctionisquitenaturalgivenstan- dard quantum mechanics and various realist quantum theories such as Bohmian mechanics, GRW spontaneous collapse theories, and Everettian quantum mechan- ics. Inthosetheories,theuniversalwavefunctionisindispensabletothekinematics andthedynamicsofthequantumsystem. However,asIwouldliketoemphasizein thispaper,ourworldisnotjustquantum-mechanical. Wealsoliveinaworldwitha strongarrowoftime(entropygradient). Therearethermodynamicphenomenathat we hope to explain with quantum mechanics and quantum statistical mechanics. A central theme of this paper is to suggest that quantum statistical mechanics is highly relevant for assessing the fundamentality and reality of the universal wave function. Wewilltakeacloselookattheconnectionsbetweenthefoundationsofquantum statistical mechanics and various solutions to the quantum measurement problem. Whenwedo,werealizethatwedonotneedtopostulateauniversalwavefunction. Weonlyneedcertain“coarse-grained”informationaboutthequantummacrostate, which can be represented by either a class of universal wave functions or a density matrix. A natural question is: can we describe the universe with a fundamental densitymatrixinsteadofawavefunction? The first step of of this paper is to argue that we can. I call this view Density MatrixRealism,thethesisthattheuniversalquantumstateisgivenbyafundamental densitymatrixthatrepresentssomethingphysical. DensityMatrixRealismmightbe unfamiliartosomepeople,asweusuallyusemixedstatestorepresentmacrostates underepistemicuncertainties: wedonotknowtheprecisemicrostate. Butitseems to be an implicit attitude among some working physicists and has been previously discussedinfoundationsofquantummechanics. The second step is to point out that Density Matrix Realism allows us to unify quantum ontology with time-asymmetry in a new way. In classical and quantum statisticalmechanics,thermodynamictime-asymmetryarisesfromaspecialbound- aryconditionthatisnowcalledthePastHypothesis.2 Isuggestthattheinformation ffi in the Past Hypothesis is su cient to determine a unique and simple fundamental density matrix. This can be done by postulating what I call the Initial Projection Hypothesis: thequantumstateoftheuniverseatt isgivenbytheuniqueprojection 0 Deckert(2017),Chen(2017a,b,ms). NoticethatthisisnothowAlbert,Loewer,andNeyusetheterm. Forthem,tobeawavefunctionrealististobearealistaboutthewavefunctionandafundamental high-dimensionalspace—the“configurationspace.” Forthepurposeofthispaper,letususeWave Function Realism to designate just the commitment that the wave function represents something physical. 2SeeAlbert(2000). 3 onthespeciallow-dimensionalHilbertspace. The third step is to show that, because of the simplicity and the uniqueness of the initial quantum state (now given by a fundamental density matrix), we have a strong case for the Nomological Thesis: the initial quantum state of the world is exactlyspecifiedbyalawofnature. As we shall see, this package of views has interesting implications for the dy- namicunityoftheuniverseandthesubsystems,reductionofstatisticalmechanical probabilities to quantum mechanics, and Humean supervenience in a quantum world. Here is the roadmap of the paper. First, in §2, I review the foundations of quantum mechanics and quantum statistical mechanics. In §3, I introduce the framework of Density Matrix Realism and illustrate it with a concrete example. In §4,IformulatetheInitialProjectionHypothesisintheframeworkofDensityMatrix Realism. In§5,Idiscusstheirimplicationsfordynamicalandtheoreticalunification. In§6,IsuggestthattheyprovideastrongcasefortheNomologicalThesisandanew solutiontotheconflictbetweenquantumentanglementandHumeansupervenience. 