ebook img

The Un-Stoic Spinoza: An Analysis of Spinoza, Aristotle, and Epicurus's Accounts of Pleasure PDF

191 Pages·2017·1.15 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Un-Stoic Spinoza: An Analysis of Spinoza, Aristotle, and Epicurus's Accounts of Pleasure

The Un-Stoic Spinoza: An Analysis of Spinoza, Aristotle, and Epicurus’s Accounts of Pleasure by Brandon Smith A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario © 2018, Brandon Smith ii Abstract: The purpose of this thesis is to provide a contrast to the literature on early modern Dutch philosopher Benedictus de Spinoza’s notable agreements with Stoic eudaimonism in his ethical framework. I intend to emphasize what is meaningfully non-Stoic in Spinoza’s own eudaimonism, while nevertheless granting that there is undeniable conceptual common-ground between them. I seek to illustrate where Spinoza departs from Stoic eudaimonism by outlining his agreements with two philosophers who function as a conceptual contrast to the Stoics: Aristotle and Epicurus. This thesis, in turn, lays out Aristotle, Epicurus, and Spinoza’s respective views on the ontological and ethical (that is eudaimonistic) nature of pleasure. All three philosophers are committed to two fundamental claims that are strongly antithetical to the Stoic view of pleasure: (a) pleasure holds a necessary connection to the health of one’s state of being and (b) pleasure is by nature good. iii Acknowledgements A project such as this is in no way a solitary endeavour. It involves support from a wide range of people. Firstly, I must thank Prof. Annie Larivée and Prof. Melissa Frankel for their enthusiasm, commitment, patience, and endless encouragement in helping me conceptualize and produce an undeniably ambitious work. Your guidance has not only bettered this thesis, but also me as a scholar. Secondly, I must thank my various companions. Nyx Halford, Rebecca Robb, and Courteney Crump, thank you for being the best friends an Aristotelian, Epicurean, or Spinozist could ask for. To Jennifer Shields, my first true Stoic friend, I express my gratitude to you for your welcoming nature, kind encouragement, and intellectual delight. To Emilie Duschesne, I give my utmost love and gratitude to you for your love of learning, thoughtfulness, loyalty, and profound compassion. It is an unquestionable fact that this project would never have been completed without you, and may it be a testament to the virtue of our friendship and perseverance. To my MS family, Patty, Rae, Orion, Tif, Katterina, Raya, Anna, Bex, Mica, Racheal, and Adri, thank you deeply for making me wealthy in love. Finally, I very humbly thank my parents, James and Janet Smith. I am where I am and I have done what I have done here, precisely because of your profound and endless love, support, patience, and encouragement. Thank you all for your causal role in my self-contentment, katastematic enjoyment, and true pleasure. iv Table of Contents Abstract: ………………………………………………………………………………………... ii Acknowledgements: …………………………………………………………………………… iii Table of Contents: ……………………………………………………………………………... iv List of Abbreviations: ………………………………………………………………………..... vi Preface: ……………………………………………………………………………………….... ix Chapter 1: Stoicism and Spinoza’s Eudaimonism………………………………………….... 1 1.1 Eudaimonism………………………………………………………………………... 1 1.2 A Dual-Aspect Conception of Emotion……………………………………………. 10 1.3 Stoic Pleasure………………………………………………………………………. 24 Chapter 2: Spinoza’s Account of Pleasure…………………………………………………... 30 2.1 Spinoza’s Ontology of Pleasure……………………………………………………. 30 2.2 Spinoza’s Ethics of Pleasure……………………………………………………….. 52 Chapter 3: Aristotle’s Account of Pleasure…………………………………………………. 69 3.1 Aristotle’s Ontology of Pleasure…………………………………………………… 69 3.2 Aristotle’s Ethics of Pleasure………………………………………………………. 79 Chapter 4: Epicurus’s Account of Pleasure…….………………………………………….. 104 4.1 Epicurus’s Ontology of Pleasure………………………………………………….. 104 4.2 Epicurus’s Ethics of Pleasure……………………………………………………... 121 Chapter 5: Spinoza’s Non-Stoic Eudaimonism……………………………………………. 136 v 5.1 Spinoza’s Relation to Aristotle and Epicurus…………………………………….. 136 5.2 Spinoza’s Relation to the Stoics………………………………………………….. 155 5.3 Conclusion………………………………………………………………………... 168 Bibliography: ……………………………………………………………………………….. 