THE TROPOLOGICAL UNIVERSE: ALEXANDER NECKAM'S ENCYCLOPEDIAS AND THE NATURES OF THINGS AT THE TURN OF THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY BY Tomas Zahora BA, Kansas Newman College, 1998 MA, Wichita State University, 2001 DISSERTATION SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AT FORDHAM UNIVERSITY NEW YORK AUGUST, 2007 UMI Number: 3301442 Copyright 2008 by Zahora, Tomas All rights reserved. INFORMATION TO USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleed-through, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. ® UMI UMI Microform 3301442 Copyright 2008 by ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This microform edition is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 E. Eisenhower Parkway PO Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 CONTENTS ABBREVIATIONS iv INTRODUCTION 1 Borges, Diderot, and Wikipedia Unchanging Natures of Changeable Things: Making a Case for the Study of Alexander Neckam Contribution and Methodology of the Dissertation CHAPTER 1. ALEXANDER NECKAM AND MEDIEVAL ENCYCLOPEDISM 29 Biographical Introduction The Scientist The Moralist The Encyclopedist CHAPTER 2. ENCYCLOPEDIC STRUCTURES 52 Encyclopedic Structures The First Encyclopedia: De naturis rerum Neckam's Hexaemeron: Solatium fide lis animae From the De naturis rerum to the Laus sapientie divine Cosmology, Physici, and the Encyclopedic Ordo CHAPTER 3. DE NATURIS RERUMTART I: PHYSICA 97 The Exegetical Tradition of Physica Physica in the Twelfth Century Neckam and Physica I: Coming to Terms with Traditions Neckam and Physica II: The Commentary on Martianus Capella Neckam and Physica III: Aristotle, the Salernitan Questions, and Anima Mundi Two Spheres of Knowledge: Human and Divine CHAPTER 4. DE NATURIS RERUM PART II: THE NATURES OF THINGS . 149 The Inscribed Universe The Tropological Matrix The Septem Dona: World Moved by Spiritual Bonds Neckam's Didactic-Encyclopedic Program Inquiry, Curiosity, Logic, and the Limits of Knowledge CHAPTER 5. LAUS SAPIENTIE DIVINE: PRAISING GOD IN A SUITABLE MANNER 190 Mere Poetry? Opus Geminum: The Vanity and Utility of Things Elements, Nature, and Serious Games Heresy and Rhetoric: Faustus, Zoilus, and Dualism Free Choice in a Fallen World: The Case of Harmful Animals n New Learning in the Laus sapientie divine A Proper Praise of God CHAPTER 6. AGAINST THE TIDES: ENCYCLOPEDIAS, EDUCATION, PARADIGMS, AND CHANGE 233 A Scholar's Conversion Neckam's Didactic Mission: The Ideal and the Reality The Mendicant Solution Everything in Its Place: The New Encyclopedias Conclusion: Paradigm Shift in the Thirteenth Century BIBLIOGRAPHY 272 ABSTRACT VITA in ABBREVIATIONS Berry Gregory Berry. "A Partial Edition of Alexander Neckam's Laus sapientie divine." Ed. and trans. Gregory L. Berry. Ph.D. Diss., Yale University, 1967. Commentary on Ecclesiastes Alexander Neckam. De naturis rerum and Commentary on Ecclesiastes {Incipit opus magistri Alexandri de sancto Albano de naturis rerum). Cambridge, Trinity College, R. 16. 4 (952), fols. 1- 237rb (s. xiiex). Commentary on Proverbs Alexander Neckam. Commentary on Proverbs {Incipit tractatus magistri Alexandri abbatis cyrenc' super parabolas Salomonis). Oxford, Jesus College 94, fols. 57ra-74rb (s. xiiiin). De naturis rerum Alexander Neckam. Alexandri Neckam De naturis rerum libri duo. With the Poem of the Same Author, De laudibus divinae sapientiae. Ed. Thomas Wright, 1-354. London, 1863. Reprint: Wiesbaden, 1967. Hunt. R. W. Hunt. The Schools and the Cloister: The Life and Writings of Alexander Nequam (1157-1217). Ed. Margaret Gibson. Oxford, 1984. Laus sapientie divine Alexander Neckam. Alexandri Neckam De naturis rerum libri duo. With the Poem of the Same Author, De laudibus divinae sapientiae. Ed. Thomas Wright, 357-503. London, 1963. Reprint: Wiesbaden, 1967. NECAP Alexander Neckam. Commentary on Martianus Capella {Alexander Nequam super Marcianum de nupciis Mercurii et Philologie). Oxford, Bodleian Library, Digby 221, fols. 34vb-88ra (s. xiv). NECS Alexander Neckam. Sermons 1-53. Oxford, Bodleian Library, Wood empt. 13 (SC 8601), fols. l-144v (s. xiiiin). Speculum speculationum Alexander Neckam. Speculum speculationum. Ed. Rodney M. Thomson. New York, 1988. Wedge George F. Wedge. De naturis rerum. "Alexander Neckam's De naturis rerum: A Study, together with Representative Passages in Translation." Ed. and trans. George F. Wedge. Ph.D. Diss., University of Minnesota, 1967. IV INTRODUCTION Borges, Diderot, and the Wikipedia I affirm that the library is interminable. The idealists argue that the hexagonal halls are a necessary form of absolute space or, at least, of our intuition of space. They contend that a triangular or pentagonal hall is inconceivable. (The mystics claim that to them ecstasy reveals a round chamber containing a great book with a continuous back circling the walls of the room; but their testimony is suspect; their words, obscure. That cyclical book is God.) Let it suffice me, for the time being, to repeat the classic dictum: The Library is a sphere whose consummate center is any hexagon, and whose circumference is inaccessible. Jorge Borges' library of Babel contains, in printed and bound, carefully shelved