THE TECHNOCRATS 1919-1967: A CASE STUDY OF CONFLICT AND CHANGE IN A SOCIAL MOVEMENT by David Adair B .A. , Sir George Williams University, 1967 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Political Science, Sociology and Anthropology DAVID ADAIR, 1970 SIMON FIEA'SER UN~VERSITY January, 1970 APPROVAL Name: David Adair Degree: Master 'of Arts Title of Thesis: The Technocrats 1919-1967: A Case Study of Conflict and Change in a Social Movement Examining Committee: . Pr6fessor G RUSE, Senior Supervisor . Professor David F Aberle, External Examiner UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH. COLUMBIA VANCOUVER, B C. ABSTRACT The study examines the organizational and ideological changes within the Technocracy movement during the period 1919-1968. An attempt is made to account for the development within the movement of active reform factors at different points in time. The contrasts and conflicts between the active reform factions and the usu- ally more passive, though ideologically revolutionary main segment of the movement, are focussed on and argued to be important determinants of subsequent organizational and ideological changes. Technocracy is compared with the millennium movements, and the relationship between participants1 conception of their role in terms of effecting change, and their time orientation on the relative imminence of the millennium, is examined. In this regard it is argued that a belief in an imminent millennium tends to militate against active efforts on the part of members to "make the revolution1'. It is argued that Technocracy can only be considered a social movement for approximately half of its history, and the question: When does a movement cease to be a movement? , is dealt with. Technocracy is described as a small-scale revolutionary movement in a pre- dominantly non-revolutionary social setting. The problems and paradoxes confronting such a movement, and the various ideological and tactical alternatives open to it are examined in some detail. The meaning to its members of the organization in its later stages is analyzed, and it is argued that a number of the psychic attitudes of partici- pants, normally considered to be explanations of such persons1 propensity for initial recruitment into a movement may, in fact, be a consequence of participation rather than a cause of it. Finally, the reasons for the relative lack of internal change and conflict in the movement since 1948 are examined briefly. n iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page .............................................................. Abstract iii .................. Chapter One .T echnocracy: The Questions To Be Asked 1 .......................................................... Notes 8 Chapter Two .T he Historical Setting: The Great Depression And Its ..................................................... Movements 9 .......................................................... Notes 12 ....... Chapter Three .T he Technical Alliance: Forerunner of Technocracy 13 ........................................... Technocratic Thought 14 .......................................................... Notes 22 Chapter Four .T he Emergence Of Technocracy And The Early Public ...................................................... Response 24 ........................................... The Historical Record 24 .................................. The Emergence Of Technocracy 25 .......................................................... Notes 31 ............... Chapter Five .T echnocracy 1932.1933. Craze Or Movement 32 ...... Ambiguity And Inevitability .T he Emergence Of Millenni a1i' sm 34 .......................................................... Notes 40 Chapter Six .T echnocracy 1933-1935: The Development Of An Organized ...................................................... Movement 42 ................................ The Development Of Two Factions 42 .......................................................... < Notes 57 .. ........ Chapter Seven .T echnocracy Inc 1934 To The Second World War 60 .......................................................... Notes 81 ...................................... Chapter Eight .T otal Conscription 84 .......................................................... Notes 92 ................................ Chapter Nine .V .an couver After The War 94 .......................................................... Notes 107 ......................................... Chapter Ten .T he Split Of 1948 109 ............................................ Contributing Factors 109 .......................................................... Notes 118 ... Chapter Eleven .1 950 To 1968 .C hanging Themes And Declining Activity 120 ...................................................... Notes 124 iv Page ....................... Chapter Twelve .T echnocracy Today In Vancouver 125 ..................................... The Current Events Classes 131 .......................................................... Notes 140 Chapter Thirteen .S ome Theoretical Considerations Involved In The .......................... Problem Of "Being A Technocrat Today" 142 ................. Nature Of Commitments Demanded Of Participants 148 ....... Nature Of Control And Compliance Applicable To Participants 150 ............... Nature Of Definitions Of Participants And 'Outsiders' 151 .......................................................... Notes 154 Chapter Fourteen .T he Educated Technocrat And The Future Of The ...................................................... Movement 156 .......................................................... Notes 162 ............................. Chapter Fifteen .S ummary And Conclusions 163 ......................................... A Question Of Definition 165 .......................................................... Notes 177 ...................................................... I Books 178 ............... I1 Pamphlets. Periodicals. And Fugitive Literature 179 ........................................ III Unpublished Material 182 ............................. Appendix 1 .M ethodological Appendix 183 ................................................ Notes 189 . ................... Appendix 2 .T echnocracy Inc Suggestion Form 190 \ LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS . Graphs . .... Fig 4:l Articles On Technocracy. New York Times 1932-1933 27 . ........... Fig 4:2 Periodical Article On Technocracy 1932.1933. 27 Maps . ................... Fig . 7:l Howard Scott's 1937 Continental Tour . .............. 72 Fig 9:l Technocracy Sections In Canada And U S.A 95 . ............................ Fig 9:2 Milligan Tour - March 1946 96 . ............................. Fig 9:3 Fearman Tour .M ay 1946 97 . ............................... Fig . 9:4 Gerald Tour .M ay 1946 ............................. 98 Fig . 9:5 McCaslin Tour .M ay 1946 ......................... 98 Fig 9:6 Frazeur Tour .F ebruary 1947 99 . ........................... Fig 9:7 Porter Tour .F ebruary 1947 100 . ............................ Fig . 9:8 Milligan Tour .M arch 1947 ....................... 100 Fig. 9:9 Porter Tour .M arch-April. .1.9.4.7. ....................... 101 Fig . 9:10 Wildfong Tour .M ay 1947 ........................... 102 Fig 9: 11 Templeton Tour .J une 1947 102 CHAPTER ONE TECHNOCRACY: THE QUESTIONS TO BE ASKED The Technocracy movement in the U. S. A. and Canada has existed in one form or another for approximately thirty-seven years. The intellectual origins can be traced back considerably further (see Chapter Three), while a group called the Tech- nical Alliance, which was organized in the 1918-1920 period, was clearly a forerunner of Technocracy as it developed the ideology that became the early basis of Technocracy and included several of the principal figures who launched the Technocracy movement in 1932-1933. During this period of otherwise impressive longevity, the movement has had no discernable social-political effects on the wider society, and while its ability to survive is interesting, it is neither Technocracy's long life nor its 'works1 that justify our study of the movement. Neither is the movement a particularly good example or refutation of a specific model or conception of movements. Nor is it an ideal case of a particular cell in some typology of movements. In fact it is the very opposite of this latter case that initially makes Technocracy of potential interest. There are two aspects of this interesting difficulty. In the first place it is not at all simple, regard- less of the definition chosen, to decide just when Technocracy was, or was not, a social movement, and in the second place it is even more difficult to decide what KIND of movement Technocracy was. Various typologies are constructed for different uses and employ, therefore, differing criteria, and may focus on a wide variance of sub- jects even within the same general field of interest. Hence it is in itself neither strange nor contradictory that Technocracy can be described by a wide range of dif- ferent labels. Hence the movement can, without any contradiction, be referred to as: Millennial, Utopian, Messianic, Authoritarian, Scientistic, Revolutionary, and Reformist. The utility of these designations starts to become questionable, however, when upon detailed examination of the history and development of the movement it becomes apparent that not only are they less accurate at some periods than at others, I but in addition they are sometimes inappropriate or misleading when applied to par- ticular segments of the larger movement. For example, it is quite clear that the goals of that branch of the movement that still survives (Technocracy Inc. ) have been rather consistently revolutionary in that they have advocated fundamental re-struc- turing of capitalist society, while on the other hand several of the other Technocracy groups have tended more toward a piecemeal reform approach. Another commonly used typological distinction focusses on the means through which a movement seeks to attain its ends. Here too we find different segments of the Technocracy movement holding to radically different formulations. It is also apparent that within these divergent (and often competing) groups there occurs considerable fluctuation over a period of time, over these matters of tactics. Unless Technocracy is to be regarded as unique, or atypical of social move- ments, which seems unlikely, the above observations raise questions both about the general utility of such typological distinctions and about their more specific value with regard to the Technocracy movement. There are two related possibilities that I see as relevant. In the first place it may be that the kinds of distinctions such labels allow are too general. That is, too many attributes are subsumed under the same category, with the result that some potentially interesting disc\ epan cies or divergencies are lost. For example, we might observe that movement X is a revolutionary movement and proceed to analyze it as such, failing to note that there have been within the movement recurrent tendencies toward reformism. In consequence, no analysis would emerge on the subject of factors producing such trends in the movement. The second matter, which is related to the first, is that such typological dis- tinctions, in part because of excessive generality, may tend to produce a static analysis of the movement. If, for instance, we are describing an existing or now de- funct movement and we conclude that this is, or was, X kind of movement, it is quite possible that we will fail to go further and examine contradictory attributes at various points in time. Normally our categorization is not so absolute as this, and what is said, or at least implied, is that this is (or was), by and large, X kind of movement. Tendencies and tensions toward change, and contradictory characteristics within the movement, are thus regarded as of minor importance so long as the main body of the movement is not fundamentally altered. A second way in which a static bias is produced is that either implicitly or explicitly the movement is categorized, not (as above) by an overall or summary historical evaluation, but at one particular point in time. A sort of conceptual 'snapshot1 is produced of the movement. Change is thereby ignored. Without going into an elaborate discussion of static versus dynamic models, it is clear that static concepts are of dubious value in analysis of what is BECOMING as opposed to what IS. We anticipate that the more static a concept is the less value it will