171 vi List of Abbreviations Aristotle: NE: Nicomachean Ethics OS: On the Soul PoA: Posterior Analytics PrA: Prior Analytics All references in the Nicomachean Ethics are translated by Christopher Rowe, Oxford UP, 2002. All other primary sources are taken from The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, edited by Jonathan Barnes, vols, 1 and 2, Princeton UP, 1984. Descartes: PP: Principles of Philosophy All references are taken from The Continental Rationalists, vol. 1, Cambridge UP, 1985. Past Masters. Epicurus: M: Letter to Menoceus PD: Principal Doctrines H: Letter to Herodotus I: Letter to Idomeneus vii All primary sources are taken from the The Epicurus Reader: Selected Writings and Testimonia, edited and translated by Brad Inwood and L.P. Gerson, Hackett, 1994. Spinoza: E: Ethics App. = Appendix Ax. = Axiom C = Corollary Def. = Definition Def. Aff. = Definitions of the Affects L = Lemma P = Proposition Post. = Postulate Pref. = Preface S = Scholium Ep: The Letters TIE: Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect All primary sources are taken from Spinoza: Complete Works, edited by Michael L. Morgan, translated by Samuel Shirley, Hackett, 2002. viii Epicurean/Stoic Sources: HB: Epictetus, Handbook LP: Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers OM: Cicero, On Moral Ends TD: Cicero, Tusculan Disputations A: Marcus Aurelius, Meditations ix Preface: The aim of this thesis is to examine, and subsequently to emphasize, the non-Stoic aspects of early modern Dutch philosopher Benedictus de Spinoza’s philosophy. For the purposes of this analysis, I will focus specifically on the literature concerning Spinoza’s relation to the ethical philosophy of the ancients, namely his eudaimonism. A eudaimonistic ethic understands the end of morality, i.e. the highest good, to be happiness. In English Spinoza scholarship, it is often shown that Spinoza’s eudaimonism shares a strong resemblance to the ancient Graeco-Roman eudaimonism of Stoicism. Scholars such as A.A. Long, Susan James, Jon Miller, Steven Nadler, and Derk Pereboom describe significant agreements between these two philosophies. Spinoza and the Stoics are argued to share a deterministic metaphysics, a critique of passions as involving erroneous judgments, a conception of living happily as synonymous with virtue and living according to Nature, a distinction between irrational (passions) and rational emotions, and finally the view that pleasure, suffering, striving, and avoidance are all (in some sense) primary emotions. Such literature, in turn, makes it persuasive to view Spinoza as a Neo-Stoic in many ways.1 Other literature, however, seeks to problematize this Neo-Stoic perspective on Spinoza’s ethical philosophy. Matthew Kisner argues that for Spinoza, contra Stoicism, passions are not absolutely opposed to virtue, and in fact serve as useful and necessary tools in gauging good/bad 1 James (“Spinoza the Stoic” 292, 310-16) and Pereboom (1) are explicit in supporting this claim, as both argue that Spinoza is reconceptualizing Stoicism in some sense. x and making oneself more virtuous (“Spinoza’s Virtuous Passions” 761-2, 777-81). Aurelia Armstrong too argues that Spinoza values passions in living happily, by emphasizing the “dynamic power” of individuals through the conatus, which involves a necessary relation between acting and being acted on in perseverance (14-8). Edwin Curley and Genevieve Lloyd take a different approach, claiming there are Epicurean elements to be found in Spinoza’s ethics (Epicureanism being a major Hellenistic opponent to Stoicism). Curley asserts that Spinoza’s Conatus Principle (E IIIP6) “neatly reconciles Stoic and Epicurean” conceptions of human nature “insofar as it incorporates into the conatus a striving not only for self-preservation [the primary desire for the Stoics],” but also pleasure as increased “power of action,” pleasure being the primary object of desire for the Epicureans (Behind the Geometrical Method 114-5). Lloyd also positions Spinoza between the Stoics and Epicureans, arguing that “Spinoza’s treatment of the emotions can be seen as ingeniously bringing together ancient Stoic repudiation of the passions as involving erroneous beliefs, and the apparently opposed Epicurean treatment of pleasure as the highest good . . .” (80). Through these scholars we consequently can see an illustration of the non-Stoic aspects of Spinoza’s eudaimonism in terms of the ethical value of passions, and more specifically pleasure. This thesis focuses on the subject of pleasure as the strongest point of ethical dissension between the Stoics and Spinoza. My approach, however, differs somewhat from the above scholars. While I too seek to emphasize Spinoza’s separation from Stoic ethical doctrine, I intend to accomplish this task by inverting the Stoic literature on Spinoza through a comparison of his eudaimonism with ancient eudaimonistic ethics that serve as a significant conceptual contrast to Stoicism, namely those of Aristotle and Epicurus. I favour this approach because it is possible to

Description:
I seek to illustrate where Spinoza departs from Stoic eudaimonism by . emotions. Such literature, in turn, makes it persuasive to view Spinoza as a superior to incontinence (akrasia), where one deliberates rationally about what
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.