ebook img

THE UNWRITTEN LAWS AND THE ANCESTRAL CONSTITUTION OF ANCIENT ATHENS PDF

194 Pages·8.754 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview THE UNWRITTEN LAWS AND THE ANCESTRAL CONSTITUTION OF ANCIENT ATHENS

Copyright by Martin Ostwald 195? THE UNWRITTEN LAWS AND THE ANCESTRAL CONSTITUTION OF ANCIENT ATHENS by Martin Ostwald Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements For the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, in the Faculty of Philosophy, Columbia University. CONTENTS Introduction 1 I. The Revision of the Laws from 411 to 403 B.C. and its Problems 30 II. Draco, Solon, and the Ancestral Constitution 55 III. Tribes, Trittyes, and Naukraries 72 TV. The Census Classes 90 V. The Rights of the People 95 a. The Assembly and the Election of the Magistrates 95 b. The Popular Lawcourt 106 VI. The Council and its Functions 110 VII. Safeguards for the Protection of the Ancestral Constitution 130 a. Oaths 130 b. Solon's Law on Faction 146 c. The Laws against Tyranny 150 d. The Legislative Process 173 e. The Ypacpl) itapavop^ov 180 VIII. Conclusion 189 INTRODUCTION An attempt to treat a subject which has been handled in as masterly and in many ways as definitive a fashion as have the unwritten laws in Rudolf Hirzel’s great work"*" would seem, at first glance, to be an ambitious, if not a foolhardy enterprise. Yet a fresh approach to the subject is not only justified, but even desirable. The reason for this is not merely the fact that, with the exception of one monograph by 2 the Italian scholar Francesco Flumene, no comprehensive treatment of the subject has appeared since 1903, but rather that much can and must be added to Hirzel’s findings. Thus, the following pages aim at supplementing and clarifying rather than superseding the work that has already been done on the unwritten laws. The questions which Hirzel raised are two. The first of these inquires into the nature and significance of the con­ cept of the unwritten law as opposed to the written law among the Athenians and examines the history of the conflict between these two kinds of law. The second question is an investiga­ tion into the origins and sanctions of the unwritten law. In his answer to the first question, Hirzel demonstrated 1. Rudolf Hirzel, n,'Ay(<yos No^oj n in Abhandlungen der philo- logisch-historischen Classe der kgl. sâchsischen Gesell­ schaft der Wissenschaften. (Leipzig; 19o3). Hr. 1. 2. Francesco Flumene, La legge “non scritta" nella storia e nella dottrina eticô^giuridica dellajSrecia classica (Sassari: Stamper!a della L.I.S., 192$). 2 the existence of two concepts of "unwritten law” among the Greeks. The Greeks, according to Hirzel,thought of the un­ written law not only as a general body of "natural” precepts which are common to all men, but also as a group of regula­ tions which, in addition to the written laws, governs the life of a particular community. But, although the existence of this distinction in Greek thought cannot be denied, Hirzel*s choice of a number of passages from Aristotle*s Rhetoric as his point of departure is unfortunate.3 The Rhetoric is a practical handbook, written for the student of oratory, and does, therefore, not lend itself very readily to the kind of philosophical and systematic treatment of the &YPtt9°l v6p,ot at which Hirzel aims. The distinction drawn in the Rhetoric between the «ypecpoe v<$p.oç which is general and exists by uni­ versal agreement2*" and the %yp@(pog vopog as a subdivision of the particular laws of the stateis demanded by the practical nature of the different subjects with which Aristotle has to deal within the framework of this treatise; it is not a theo­ retical and systematic distinction and the cleavage between the two in content is not as incisive as Hirzel thinks it is. The first discussion of the «yp«<poç v£p.oc in the Rhetoric occurs in the section on accusation and defense, in which Aristotle defines wrongdoing «btxecv ) as "the volun- * 4 5 3» See R. Hirzel, op. pit., pp. 1-11. 4. Aristotle, Rhetoric. I, 10, p. 1368 b 7-9 and 15, p. 1375 a 27 - 1375*TT7H 5. Ibid.. 13, p. 1373 b 4-6 and 1374 a 20-26. 