2 Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and Statistical Mechanics Inthissection,wefirstreviewthefoundationsofquantummechanicsandstatistical mechanics. As we shall see in the next section, they suggest an alternative to Wave FunctionRealism. 2.1 Quantum Mechanics Standard quantum mechanics is often presented with a set of axioms and rules about measurement. Firstly, there is a quantum state of the system, represented by a wave function ψ. For a N-particle quantum system in R3, the wave function is a (square-integrable) function from the configuration space R3N to the spin space Ck. Secondly, the wave function evolves in time according to the the Schrödinger equation: ∂ψ ih̵ =Hψ (1) ∂ t Thirdly, the Schrödinger evolution of the wave function is supplemented with col- lapserules. Thewavefunctiontypicallyevolvesintosuperpositionsofmacrostates, suchasthecatbeingaliveandthecatbeingdead. Thiscanberepresentedbywave functions on the configuration space with disjoint macroscopic supports X and Y. During measurements, which are not precisely defined processes in the standard theory, the wave function undergoes collapses. Moreover, the probability that it collapsesintoanyparticularmacrostateX isgivenbytheBornrule: P(X)=∫ ∣ψ(x)∣2dx (2) X 4 As such, quantum mechanics is not a candidate for a fundamental physical theory. It has two dynamical laws: the deterministic Schrödinger equation and the stochastic collapse rule. What are the conditions for applying the former, and what are the conditions for applying the latter? Measurements and observations areextremelyvagueconcepts. Takeaconcreteexperimentalapparatusforexample. When should we treat it as part of the quantum system that evolves linearly and when should we treat it as an “observer,” i.e. something that stands outside the quantum system and collapses the wave function? That is, in short, the quantum measurementproblem.3 Various solutions have been proposed regarding the measurement problem. Bohmianmechanics(BM)solvesitbyaddingparticlestotheontologyandanaddi- tional guidance equation for the particles’ motion. Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber (GRW) theoriespostulateaspontaneouscollapsemechanism. Everettianquantummechan- ics(EQM)simplyremovesthecollapserulesfromstandardquantummechanicsand suggestthattherearemanyemergentworlds,correspondingtoemergentbranches of the wave function, which are all real. My aim here is not to adjudicate among ffi these theories. Su ce it to say that they are all quantum theories that remove the centralityofobservationsandobservers. Tosimplifythediscussions,IwilluseBMasakeyexample.4 InBM,inaddition to the wave function that evolves linearly according to the Schrödinger equation, , ,..., there are particles with precise locations, Q Q Q , which follow the guidance 1 2 N equation: dQ h̵ ψ∗∇ψ i = Im i (3) dt m ψ∗ψ i Moreover, the initial particle distribution is given by the Quantum Equilibrium Hypothesis: ρ (x)=∣ψ(x,t )∣2 (4) t0 0 Bytheequivariancetheorem,ifthisconditionholdsattheinitialtime,thenitholdsat all time. Consequently, BM agrees with standard quantum mechanics with respect to the Born rule predictions (which are all there is to the observable predictions of quantummechanics). ψ In BM, the wave function is central to the quantum system. It not only has its own dynamics described by (1) but also guides particle motion via (3). Its connection to the empirical predictions of quantum mechanics is manifested in (2) and(4). ForauniversewithN elementaryparticles,letuscallthewavefunctionof the universe the universal wave function and denote it as Ψ(q ,q ,...q ). Therefore, 1 2 N Ψ at least prima facie, the universal wave function seems central to the description ofthekinematicsandthedynamicsoftheuniverseasawhole. 