have in helping us to understand the dynamics of movements. It should be clear that the sort of difficulties we are considering with regard to these general typological distinctions are variously significant, depending upon the type of movement under consideration. They would be relatively insignificant, for instance, in movements that are short lived and consistent in terms of ideology, or- ganization, and tactics, in which there is a high degree of consensus among partici- pants about what the movement is and should be, and how it should pursue its goals, and in which this consistency is maintained throughout the life span of the movement. This is not to suggest that there will be no conflict or debate at any point, but only that it never comes to the point where it generates internal factions or l'wingsl'. Such internal consistency may not necessarily require a short life span, but is most likely to be found in short-lived movements. It seems likely, also, that most such move- ments will be those usually designated reform movements. The 'ideal1 case is the small- scale reform movement that originates in response to a specific issue, propagandizes, recruits participants, exerts some sort of pressure on the relevant other group or individual, and then, upon attaining its ends within a relatively short time (to its own satisfaction at least), disbands or perhaps changes its function and becomes some- - thing other than a movement say perhaps a voluntary association. The 'ideal' opposite case to this, and the one where the typological problems raised are most severe, is the movement (like Technocracy) that exists over an extended period of time, experiences extensive and differing pressures, both internal and external, generates changes in ideology, organizational form, and recruitment tactics, and goes through splits or schisms that may result in the emergence of opposing "wings". These "wings" or factions may separate from the original move- ment and form new movements, or may remain within the movement and force changes in various aspects of the larger movement. There are several other possible effects of such conflicts and probably empirical examples of each logical possibility. The most fundamental change, of course, occurs when such a conflict shifts a movement, from one cell in a typology to one diametrically opposed. Say, for instance, where a movement that was revolutionary becomes a reform movement. To label these long-lived, heterogeneous, changing movements by one general label may be excessively simplistic and have the result of obscuring potentially signi- ficant internal tensions and changes, or more simply, movementsf processes. U These comments are intended only to set a general framework from which to to develop the more specific questions that are the prime focus of this study of Technocracy. It is not my intention, therefore, to develop the, as yet, analytically 'rough' distinctions between these 'ideal' cases into a full blown typology. It is enough to draw a distinction between the simpler, more homogeneous sort of move- ment and the more complex, heterogeneous type of which Technocracy is an example. Given these general observations it is now possible to deal with the more detailed and specific questions relevant to this study. It is implicit in the above that our questions center around matters of internal movement change and process. In examining these it is necessary to analyze in some greater detail the already noted difficulties of typological distinction. Throughout the study of this movement, the parallels that I considered most I II striking and persistent were between Technocracy and those movements usually des- cribed as millennial. To be more precise, some segments of the movement, at some points in time, displayed a number of attributes similar to those of the millen- nial type of movement. For instance, both are revolutionary in the sense that parti- cipants anticipate a fundamental restructuring of basic societal institutions. In addition, both regard "time as a linear process which leads to a final future";' in other words, 'la decisive consummation of all history".2 Technocracy developed an . ideology that has been described by Henry Elsner Jr., who is perhaps the best informed student of the movement, as a form of ~cientism.~Th e parallels between millennial beliefs and Scientism are pointed out most clearly by Jarvie in The Revolution in Anthropology. 4 A messianic form of leadership is an additional parallel between most millennial hlovements and Technocracy. 6 Other similarities could be noted, but two are of immediate significance. The first involves participants' expectations regarding the relative immediacy of the coming millennium, while the second involves the more far-reaching matter of the role of the group in bringing about the millennium. On the former, Talmon says, "Radical millenarian movements regard the millennium as imminent and live in tense expectation and preparation for it. The 11' inclusion of the phrase 'land preparation for it" in an observation on time orientations is most appropriate as the two matters are closely intertwined. It seems likely, for instance, that the kinds of preparation regarded as suitable will depend at least in part upon the group's conception of the relative imminence of the coming millennium. This is one of the specific questions that we will examine in the case of Technocracy. A related problem, also relevant to Technocracy, is the group's response to changes, alterations, and outright failures of the prophecy of a coming millennium. The more specific the prophecy is, of course, the more open it is to being perceived as failing. Technocracy is interesting in this regard in that at one point in its history it had a very clear and specific prophecy, which was in no conceivable sense realized.' The second parallel with millennial movements that is particularly relevant concerns changing definitions of the appropriate role of the movement in bringing about the anticipated changes. On this subject Talmon says, "All millenarian move- ments share a fundamental vagueness about the actual way in which the new order will " be brought about. And further, on the role of participants, "The followers of these
Description: