ebook img

The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity (Sather Classical Lectures) PDF

276 Pages·1982·30.26 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity (Sather Classical Lectures)

The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity ALBRECHT DIHLE SATHER CLASSICAL LECTURES Volume Forty Eight The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity T h is One BXD4-8NS-CUZK naterial The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity ALBRECHT DIHLE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS Berkeley * Los Angeles • London Copyrighted material University of California Press Berkeley and Los Angeles, California University of California Press, Ltd. London, England © 1982 The Regents of the University of California Printed in the United States of America 12 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Dihle, Albrecht. The theory of will in classical antiquity. (Sather classical lectures; v. 48) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Free will and determinism—History. 2. Philosophy, Ancient— History. I. Title. II. Series. BI87.F7D54 128'.3 81-7424 ISBN 0-520-04059-7 AACR2 Copyrighted material CONTENTS PRPFArE VII I COSMOLOGICAI CONCEPTIONS IN THF SECOND CENTURY A.O. 1 II THF GRFFK VIFW OF HUMAN ACTION I 20 IÎI THF GRFFK VIEW OF HUMAN ACTION Π 48 IV ST. PAUL AND PHILO te V PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION IN LATE ANTIQUITY 99 VI ST. AUGUSTINE AND HIS CONCEPT OF WILL 123 m APPENDIX I APPENDIX II Ι M) NOTES 159 BIBLIOGRAPHY 24i INDFX OF GRFFK AND LATIN WORDS 259 INDFV OF PASSAGES CITED ?6() GFNFRAI INDEX ?fiX PREFACE This book contains the text of six lectures which I had the honour of delivering at Berkeley in 1974. They are presented in a version considerably fuller than that which was given originally, al though their oral style has been preserved. I am glad to be given the opportunity to express my profound grati tude to all those who have kindly helped me, directly or indirectly, in producing and publishing the present book. First of all, I wish to thank the members of the Department of Classics of the University of California at Berkeley and their chairman in 1974, Professor T. E. Rosenmeyer. They elected me to serve as a Sather Professor at Berkeley, they extended their warm and generous hospitality to my family, and they made my stay at Berkeley stimulating and rewarding beyond all expectation. Mr. (now Professor) G. W. Most kindly went through the whole manuscript in order to Anglicize—wherever this was possible—what I had formulated according to the rules of English elementary grammar. Moreover, he added valuable remarks and prevented me from many mistakes. The manuscript was finished in 1978. The subject of the lectures is large and complex, and inevitably im plies problems which are, strictly speaking, outside my competence. So I tried to make clear both in the text and notes whenever I had to depend on previous scholarship. Yet my being indebted to colleagues and friends extends far beyond these documented cases, especially in the field of theological and philosophical studies. In this area I was greatly helped and continuously instructed, over many years and quite independently from the production of this book, by Professor Hans von Campenhausen and Professor Gunther Patzig. The errors and mistakes, however, which specialists are likely to discover in various passages of this book, are entirely my own. 1 wish to thank Mrs. Karin Harmon for the great pains she took in producing the typescripts of several versions of the book. Miss Wal- VII Co;?yr ghlec material vin Preface traut Foss and Dr. William Furley for sharing the tedious cask of proof reading and indexing, and the staff of the University of California Press for their accurate operation. My wife made greater sacrifices for my scholarly work than anyone else. She also created the conditions under which this book could be produced. Copyrighted material I. Cosmological Conceptions in the Second Century AD BF.TWFF.N λ.Γ>. 170 and 180 the famous physician Gaten published, among other works, the treatise. On tlx Parts of the Human Body. In the chapter on the eyes he deals in great detail with rhe fact that eyelashes are characteristically different in size, number, and quality from any other kind of human hair, and points out that this very fact can be easily explained by the function of eyelashes in the human organism. His argument, therefore, is worked out entirely along the lines of Aristotelian or Stoic teleology. In this context Galen inserts an interesting digression. The Jews, he says, derive rhe origin and structure of the universe exclusively from the arbitrary intention of the divine creator.' He can transform a lump of earth into a horse or a bird or whatever he pleases. Creation depends solely and entirely on the will of the creator. This opinion, according to Galen, is certainly preferable to the aleatoric conception of Epicurus who attributes everything to chance. But it is quite incompatible with Greek ideas of cosmology and cosmogony as expounded most clearly by Plato and Aristotle. The Greek creator or demiurge brings to reality only what reason evinces as being possible,'1 and from all possibilities he always chooses the best one.' A hundred years earlier, in about A. 15. 60 or 70, the Elder Pliny {/tat. hist. 2.27) had already formulated the very same creed of Greco- Roman intellectuals wirhour any reference to Jewish ideas. "Not even for God are all things possible . .. he cannot bestow eternity on mor­ tals . . . he cannot cause twice ten not to be twenty or do other things along similar lines, and these facts unquestionably demonstrate the power of nature." Seneca (ep. 95.-19) made a similar statement at nearly che same time, in Stoic terms and with special reference to the relation between God and man: Errat qui deos pillai nacere nolle: non poisunt. "They who believe the gods do not want to do harm are mistaken; the gods cannot." The nature of the gods makes it impossible for them to do Copyrighted material 2 Cosmological Conceptions in the Second Century A.D. any harm, and even a god is nor able to change his nature.''Cicero does, in fact, regard the will of the creator as the ultimate cause of man's distinguished position in the universe (tfe kg. 1.27). Yet this will does not mean arbitrary intention or unpredictable exercise of divine power. Every act of divine rule over the universe is but a detail of a comprehen sive and perfectly rational programme by which is caused the order, the beauty, and the usefulness of the cosmos. Theology in the tradition of Greco-Roman philosophy was hardly concerned with the problem of divine power, the most significant dif ference between man and God according to the fundamental religious experience: ènei ή πολύ φέριεροί eioiv (since, in truth, they are might­ ier by far), to use a Homeric formula. Greek philosophical theology concentrated instead, from the very beginning, on the order, reg­ ularity, and beauty that are established and maintained through divine activity. Here Greek philosophy found the mast striking, though un­ derstandable and almost predictable, manifestation of the divine—in contrast to ideas prevailing in many other religions (cf. Heraclitus Β 114). At the end of the dialogue De divinalione, Cicero distinguishes between superstitio and reÎigio: the first depresses the hearts of believers by making them afraid of the power and the unpredictable actions of the gods. The other leads to admiration and understanding of the order and beauty which are brought about by the divine rule (2.148). This philosophical theology or cosmology rests on a basic presup position: the human mind has to be capable of perceiving and under standing the rarional order of the universe and, consequently, the na ture of the divine. Everything that goes on in the universe has been arranged and initiated by the same reason that man has been given, so that he may understand his own position in rhe universe and act accord ingly. There is no need for assuming behind or apart from the entirely rational programming of reality a will of which the impulse or man ifestation is unpredictable. The word ιό θέλον, used by the astrologer Vettius Valens (5.9) in order to denote what is going to happen accord­ ing to the cosmic order, has not that connotation of will. Narure, cos­ mos, order of the universe, providence—all these concepts illustrate that everything happens only in consequence of a preconceived and ra­ tional arrangement without a separate will spontaneously interfering with the process. That presupposition is not invalidated by the fact that Copyrighted material Cosmoiogical Conceptions in the Second Century λ.ι>. 3 man, in his empirical condition, is not always capable of lull apprecia­ tion of the cosmic order. That very conception underlies a great many philosophical theories. For the Stoics, for inscance (Cleanthes ap. Sen. ep. 41.1, quaest. rial. 2.35), the purpose of prayer was only to ascertain the identity between reason as the ruler of the universe and reason as the leading force in the human soul. But even Platonists like Plutarch Us. el Os. 1) or Maximus of Tyre (OK 5) who regarded prayer as a dialogue between two partners," explicitly rejected the idea that prayer could influence or change the intention of God. Such a change could only lead to something worse, since God could not possibly improve on his own perfect rationality. Prayer had only to contribute to a fuller cognition of God. It seemed useless to a Platonist to comply with the intention of God without try­ ing to understand it. The practice of popular religion, in Greece and elsewhere, had al­ ways used prayer to influence or change rather than to understand the intention of the divinity involved. So prayer, in the popular sense, re­ ferred to the gods' power and benevolence and was nor primarily meant to appreciate the immovable order of their government. The notion that divine rule over both cosmic and human affairs is perfect and ra­ tional was, after all, a concept resulting from philosophical specula­ tion.'' It was with regard ro the popular notion of prayer that the physi­ cian and philosopher Sextus repeatedly contrasted prayer with telling the truth {adv. math. 7.401, hyp. 3.244 etc.). To pray according to popular practice means, from the philosophical point of view, to dis­ regard the perfect order which the gods have established. Their power, sublimity, goodness—all result from their perfect rationality, accord­ ing to the belief of Galen and his contemporaries. "" This belief, however, which Galen formulated to contest the Biblical concept of creation, was deeply rooted in the philosophical tradition, which had become, in the course of nearly five centuries, one of the main factors of general education. Both conceptions, the Greek and the Biblical, were monotheistic, despite their disagreement in many other respects. Whenever Greek philosophers became involved in theological problems, they ended, with a few exceptions, at the conception of a divine monarch of the universe.I: Proclus, the Neoplatonist of the fifth century A.15., found this conception fully developed already in Homer Copyrighted material

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.