3SeeBell(1990),Myrvold(2017)forintroductionstothequantummeasurementproblem. 4SeeDürretal.(1992)forarigorouspresentationofBManditsstatisticalanalysis. 5 2.2 Statistical Mechanics Letusnowconsidermacroscopicsystemssuchasgasinabox. Thiscanbedescribed by a system of N particles, with N > 1020. If the system is governed by classical ffi mechanics,althoughitisdi culttosolvethesystemofequationsexactly,wecanstill useclassicalstatisticalmechanics(CSM)todescribeitsstatisticalbehaviors,suchas approachtothermalequilibriumsuggestedbytheSecondLawofThermodynamics. Similarly, if the system is governed by quantum mechanics, we can use quantum statisticalmechanics(QSM)todescribeitsstatisticalbehaviors. Generallyspeaking, ff there are two di erent views on CSM: the individualistic view and the ensemblist view. We will first illustrate the two views with CSM, which is more familiar and willbehelpfulforunderstandingthetwoviewsinQSM. 2.2.1 ElementsofClassicalStatisticalMechanics Let us review the basic elements of CSM on the individualistic view.5 For con- creteness, let us consider a classical-mechanical system with N particles in a box Λ=[0,L]3 ⊂R3 andaHamiltonianH. 1. Microstate: atanytimet,themicrostateofthesystemisgivenbyapointona 6N-dimensionalphasespace, X =(q ,...,q ;p ,...,p )∈Γ ⊆R6N, (5) 1 N 1 n total Γ where isthetotalphasespaceofthesystem. total 2. Dynamics: the time dependence of X = (q ,...,q ;p ,...,p ;t) is given by the t 1 N 1 n Hamiltonianequationsofmotion: ∂q ∂H ∂p ∂H i = , i =− . (6) ∂ ∂ ∂ ∂ t p t q i i 3. Energyshell: thephysicallyrelevantpartofthetotalphasespaceistheenergy shellΓ⊆Γ definedas: total Γ={X ∈Γ ∶E≤H(x)≤E+δE}. (7) total Γ. Weonlyconsidermicrostatesin 4. Measure: the measure µ is the standard Lebesgue measure of volume ∣⋅∣ on R6N. Γ 5. Macrostate: with a choice of macro-variables, the energy shell can be parti- Γ tionedintomacrostates ν: Γ=⋃Γν. (8) ν 5HereIfollowthediscussioninGoldsteinandTumulka(2011). 6 Γ 6. Uniquecorrespondence: everyphasepointX belongstooneandonlyone ν. Γ 7. Thermalequilibrium: typically,thereisadominantmacrostate thathasthe eq µ mostvolumewithrespectto : µ(Γ ) eq ≈1. (9) µ(Γ) AsystemisinthermalequilibriumifitsphasepointX ∈Γ . eq 8. Boltzmann Entropy: the Boltzmann entropy of a classical-mechanical system inmicrostateX isgivenby: S (X)=k log(µ(Γ(X))), (10) B B where Γ(X) denotes the macrostate containing X. The thermal equilibrium statethushasthemaximumentropy. 9. Low-Entropy Initial Condition: when we consider the universe as a classical- mechanical system, we postulate a special low-entropy boundary condition, whichDavidAlbertcallsthePastHypothesis: X ∈Γ ,µ(Γ )≪µ(Γ )≈µ(Γ), (11) t0 PH PH eq Γ where is the Past Hypothesis macrostate with volume much smaller than PH that of the equilibrium macrostate. Hence, S (X ), the Boltzmann entropy B t0 of the microstate at the boundary, is very small compared to that of thermal equilibrium. 