ebook img

Thinking Without a Banister: Essays in Understanding, 1953–1975 PDF

511 Pages·2018·3.45 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Thinking Without a Banister: Essays in Understanding, 1953–1975

ALSO BY HANNAH ARENDT Nonfiction Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought Crises of the Republic Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil Essays in Understanding, 1930–1954 The Human Condition The Jew as Pariah: Jewish Identity and Politics in the Modern Age The Jewish Writings Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy The Life of the Mind, Vol. I Thinking, Vol. II Willing Love and Saint Augustine Men in Dark Times On Revolution On Violence The Origins of Totalitarianism The Promise of Politics Rahel Varnhagen: The Life of a Jewish Woman Responsibility and Judgment Correspondence Between Friends: The Correspondence of Hannah Arendt and Mary McCarthy, 1949–1975 Correspondence, 1926–1969 (with Karl Jaspers) Letters,1925–1975 (with Martin Heidegger) Within Four Walls: The Correspondence Between Hannah Arendt and Heinrich Blücher, 1936–1968 Contents Cover Also by Hannah Arendt Title Page Copyright Epigraph Introduction by Jerome Kohn Acknowledgments Publication History Karl Marx and the Tradition of Western Political Thought The Great Tradition Authority in the Twentieth Century Letter to Robert M. Hutchins The Hungarian Revolution and Totalitarian Imperialism Totalitarianism Culture and Politics Challenges to Traditional Ethics: A Response to Michael Polanyi Reflections on the 1960 National Conventions: Kennedy vs. Nixon Action and the “Pursuit of Happiness” Freedom and Politics, a Lecture The Cold War and the West Nation-State and Democracy Kennedy and After Nathalie Sarraute “As If Speaking to a Brick Wall”: A Conversation with Joachim Fest Labor, Work, Action Politics and Crime: An Exchange of Letters Introduction to The Warriors by J. Glenn Gray On the Human Condition The Crisis Character of Modern Society Revolution and Freedom, a Lecture Is America by Nature a Violent Society? The Possessed “The Freedom to Be Free”: The Conditions and Meaning of Revolution Imagination He’s All Dwight Emerson-Thoreau Medal Address The Archimedean Point Heidegger at Eighty For Martin Heidegger War Crimes and the American Conscience Letter to the Editor of The New York Review of Books Values in Contemporary Society Hannah Arendt on Hannah Arendt Remarks Address to the Advisory Council on Philosophy at Princeton University Interview with Roger Errera Public Rights and Private Interests: A Response to Charles Frankel Preliminary Remarks About the Life of the Mind Transition Remembering Wystan H. Auden, Who Died in the Night of the Twenty-eighth of September, 1973 There’s this other thing, which Draenos brought up…“groundless thinking.” I have a metaphor which is not quite that cruel, and which I have never published but kept for myself. I call it thinking without a banister—in German, Denken ohne Geländer. That is, as you go up and down the stairs you can always hold on to the banister so that you don’t fall down, but we have lost this banister. That is the way I tell it to myself. And this is indeed what I try to do. —Hannah Arendt INTRODUCTION Jerome Kohn The Republic of the United States of America has been in a state of decline for more than fifty years, that is, if the decline is dated from the debacle of the invasion of Cuba at the Bay of Pigs in 1961. More than a century before that, John Quincy Adams already despaired of what he called the “noble experiment,” chiefly due to the mordant division of public opinion over the issue of human slavery. Today, the apathy of public opinion is denounced by politicians of all parties and pundits of all political stripes, for the sake of their own power. But for the people, what does an addiction to polls, however cockeyed their results, signify other than an obsession with public opinion? It will come as no surprise to those familiar with Hannah Arendt’s way of thinking that she believed polls, like senseless calls for donations, signify either having lost or been swindled out of one’s own opinion. Speaking with a group of students in Chicago in 1963, Arendt said that every one of us “is forced to make up his mind and then exchange his opinion with others. You may remember,” she said, “the great mistrust the founders had in public opinion, which stands opposed to public spirit. Where public spirit is lacking, public opinion comes in its stead.” To Arendt this is a “perversion,” and a danger to all republics, perhaps especially those that consider themselves democracies. For (now quoting Madison, Federalist, 50) “when men exert their reason cooly and freely on a variety of distinct questions, they inevitably fall into different opinions….When they are governed by a common passion, their opinions, if they are so to be called, will be the same.”*1 Thomas Jefferson was a “party of one,” though not in the sense of The Loners’ Manifesto,*2 which would transmogrify loners, political and otherwise, into a group identity! In a letter to Francis Hopkinson written from Paris in March of 1789, Jefferson wrote: “I am not a federalist, because I never submitted the whole system of my opinions to the creed of any party of men whatever in religion, in philosophy, in politics, or in any thing else where I was capable of thinking for myself. Such an addiction is the last degradation of a free and moral agent. If I could not go to heaven but with a party, I would not go there at all. Therefore I protest to you I am not of the party of federalists. But I am much farther from that of the Antifederalists.” If the American Republic has failed, who bears the responsibility? That question can be construed economically or—in various forms—psychologically, which, to Arendt, would bring forth social rather than political answers. To respond politically would require an observer standing at a distance from the certain but ambiguous sociability of men and women. A political response would be to a somewhat different and more precise question: How have citizens of the United States dissipated the power of their Republic? Her last public address, delivered in the last year of her life, 1975, in celebration of the approaching two hundredth anniversary of the birth of the American Republic, contains indications of what she might say today. There she emphasized “the erosion of power in this country, the nadir of self-confidence when victory over one of the tiniest and most helpless countries could cheer the inhabitants of what only a few decades ago really was the ‘mightiest power on earth’ ”*3 (referring to the United States in the mid-to late 1940s, after the Allied victory in World War II). She next mentions something that, by 1975, seemed to her the “mini-crisis triggered by Joe McCarthy” in the 1950s, which heralded “the destruction of a reliable and devoted civil service…probably the most important achievement of the long Roosevelt administration.” From that point on there had been a “cataclysm of events, tumbling over one another,” and, in words frequently quoted, “cascading like a Niagara Falls of history whose sweeping force leaves everybody, spectators who try to reflect on it and actors who try to slow it down, equally numbed and paralyzed.” Now, more than forty years after Arendt delivered that speech, how often do we still hear this country hailed as the world’s greatest power, or sole superpower, with even less justification than in 1975? Even more confusing, today this swagger is accompanied by the politically empty economic caveat that somehow America must return to her former “wealth” and “greatness.” The ground beneath Arendt’s political thought and speech, the soil that nourished it, was unusually fertile, for better and worse. One matter she almost certainly would be inclined to address today concerns the seemingly relentless political lies at the highest levels of the executive branch—but not only there—of the U.S. government. This lying does not threaten the truth, as the grammatically inept and self-contradictory description of our times as “post-truth” implies, but rather undercuts our ability to believe in the reality of political goings-on as such. If the consequence of the loss of a sense of reality also spells the loss of political power, on the one hand, there is the more crucial matter of how citizens’ exercise of freedom generates power, on the other. This is why the “freedom to be free,” as she states forcefully in this volume, is for Arendt the end or telos of political revolution. Of course, none of this is to deny that self-driven financial imbalances, death-ridden racial inequalities, along with other diverse forms of brutality, bureaucratic corruption, and social injustice, deprive us of freedom in ways that are becoming ever more apparent. These are the signs of an encroaching social totalism, the more or less complete repression of political freedom in, for example, a republic that has become a bureaucracy. Such totalism need not arrive or result in the terror Arendt perceived as the essence of twentieth-century totalitarianism, but its signs are, I believe, what she cautions us to beware of as “the true predicaments of our time [in] their authentic form.”*4 Of what does political freedom consist? To cast a secret ballot while alone in a voting booth, is that to be free? Is to teach, to write, or to read to be free? For Arendt, the simplest answer appears to be that the capacities to act and to speak —speech as distinct from mere talk—are the conditions sine qua non of political freedom. The question that then falls upon us is where and how do acting and speaking together generate power? Unlike military force—including the massed armies and novel weapons of World War II, which still endure—political power for Arendt, at least negatively, is not engendered by men and women talking to their peers about themselves, their families, or their careers. What does relate to power is the speaking out of citizens, their arguing with eloquence in public to persuade other citizens of their opinions. That is the opposite of obedience. Citizens fit words to events that by definition are not their own: no one says “my event,” because an event is objective, it stands over against many people, and its consequences affect a plurality of different people. The power contained within an event is the potentiality of citizens who recognize their faculty to render it, to a greater or lesser extent, tractable. The condition of that tractability is political commonalty, from which the stamp or mold of human inequality is effaced. Political commonalty is actualized public space, which Arendt calls “an island of freedom.” Such an island has only rarely appeared in a world that for the greater part of its history may be likened to a sea of distrust, malfeasance, and iniquity. Arendt’s letter to Robert Hutchins, included in this volume, is rich with examples of what she recognizes as common political concerns. To some readers, this may suggest the possibility of a common world. How that might develop, and what form of government would best suit it, are fundamental issues raised by attempting to understand such a world. Arendt’s view of realizing a common world was never optimistic, and she was reticent to discuss a form of government that had hardly yet, and then only briefly, appeared in the world. Still, on one occasion, when asked about the prospects of a council system of government, she replied: “Very slight, if at all. And yet perhaps, after all—in the wake of the next revolution.”*5 Her conception of council systems of governance is not detailed, for they would be new beginnings that cannot be fully grasped in advance. Nevertheless, her vision of them is immense. Arendt saw totalitarianism as “a novel form of government,” one of total destruction, and it had no positive counterpart in the sense that monarchy is the counterpart of tyranny, aristocracy of oligarchy, and democracy of ochlocracy. These pairings had remained virtually unchanged since antiquity, until Arendt added the council system as the positive counterpart to totalitarianism and, by extension, to all forms of totalism. Her most extensive account of this system of governance is in her essay on the Hungarian Revolution, which is published here in its entirety for the first time. At the basic level (which is also the basis of power) councils are composed of men and women who have common interests in issues such as fair wages and adequate housing, primary and secondary education, personal safety, and public security. These basic local levels would then elect higher and smaller regional levels of councils whose members would have researched and studied the specifics of resolving these issues. At the top of the pyramid, a governmental or steering council, also elected from below, would direct and organize the conglomerate of common interests within its jurisdiction. It may be worth mentioning here that Arendt strenuously opposed any notion of “world government,” as potentially the greatest tyranny imaginable. In council systems of government the freedom to move, to think, and to act would be present at each level, but power would be actualized only in the basic levels’ responsibility for the fulfillment of the duties and commitments of the levels above it. Council governments would result in a common world, one literally overflowing with interests that lie between (inter esse) the world’s plurality of men and women, relating them as acting and speaking individuals while maintaining sufficient space between them for each to address others from his or her unique point of view. This in-between space would exist in any one council system and in

Description:
Hannah Arendt was born in Germany in 1906 and lived in America from 1941 until her death in 1975. Thus her life spanned the tumultuous years of the twentieth century, as did her thought. She did not consider herself a philosopher, though she studied and maintained close relationships with two great
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.