ebook img

The Theory of Communicative Action Volume 1: Reason and the rationalization of society PDF

508 Pages·1987·31.16 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Theory of Communicative Action Volume 1: Reason and the rationalization of society

THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION Volume 1 REASON AND THE RATIONALIZATION OF SOCIETY Ji.irgen Habermas Translated by Thomas McCarthy Beacon Press Boston German text: Copyright ©1981 by Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, originally published as Theorie des Kommunikativen Handelns, Band I, .. Handlungsrationalitiit und gesel/scha{tliche Rationalisierur>o Introduction and English translation: Copyright ©1984 ·con Press Beacon Press books are published u 'he ausr: of the Unitarian Universalist Associ< • ·' >f Cong1 in North America, 25 Beacon Street, .or, Mas::,.;. .J8 Published simultaneously in Canada by Fitzhenry & Whiteside Limited, Toronto All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America (hardcover) 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 (paperback) 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data: Habermas, Jiirgen. The theory of communicative action. Translation of: Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Includes bibliographical references and index. Contents: v. 1. Reason and the rationalization of society. 1. Sociology-Philosophy-Collected works. 2. Rationalism-Collected works. 3. Social action Collected works. 4. Communication-Philosophy Collected works. 5. Functionalism-Collected works. I. Title. HM24.H3213 1983 301' .01 82·72506 ISBN 0·8070·1506·7 (v. I) ISBN 0-8070-1507·5 (v. ll(pbk.) Contents Volume 1: Reason and the Rationalization of Society Translator's Introduction v Author's Preface xxxix I. Introduction: Approaches to the Problem of Rationality 1 1. "Rationality" -A Preliminary Specification 8 2. Some Characteristics of the Mythical and the Modern Ways of Understanding the World 43 3. Relations to the World and Aspects of Rationality in Four Sociological Concepts of Action 75 4. The Problem of Understanding Meaning in the Social Sciences 102 II. Max Weber's Theory of Rationalization 143 1. Occidental Rationalism 157 2. The Disenchantment of Religious-Metaphysical Worldviews and the Emergence of Modern Structures of Consciousness 186 3. Modernization as Societal Rationalization: The Role of the Protestant Ethic 216 4. The Rationalization of Law. Weber's Diagnosis of the Times 243 III. Intermediate Reflections: Social Action, Purposive Activity, and Communication 273 IV. From Lukacs to Adorno: Rationalization as Reification 339 1. Max Weber in the Tradition of Western Marxism 345 2. The Critique of Instrumental Reason 366 Notes 403 Index 459 Contents Volume 2. Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason V. The Paradigm Shift in Mead and Durkheim: From Purposive Activity to Communicative Action 1. The Foundations of Social Science in the Theory of Communication 2. The Authority of the Sacred and the Normative Background of Communicative Action 3. The Rational Structure of the Linguistification of the Sacred VI. Intermediate Reflections: System and Lifeworld 1. The Concept of the Lifeworld and the Hermeneutic Idealism of Interpretive Sociology 2. The Uncoupling of System and Lifeworld VII. Talcott Parsons: Problems in the Construction of Social Theory 1. From Normativistic Theory of Action to Systems Theory of Society 2. The Development of Systems Theory 3. The Theory of Modernity VIII. Concluding Reflections: From Parsons through Weber to Marx 1. A Backward Glance: Weber's Theory of Modernity 2. Marx and the Thesis of Internal Colonization 3. The Tasks of a Critical Theory of Society Translator's Introduction Since the beginning of the modern era the prospect of a limitless advance of science and technology, accompanied at each step by moral and political improvement, has exercised a considerable hold over Western thought. Against this the radicalized con sciousness of modernity of the nineteenth century voiced funda mental and lasting doubts about the relation of "progress" to freedom and justice, happiness and self-realization. When Nietzsche traced the advent of nihilism back to the basic values of Western culture-"because nihilism represents the ultimate logical conclusion of our great values and ideas"-he gave classic expression to a stream of cultural pessimism that flows power fully again in contemporary consciousness. Antimodernism is rampant today, and in a variety of forms; what they share is an opposition to completing "the project of modernity" insofar as this is taken to be a matter of rationalization. There are, of course, good reasons for being critical of the illusions of the Enlighten ment. The retreat of "dogmatism" and "superstition" has been accompanied by fragmentation, discontinuity and loss of mean ing. Critical distance from tradition has gone hand in hand with anomie and alienation, unstable identities and existential inse curities. Technical progress has by no means been an unmixed blessing; and the rationalization of administration has all too often meant the end of freedom and self-determination. There is no need to go ori enumerating such phenomena; a sense of having exhausted our cultural, social, and political resources is perva sive. But there is a need to subject these phenomena to careful analysis if we wish to avoid a precipitate abandonment of the achievements of modernity. What is called for, it might be argued, is an enlightened suspicion of enlightenment, a reasoned critique v vi REASON AND THE RATIONALIZATION OF SOCIETY of Western rationalism, a careful reckoning of the profits and losses entailed by ''progress.'' Today, once again, reason can be defended only by way of a critique of reason. Jiirgen Habermas has been called "the last great rationalist," and in a certain sense he is. But his is a rationalism with important differences; for, in good dialectical fashion, he has sought to incorporate into it the central insights of the critique of rational ism. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, published in two volumes in 1981, represents the culmination to date of his efforts.1 Reason and the Rationalization of Society is a translation, with minor revisions, of the first volume; a translation of the second volume, System and Lifeworld: A Critique of Functionalist Reason, will follow. There are both advantages and disadvantages to publishing the two volumes separately. On the positive side, the Anglo American reception of a major work in twentieth-century social theory can get underway sooner, at a time when the questions it treats are moving rapidly to the center of intellectual interest. As the English-language discussion of these issues has not yet congealed into hard and fast patterns, the appearance of this volume at this time may well play a significant role in structuring it. On the negative side, there is the fact that Habermas sustains a continuous line of thought across the near1 y 1, 200 pages of the two volumes. The part of the argument deployed in Volume 1, while certainly intelligible and interesting in its own right, might well be misconstrued when detached from that larger context. In this introduction I hope to reduce that danger by sketching the argument of the book as a whole, especially the points devel oped in Volume 2. In the preface, and elsewhere, Habermas tells us that The Theory of Communicative Action has three interrelated concerns: (1) to develop a concept of rationality that is no longer tied to, and limited by, the subjectivistic and individualistic premises of modern philosophy and social theory; (2) to construct a two-level concept of soCiety that integrates the lifeworld and system paradigms; and, finally, (3) to sketch out, against this background, a critical theory of modernity which analyzes and accounts for its pathologies in a way that suggests a redirection rather than an abandonment of the project of enlightenment. Part I of this introduction deals with the first of these concerns; part II con siders the lifeworld/system question and its relevance for a theory of contemporary society. But first, one general remark on Habermas's approach: He develops these themes through a some- THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION vn what unusual combination of theoretical constructions with his torical reconstructions of the ideas of "classical" social theorists. The thinkers discussed-Marx, Weber, Durkheim, Mead, Lukacs, Horkheimer, Adorno, Parsons-are, he holds, still very much alive. Rather than regarding them as so many corpses to be dis sected exegetically, he treats them as virtual dialogue partners from whom a great deal that is of contemporary significance can still be learned. The aim of his "historical reconstructions with systematic intent'' is to excavate and incorporate their positive contributions, to criticize and overcome their weaknesses, by thinking with them to go beyond them. Interspersed throughout these critical dialogues with the classics are numerous excurses and two chapter-length Zwischen betrachtungen, or intermediate reflections, devoted to systematic questions. The concluding chapter attempts to combine the fruits of his historical reconstructions with the results of his systematic reflections in sketching· a critical theory of modernity. For reasons that Habermas sets forth in the text and that I briefly mention below, he holds that an adequate theory of society must integrate methods and problematics previously assigned exclusively to either philosophy or empirical social science. In the first portion of this introduction I consider some of the more "philosophical" aspects of the theory of communica tive action; in the second part, I turn to more "sociological" themes. I The Cartesian paradigm of the solitary thinker-solus ipse-as the proper, even unavoidable, framework for radical reflection on knowledge and morality dominated philosophical thought in the early modern period. The methodological solipsism it entailed marked the approach of Kant at the end of the eighteenth century no less than that of his empiricist and rationalist predecessors in the two preceding centuries. This monological approach pre ordained certain ways of posing the basic problems of thought and action: subject versus object, reason versus sense, reason versus desire, mind versus body, self versus other,· and so on. In the course of the nineteenth century this Cartesian paradigm and the subjectivistic orientation associated with it were radically challenged. Early in the century Hegel demonstrated the intrin sically historical and social character of the structures of con sciousness. Marx went even further, insisting that mind is not viii REASON AND THE RATIONALIZATION OF SOCIETY the ground of nature but nature that of mind; he stressed that human consciousness is essentially embodied and practical and argued that forms of consciousness are an encoded representa tion of forms of social reproduction. In establishing the continuity of the human species with the rest of nature, Darwin paved the way for connecting intelligence with self-preservation, that is, for a basically functionalist conception of reason such as we find in American Pragmatism. Nietzsche and Freud disclosed the un conscious at the heart of consciousness, the role of the precon ceptual and nonconceptual within the conceptual realm. Histori cism exhibited in detail the historical and cultural variability of categories of thought and principles of action. The end result was, in Habermas's phrase, a "desublimation of spirit" and, as a con sequence, a "disempowering of philosophy." But the history of ideas is full of surprises; and twentieth century philosophy bore witness to the continued power of the Cartesian model, in a variety of forms-from Edmund Husserl's openly Cartesian phenomenology to the Cartesianism lying just below the surface of logical empiricism. More recently, however, the critique of this model has been vigorously renewed. Thus we are said to be living in a "post-Heideggerian," "post Wittgensteinian," "poststructuralist" age. The spirit has once again been desublimated. Subjectivity has been shown to be "infiltrated with the world" in such a way that "otherness is carried to the very heart of selfhood."2 This "twilight of subjectivity'' is not merely an intraphilosophic affair, a reminder to philosophers that they are not after all the high priests of culture.3 lt is the theoretical center of the stream of antimodern ist thought I mentioned at the outset; thus it has implications that go well beyond the confines of academic philosophy. The critique of "rootless rationalism" goes hand in hand with an unmasking of the anthropocentric, egoistic, possessive, and domineering aspects of Western individualism; together they frequently serve as a prologue to the rejection of central concepts of European humanism. We cannot ignore the question of whether, in the absence of an archimedean point outside the world, anything can be salvaged from these emphatic concepts and the universalist claims connected with them. And if the subject is desublimated, can we really expect much more from general social "theory" than a historicist contemplation of the variety of forms of life in the musee imaginaire of the past; or a hermeneuFc dialogue with other cultures and epochs about the common concerns of THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION ix human life; or, perhaps, a genealogical unmasking of any pretense to universal validity? Habermas's response to the decline of the paradigm of con sciousness is an explicit shift to the paradigm of language-not to language as a syntactic or semantic system, but to language in-use or speech. Thus he develops the categorial framework and normative foundations of his social theory in the form of a general theory of communicative action. "If we assume that the human species maintains itself through the socially coordinated activities of its members and that this coordination is established through communication-and in certain spheres of life, through commu nication aimed at reaching agreement-then the reproduction of the species also requires satisfying the conditions of a rationality inherent in communicative action" (1:397). In the atomistic perspective of much of modern thought, the subject stands over against a world of objects to which it has two basic relations: representation and action. Accordingly, the type of rationality associated with this model is the "cognitive-instru mental" rationality of a subject capable of gaining knowledge about a contingent environment and putting it to effective use in intelligently adapting to and manipulating that environment. By stressing the fact that the goal-directed actions of different individuals are socially coordinated, Habermas shifts our attention to the broader context of individual purposive actions, to the structures of social interaction in which teleological actions are located. The communicative model of action does not equate action with communication. Language is a means of communica tion which serves mutual understanding, whereas actors, in coming to an understanding with one another so as to coor dinate their actions, pursue their particular aims ... Concepts of social action are distinguished by how they specify this coordination among the goal-directed actions of different par ticipants-as the interlacing of egocentric calculations of utility, as a socially integrating consensus· about norms and values instilled through cultural tradition and socialization, or as reaching understanding in the sense of a cooperative process of interpretation ... The interpretive accomplish ments on which cooperative processes [of situation .defi nition) are based represent the mechanism for coordinating action; communicative action is not exhausted by the act of reaching understanding ... (1: 101)

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.