10. AcentraltaskofCSMistoestablishmathematicalresultsthatdemonstrate(or suggest)that forµ−mostmicrostates satisfyingthe PastHypothesis, theywill approachthermalequilibrium(inreasonabletime). AboveistheindividualisticviewofCSMinanutshell. Incontrast,theensemblist ff view di ers in several ways. First, on the ensemblist view, instead of focusing on themicrostateofanindividualsystem,thefocusisontheensembleofsystemsthat have the same statistical state ρ.6 ρ is a distribution on the energy shell, and it also ff evolves according to the Hamiltonian dynamics. The crucial di erence lies in the definition of thermal equilibrium. On the ensemblist view, a system is in thermal equilibriumif: ρ=ρ orρ=ρ , (12) mc can whereρ isthemicrocanonicalensembleandρ isthecanonicalensemble.7 mc can 6Someensemblistswouldfurtherinsistthatitmakesnosensetotalkaboutthethermodynamic stateXofanindividualsystem. 7InsteadofusingtheBoltzmannentropy,someensemblistsusetheGibbsentropy: SG(ρ)=−kB∫ ρlog(ρ)dx. Γ 7 2.2.2 ElementsofQuantumStatisticalMechanics ff The foundations of QSM have important similarities to and di erences with the foundationsofCSM.Forconcreteness,letusconsideraquantum-mechanicalsystem withN fermionsinaboxΛ=[0,L]3 ⊂R3 andaHamiltonianHˆ.8 1. Microstate: atanytimet,themicrostateofthesystemisgivenbyanormalized (andanti-symmetrized)wavefunction: ψ(q ,...,q )∈H =L2(R3N,Ck), ∥ψ∥ =1, (13) 1 N total L2 whereH =L2(R3N,Ck)isthetotalHilbertspaceofthesystem. total 2. Dynamics: the time dependence of ψ(q ,...,q ;t) is given by the Schrödinger 1 N equation: ∂ψ ih̵ =Hψ. (14) ∂ t 3. Energy shell: the physically relevant part of the total Hilbert space is the subspace(“theenergyshell”): H ⊆Htotal ,H =span{φα ∶Eα ∈[E,E+δE]}, (15) Thisisthesubspace(ofthetotalHilbertspace)spannedbyenergyeigenstates φα whoseeigenvaluesEα’sbelongtothe[E,E+δE]range. LetD=dimH ,the numberofenergylevelsbetweenEandE+δE. ψ H Weonlyconsiderwavefunctions ’sin . µ 4. Measure: the measure is given by the standard Lebesgue measure on the unitsphereintheenergysubspaceS(H ).9 5. Macrostate: withachoiceofmacro-variables(suitably“rounded”àlaVonNeu- H mann(1955)),theenergyshell canbeorthogonallydecomposedintomacro- spaces: H =⊕νHν , ∑dimHν =D (16) ν H Each νcorrespondsmoreorlesstosmallrangesofvaluesofmacro-variables thatwehavechoseninadvance. 6. Non-unique correspondence: typically, a wave function is in a superposition ofmacrostatesandisnotentirelyinanyoneofthemacrospaces. However,we Since SG(ρt) is stationary under the Hamiltonian dynamics, it is not the right kind of object for understanding the approach to thermal equilibrium in the sense of the Second Law, as we would liketohaveanobjectthatcanchange,and,inparticular,increasewithtime. 8HereIfollowthediscussionsinGoldsteinetal.(2010a)andGoldsteinandTumulka(2011). 9In cases where the Hilbert space is infinite-dimensional, we should use a Gaussian measure, whichisnottranslation-invariant. 8 ψ canmakesenseofsituationswhere is(intheHilbertspacenorm)veryclose H toamacrostate ν: ⟨ψ∣Pν∣ψ⟩≈1, (17) where Pν is the projection operator into Hν. This means that almost all of ∣ψ⟩ H liesin ν. H 7. Thermal equilibrium: typically, there is a dominant macro-space that has eq adimensionthatalmostequaltoD: H dim eq ≈1. (18) H dim ψ ψ Asystemwithwavefunction isinequilibriumifthewavefunction isvery closetoH inthesenseof(17): ⟨ψ∣P ∣ψ⟩≈1. eq eq Simple Example. Consider a gas consisting of n = 1023 atoms in a box Λ ⊆ R3. Thesystemisgovernedbyquantummechanics. Weorthogonallydecompose the Hilbert space H into 51 macro-spaces: H ⊕H ⊕H ⊕...