tomes, every possible permutation of letters. It is "a sphere whose consummate center is any hexagon, and whose circumference is inaccessible," constituting a vision of God translated into a tangible infinity of beehive-like hexagonal rooms lined with shelves in unfailing order. Its totality makes it absolute, but also monstrous: it is known that no single individual can perceive its true structure or comprehend more than a fragment of its contents. Borges' nightmare, not unfamiliar to modern researchers wandering through stacks of research libraries, underlines the paradoxical equivalence of total knowledge and no knowledge at all. It also embodies the concerns of anyone dealing with the nature of human knowing, especially those who aspire to an encyclopedic grasp of things. Among the lesser known ironies of history belongs the fact that the parents of modern encyclopedism, Denis Diderot and Jean d'Alembert, whose Encyclopedic is used as an example of the enthusiasm of the Enlightenment and the final breaking away from the chains of sterile scholastic tradition and its Aristotle, expressed a vision just as unsettling as that of the Argentine writer: ' Jorge Luis Borges, "The Library of Babel," in Ficciones, trans. Anthony Kerrigan (New York, 1962), 80. See, e.g. John North, "Encyclopedias and the Art of Knowing Everything," in Pre-Modern Encyclopaedic Texts: Proceedings of the Second COMERS Congress, Groningen, 1-4 July 1996, ed. Peter Binkley (Leiden, 1997), 183-199. 1 As long as the centuries continue to unfold, the number of books will grow continually, and one can predict that a time will come when it will be almost as difficult to learn anything from books as from the direct study of the whole universe. It will be almost as convenient to search for some bit of truth concealed in nature as it will be to find it hidden away in an immense multitude of bound volumes. The future imagined by Diderot was overshadowed by mountains of books more impenetrable than the phenomena they set out to understand and explain. A firm understanding of the totality of human knowledge by a single individual—always more a matter of ideals than of measurable actualities—would from now on resolutely, forever, remain outside of anyone's reach. "When one considers the immense material for an encyclopedia," Diderot wrote, "the only thing one perceives distinctly is that it cannot be the work of a single man. How could a single man, in the short span of his life, manage to comprehend and develop the universal system of nature and art?" The authors of the Encyclopedic voiced a growing concern among eighteenth- century intellectuals: the challenge of understanding, interpreting, apd if possible utilizing human knowledge despite the growing disparity between the limited capacity for individual knowledge and the vastly larger capacity for collective knowledge.5 Diderot's and D'Alembert's resolution of the quandary included two important steps, both adaptations of eighteenth-century encyclopedic techniques. The first consisted in assigning individual articles to specialists—or at least to scholars who had a more detailed knowledge of the subject than the average layman. In the end, besides numerous Denis Diderot, "Encyclopedic" quoted in Daniel Rosenberg, "An Eighteenth Century Time Machine. The Encyclopedia of Denis Diderot," in Postmodernism and the Enlightenment: New Perspectives in Eighteenth-Century French Intellectual History (New York, 2001), ed. Daniel Gordon, 45-66, at 54. 4 Diderot, "Encyclopedia" article in the Encyclopedic, vol. 5:635, trans. Philip Stewart, The Encyclopedia of Diderot and D 'Alembert, Collaborative Translation Project, http://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t7text/text- idx?c=did;cc=did;rgn=main;view=text;idno=did2222.0000.004. Richard Yeo, Encyclopaedic Visions: Scientific Dictionaries and Enlightenment Culture (Cambridge, 2001), xi-xiii, 79-85. 2 contributions by Diderot and thousands of articles by the work's single most important contributor, Louis de Jaucourt, the Encyclopedic included contributions by such luminaries as Necker, Montesquieu, Rousseau, and Voltaire. The second step involved a coordination of the need for the inclusion of a taxonomy of human arts and sciences with the recognition that neither the taxonomy nor the arts and sciences existed in a permanent form. In order to provide an easily accessible body of articles and at the same time an idea of the relationship between individual sciences, arts, and crafts, Diderot and D'Alembert organized the bulk of the work alphabetically, attached a volume of illustrative plates, a two-volume index, and a taxonomical table of human knowledge. The result was a vast encyclopedia in 35 volumes exemplifying the practical goals of the Enlightenment, in particular that of providing knowledge stripped of the needless complexities of sectarian (meaning Catholic) superstition, and contributing to the tangible, material improvement of the human race. The Encyclopedic's built-in flexibility was also very modern. It meant that subsequent editions could update and add to original articles and change the appended tables without having to change the structure of he entire