3 tary infliction of an injury contrary to the law.But, since obviously not all kinds of wrongdoing are subject to legal pro­ ceedings in the technical sense, the law as such is divided in­ to the particular written law of an individual state and the 7 general unwritten law which exists by universal agreement. The distinction between the general and the particular law as such is maintained in a second passage, in which unjust and just actions (ebixifp-e're xel b ix< u£p.«T< ) are classified in g relation to these two types of law. But there is a difference. For while the general law is identified with "natural” law, it is not specifically designated as unwritten, even though the subsequent discussion makes it clear that Aristotle still thinks of it as unwritten. Instead, the law of a particular state is now subdivided into the written and the unwritten law. That a differentiation between the unwritten laws of a particu­ lar state and the general law of nature common to all men had to be introduced into a classification of particular just and unjust actions becomes clear if we consider that there are in every community certain unwritten rules of conduct and tradi­ tions which are peculiar to the particular society and which, contrary to the unwritten laws common to all men, are subject 6. Ibid., 10, p. 1368 b 6: edTto b% T& eôtxetv T& pXeEitTetv exovTe xepl tIv v&iov. 7» Ibid.. p. 1368 b 7-9: Y&JLOG b’êdTÏv .0 p.lv tbioç o bl xoivOG* X^yo^bl *biov u.lv^xeÔ.ç'V yeYpgjjqiévov icoXiTetîovTe 1, xoivlv bl ode eypacpe itepa itïd iv oBoXoŸeîdOat boxeï. 8. Ibid.. 13, p. 1373 b l-o: Ta b ebixq^aTa it^vTa xal Ta bixai- cop,®T< bi^Xcopev ap^^pevo 1 xptoTov êvTevôev. œptdT^i bl) T& bf- xete xaï T& abixa itp<5çyTe v<$|iovç btfo xaï xppg ovç 6dTt btx<5ç. bl y<5p-0V T&V p.ev TblOV T&V bl XO LVOV, Tb tov plv tIv ex«tnoi£ cop idpévov itpbç avTotfg, xal tovtov T&v plv aypa^ov tIv bl y6e Y*P *® P'P'8vov, xoivlv bl tIv xaT& <pi$dtv. 4 to change over a period of years. Later in the same chapter of the Rhetoric, Aristotle, still speaking about just and unjust actions, mentions two kinds of sypacpa : "The first is measured by an excess of virtue and vice which results in praise or blame, dishonour or honour and rewards, e. g. showing gratitude to a benefactor, returning a good deed, helping one's friends, etc.; the second fills de­ ficiencies in the particular written law.The examples ad­ duced to describe the first kind show that Aristotle is here thinking of the unwritten laws common to all men, although, as we shall see later, these may have their application within an individual state.The second type, which remedies the short­ comings of the particular written law, is in the sequel identi­ fied with t& éitieixéç , the equitable. The éxieixéç fills the 9. See, for example, Plato*s complaint in his Seventh Letter, 325 d-e, about the restored democracy: ... ou y&P eti év Toîç Ttov itŒT^pcûv rjGediv xal iTqbeupad lv î) itoXiç t)|1ûov#5 KpxeÏTo, ... tcî te tü5v v^icov Yp£p,p,aTa xal eGq bieœ6e(peTo xal éiteôtbov GaupadT&v odov; cf. also Aristotle, Politics, III, 16. p. 1287 b 6-8: ETi xvoicoTegot xal itep^ xup uoTépœv t5v xaT« YpappeTg v<5pa>v 01 xaTa t& eGq eldtv* coots Ttov xaT& yp4p,p.aTa avGpantog adçpaXédTepoç, àXX ou TûÿxaT& to eGog; and Ibid., Vi. 3, p. 1319 b 33- 1320 a 4, and Nicomachean Ethics. X, 9, p. 1180 a 32 - b 2, where Aristotle prescribes the enactment of particular unwritten laws as well of the written law as the task of the lawgiver. 10. Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, 13, p. 1374 a 21-25:,T*ÛTa î/êdTlv T& p&v xaG'vitepPoX^v apeTrjç xal xaxCaç, eç*oig ovetbr] xal Eitai- voi xal aTiutai xal Tipal xal ôcopeai, oiov t6 xapiv exeiv t$ Ttoi^davTi eu xal avTeuxoieJv t2>v e5 xo i^davTa xal gonGqTixbv etvai toîç <p(Xoi£ xal odfc aXXa ToiauTa, T& bfc tou ibiou vopou xal YGYPCP-P-Gvou eXXetpa. 11. Against R. Hirzel, op. cit.. 3-4, 6-7, and 32. 12. Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, 13, p. 1374 a 26 -b 23. 5 gap where the legislator could or would not give a precise def­ inition of the crime; it considers the intent and circumstances of an action rather than the act in itself and thus makes for leniency; it looks beyond the letter of the law to the intention of the lawgiver; and it prefers arbitration to a lawsuit. The humane and lenient nature of the licie ix£ç as defined here makes it clear that it is based upon a feeling common to all civilized men. If Aristotle defines it as a particular unwritten law, he does so because this kind of ènisixéç comes under consideration only as opposed to a particular written law and because the equitable differs with different cases that are tried before a court and in relation to the different laws on which trials may be based. The fourth and last treatment of the unwritten laws in the Rhetoric occurs in the section in which the use of laws as one of the "unscientific proofs” in a lawcourt ( aTeyvoi nCdTS lç) is discussed. "It is obvious," writes Aristotle, "that if the written law is opposed to our case, we have to use the general law and fairer and juster standards ; we have to say that a de­ cision ’to the best of one’s judgment’ means not to apply the written law rigidly; that equity ( t& ème ixéç ) is constant and unchangeable as is the general law — for it is based on nature — while the written laws change frequently." H On the face * o 13 • Ibid.. tl5, p. 1375 a 27-33 : tpevsp&v yàp oti, eàv p&v ivav- jioe y o YSYpap-P-Evoç t$ itpayp.a'ci, tod xolv$ xPTldT^ov xfX toïç suisixedTSpoiç xaX &ixaioT^poic, xal^oTi T& yvcop-rj 'ey aptdTy toot edTtv T& ph itavTeXcoç xphd®®1 'cote Yeypappévote. xaT oTi T& ptv l-Rieixbc âsX pévsi xaX ovbshots psTap^XXs i, ovd* o xoiv<$g (xaT& q>i$div y^P êdTiv) oi bè YeYPaPP^'V0rcoXXdxig. of it, there can be no question but that this account of the Sitieix^g conflicts with the preceding one: in the earlier treatment "equity" was changeable, here it is constant and un­ changeable; while formerly it was grouped with the particular law of a state, it is now mentioned in the same breath with the general law of nature. This last point shows the way to­ ward a solution of the conflict. The definitions of the ETtieuxéç differ because the context is different in the two cases. In the earlier instance, just and unjust actions are discussed in relation to particular laws of a state: since a given written law cannot cover in detail all the aspects and circumstances of the crime with which it deals, the eitieixéç which, in this case, naturally varies from one case to the next has to be applied as a corrective against too rigid an interpretation of the particular written law. The last pas­ sage, on the other hand, deals with a case in which an appeal to the general unwritten laws of nature is to override the authority of the whole body of the written law, because the latter favours the opposing side. Thus, the difference be­ tween the two treatments of the èitietxég is naturally explain­ ed by the context in which each is mentioned. It springs from the nature of the subject of rhetoric which Aristotle is dis­ cussing and which compels him to deal with a variety of spe­ cific points rather than with general theoretical concepts. In order to find a philosophical treatment of the eitieixéç , we have to turn to the fifth book of the Ethics, for the dis­ 7 tinctions found in the Rhetoric are not differences in the content of the êitie txéç but only in the ways in which it can be applied in practice under different circumstances. The close relation of the two kinds of èitieixég with particular and the general unwritten laws respectively shows that the general unwritten law of nature which may occasionally supersede the written laws of the state does not differ very much in content from the particular unwritten law which fills the gaps and deficiencies in the particular written law. There­ fore, the results which Hirzel elicited from his analysis of the Rhetoric have not gone very far in uncovering any fundamental distinctions that exist between different types of aypatpo i v<$p.oi. Nor does Hirzel*s investigation into the nature, origin, and sanction of the unwritten law of particular states present an exhaustive treatment of the subject. Hirzel again takes his cue from Aristotle.^ In both the Ethics and the Politics, Aristotle speaks of particular unwritten laws which, together with the written law, are to be established by the lawgiver. What exactly are these laws and what do they stipulate? Hirzel cites a further passage from Aristotle^ that the particular un- 14. For the following, see R. Hirzel, op. cit.. pp. 13-14» 15. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, X, 9, p. 1180 a 32 - b 2; Politics. VI, 3, p. 1319 b 33 - 1320 a 4. 16. Aristotle, Politics. Ill, 16, p. 1287 b 5-8, as cited by R. Hir&el.ôp/ tit., p. 14, n. 3

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.