⊕H , where 0 2 4 100 H ν isthesubspacecorrespondingtothemacrostatethatthenumberofatoms in the left half of the box is between (ν − 1)% and (ν + 1)% of n. In this H example, has the overwhelming majority of dimensions and is thus the 50 H equilibriummacro-space. Asystemwhosewavefunctionisverycloseto 50 isinequilibrium. 8. BoltzmannEntropy: theBoltzmannentropyofaquantum-mechanicalsystem ψ ν withwavefunction thatisveryclosetoamacrostate isgivenby: SB(ψ)=kBlog(dimHν), (19) H ψ where ν denotesthesubspacecontainingalmostallof inthesenseof(17). Thethermalequilibriumstatethushasthemaximumentropy: S (eq)=k log(dimH )≈k log(D)=S (mc), (20) B B eq B B where eq denotes the equilibrium macrostate and mc the micro-canonical en- semble. 9. Low-EntropyInitialCondition: whenweconsidertheuniverseasaquantum- mechanical system, we postulate a special low-entropy boundary condition on the universal wave function—the quantum-mechanical version of the Past Hypothesis: Ψ(t )∈H ,dimH ≪dimH ≈dimH (21) 0 PH PH eq H where isthePastHypothesismacro-spacewithdimensionmuchsmaller PH than that of the equilibrium macro-space.10 Hence, the initial state has very lowentropyinthesenseof(19). 10ThePastHypothesismacro-spaceisthusfinite-dimensional. SowecanusetheLebesguemeasure ontheunitsphereasthetypicalitymeasurefor#10. 9 10. AcentraltaskofQSMistoestablishmathematicalresultsthatdemonstrate(or suggest) that for µ−most (maybe even all) wave functions satisfying the Past Hypothesis,theywillapproachthermalequilibrium(inreasonabletime). AboveistheindividualisticviewofQSMinanutshell. Incontrast,theensemblist ff view of QSM di ers in several ways. First, on the ensemblist view, instead of focusingonthewavefunctionofanindividualsystem,thefocusisonanensemble of systems that have the same statistical state Wˆ , a density matrix.11 As a statistical density matrix, Wˆ can be defined from a uniform distribution on the unit sphere in theHilbertspace: Wˆ =∫ µ(dψ)∣ψ⟩⟨ψ∣. (22) S(H) ItevolvesaccordingtothevonNeumannequation: ih̵dWˆ (t) =[Hˆ,Wˆ ]. (23) dt ff The crucial di erence between the individualistic and the ensemblist views of QSMlies,again,inthedefinitionofthermalequilibrium. Ontheensemblistview,a systemisinthermalequilibriumif: W =ρ orW =ρ , (24) mc can ρ ρ where isthemicrocanonicalensembleand isthecanonicalensemble. mc can ψ FortheQSMindividualist,ifthemicrostate ofasystemisclosetosomemacro- H H space ν in the sense of (17), we can say that the macrostate of the system is ν. However, we can also represent the macrostate by a density matrix Wˆν generated fromtheunitsphereinHν withauniformdistributionµ(dψ). Wˆ ν =∫ µ(dψ)∣ψ⟩⟨ψ∣. (25) S(Hν) In(25),thereisaclearsensethatWˆ νisdefinedwithachoiceofmeasureandfromthe H ff wave functions on the unit sphere of the Hilbert space ν. But di erent measures cangiverisetothesamedensitymatrix. Whatisessentialandintrinsictoadensity matrixisitsgeometricalmeaningintheHilbertspace—aprojectionoperator. When Hν is finite-dimensional, we can simply think of Wˆ ν as the normalized identity H operatoron ν anddefineitwithoutusingameasure: Wˆ ν = IνH , (26) dim ν H whereIν istheidentityoperatoron ν. 11SimilarlytothesituationinCSM,someensemblistswouldfurtherinsistthatitmakesnosense totalkaboutthethermodynamicstateofanindividualsystem. 10

Description:
foundations of probability, quantum statistical mechanics, wave function realism, quantum 7 Conclusion. 27. 1 Introduction. In recent debates about the metaphysics of the wave function, it is standard to assume that the universal wave function content, and since then the entropy has increased.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.