work. This also meant that each version of the Encyclopedic would represent a pinnacle of human achievement at a particular point of time. Should disaster strike—for Diderot and D'Alembert intended for their work to be a roadmap as much as an ark or time-capsule of the vast fields of knowledge—the Encyclopedie could be used as a blueprint for the restoration of the most advanced state of human achievement. Thus even if no single individual could ever again grasp the principles of all sciences, the progressive goal of the Enlightenment would be served. A philosophe would be allowed 6 Rosenberg, "An Eighteenth-Century Time Machine. The Encyclopedia of Denis Diderot," in Postmodernism and the Enlightenment: New Perspectives in Eighteenth-Century French Intellectual History, ed. Daniel Gordon (New York, 2001), 45-66. 3 to form at least an educated opinion of the matter, and collectively humanity would be provided with the means to never again have to experience another Dark Age. The intended flexibility of the Encyclopedie easily agrees with the spirit of our own age, familiar with instant access to information and the "intellectual free-for-all" of Wikipedia. To the generation brought up on the near-infinite possibilities of global communication and never-before-imagined scope and rapidity of hyperlinking anything with anything else, Diderot's "Encyclopedia" article with its concerns and hopes represents an uncannily precise forecast of things to come. This includes another characteristic of the modern age: the open challenge of those aspects of tradition that fail to keep pace with the times: Now that philosophy is rapidly advancing; that it submits all the objects within its jurisdiction to its power; now that its tone is the prevailing one, and we are beginning to shake off the yoke of authority and example to hold to the laws of reason, there exists hardly a single elementary and dogmatic work with which we can be wholly satisfied. We find these productions imitate those of men, and not nature's truth. We dare raise doubts against Aristotle and Plato; and the time has come when works which still enjoy the highest reputation will lose some of it, or will even be forgotten; certain genres of literature which, for want of real life and actual practices to serve as their models, are incapable of an invariable and reasonable poetics, will be neglected; and others which will remain, sustained by their intrinsic value, will take on an entirely new form. Such is the effect of the progress of reason; progress which will overturn so many statues, and redress some which have been overturned.8 The fact that a single individual can no longer hope to comprehend the full range of human knowledge may be disquieting to some; but perhaps it is good that such universalist dreams join the trash-bin of history. What matters is the certainty of progress, which for Diderot at least is enough to let him remain optimistic. In light of the failures of grand social-engineering schemes enacted in the spirit of the Enlightenment during the 7 Julian Dibbell, "Factually Speaking: Think Wikipedia is error-ridden? Britannica's nearly as bad—and isn't nearly as nimble," The Village Voice 22 December 2005, online edition. 8 Diderot, "Encyclopedia," trans. Philip Stewart. 4 nineteenth and twentieth centuries, and of the potentially disastrous consequences of the boundless hopes invested in industrialization it is becoming more difficult to share Diderot's optimism. But the machinery of transformation (Diderot's "progress of reason") fueled by the sciences is showing no signs of abating. If we ask many computer scientists, physicists, biologists and cognitive scientists about their current achievements and about further potential of human understanding we find different vocabulary but the same revolutionary message: we have a better understanding of phenomena than we have ever had before, and we can know still more. In order to do so we may undermine seemingly permanent traditions and institutions, and overturn previously held beliefs, including our own. Wikipedia's knocking on the doors of Britannica and Google's promised assault on the guarded access to information banks and libraries are only hints of the magnitude of possible transformation. Today, a college student with a computer and internet access is in a better position to access highly specialized information than an experienced scientist roaming academic libraries only a generation ago, and may have better means and attitude to digest and utilize what to Diderot and Borges constituted a scholarly nightmare. In a similar manner, the authors of the Encyclopedic sought to detach themselves from what they saw as a backward, superstitious tradition of Europe's Christian past: the heritage of patristic Platonism exemplified by Saint Augustine, and of medieval scholasticism with its veneration of Aristotle. In order to move forward, the philosophes thought humanity had to turn away from the monolithic, superstitious stability of the medieval past dominated by faith and Catholic institutions. Just as Wikipedia embodies the internet age's resolution to the handling of encyclopedic frustrations of totality and 5
Description: