THE SYNTAX OF TIME ANCIENT MEDITERRANEAN AND MEDIEVAL TEXTS AND CONTEXTS editors ROBERT M. BERCHMAN JACOB NEUSNER STUDIES IN PLATONISM, NEOPLATONISM, AND THE PLATONIC TRADITION edited by ROBERT M. BERCHMAN (Dowling College and Bard College) AND JOHN F. FINAMORE (University of Iowa) EDITORIAL BOARD Donald Blakeley (UCalifornia, Fresno), Jay Bregman (University of Maine) Luc Brisson (CNRS-Paris), Kevin Corrigan (Emory University) John Dillon (Trinity College, Dublin), Stephen Gersh (University of Notre Dame), Lloyd Gerson (University of Toronto), Gary Gurtler (Loyola of Chicago), Jeremiah Hackett (University of South Carolina), Ruth Majercik (UCalifornia, Santa Barbara) Peter Manchester (SUNY Stony Brook), Jean-Marc Narbonne (Laval University-Canada) Sara Pessin (University of Denver), Sara Rappe (University of Michigan) Frederic Schroeder (Queens University-Canada), Gregory Shaw (Stonehill College) Suzanne Stern-Gillet (Bolton Institute-UK), Yiota Vassilopoulou (University of Liverpool) Michael Wagner (University of San Diego) VOLUME 2 THE SYNTAX OF TIME The Phenomenology of Time in Greek Physics and Speculative Logic from Iamblichus to Anaximander BY PETER MANCHESTER BRILL LEIDEN•BOSTON 2005 This book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Manchester, Peter, 1942- The Syntax of time / by Peter Manchester. p. cm. — (Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic tradition ; v. 2) Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 90-04-14712-8 (alk. paper) 1. Time. 2. Time—History. 3. Philosophy, Ancient. I. Title. II. Series. BD638.M343 2005 115—dc22 2005050179 ISSN 1871-188X ISBN 90 04 14712 8 © Copyright 2005 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill Academic Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910 Danvers MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. printed in the netherlands CONTENTS Preface and Acknowledgments ................................................ vii Chapter One Two-Dimensional Time in Husserl and Iamblichus .................................................................................. 1 The Problem of the Flowing of Time .................................. 1 The Flux of Consciousness .................................................... 5 The Transparency of the Flux .............................................. 9 Time-Framing in Locke and Hume .................................... 11 The Dimensions of Transparency ........................................ 15 Two-Dimensional Time in Husserl ...................................... 19 The Figure of Double Continuity ........................................ 22 The Double Intentionality of Disclosure Space .................. 38 Two-Dimensional Time in Iamblichus ................................ 43 Time as the Sphere of the All .............................................. 49 Chapter Two Time and the Soul in Plotinus ...................... 55 Two-Dimensional Time in Neoplatonism ............................ 55 The Schema of Participation ................................................ 60 The Silence of Time in Plotinus .......................................... 72 Chapter Three Everywhere Now: Physical Time in Aristotle ........................................................................................ 87 Soul and the Surface of Exoteric Time .............................. 87 The Spanning of Motion ...................................................... 91 The Scaling of Spans ............................................................ 96 The Unit of Disclosure Space .............................................. 101 The Soul of Physical Time .................................................. 104 Chapter Four Parmenides: Time as the Now ...................... 106 Parmenides Thinks about Time ............................................ 106 Signpost 1: Being Ungenerated and Unperishing .............. 109 Signpost 2: Whole; Signpost 4: The Coherent One .......... 118 Signpost 3: Now is All at Once and Entirely Total .......... 126 Conclusion .............................................................................. 134 vi contents Chapter Five Heraclitus and the Need for Time .................. 136 Review: The Path to Heraclitus .......................................... 136 From Husserl to Heraclitus via Iamblichus ........................ 137 Time in Heraclitus: The Circular Joining of ée‹ and afi≈n 141 Heraclitus as a Gloss on Anaximander ................................ 150 Appendix 1 Physical Lectures on Time by Aristotle: A Minimal Translation .............................................................................. 153 Appendix 2 Fragment 8 of the Poem of Parmenides: Text and Translation ............................................................ 170 Bibliography ................................................................................ 175 Index ............................................................................................ 179 PREFACE AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I have left these chapters marked by the time it has taken me to begin, execute, and declare an end to this project. The first three are essentially the same as those presented in 1984. They are frozen in time with respect to bibliography, but have been a basis, from then until now, for my instruction in the doctoral program in phi- losophy here at Stony Brook, where the positions taken still seem to be holding up. The three, the chapters on Husserl, Plotinus, and Aristotle, have always accompanied a fourth on Parmenides. Until this year, that meant a reprise to the article I wrote in 1977–78 for the January, 1979 Parmenides issue of The Monist, “Parmenides and the Need for Eternity,” which was formally the first composition for the project “the syntax of time.” The Husserl, Plotinus, and Aristotle chapters were written over the subsequent five years to explain and defend unconventional ways I had characterized their positions in notes for that paper, giving the set of four a certain unity and finish. There was always supposed to be a fifth chapter on Heraclitus, by way of pointing toward Anaximander and my translation of his famous phrase, “according to the syntax of time.” This was not forthcom- ing, however, until Thanksgiving 1999. By the millennium it seemed the manuscript was complete—that is until January of this year, when I discovered that the entire expos- itory strategy of the 1979 Parmenides paper was based on an error. This meant it could no longer be reprinted. I needed to write my way out the same door I had come in through twenty-five years ear- lier. The Parmenides chapter is now entirely new. Through these years, I have had the sustaining interest and enthu- siasm of graduate students at Stony Brook. In spring of this year, in PHI 600 (Ancient Philosophy), our topic was “Heraclitus, Parme- nides, Empedocles, and the Vocation of Philosophy,” with Peter Kingsley as guest for a month. As in other PHI 600 seminars on Plato and Platonism and on Aristotle over the years, the level of work has been very high. I want in particular to acknowledge the Greek Cabal that formed around a previous seminar on the Presocratics in fall 1997, and then refused to die the following spring. This has evolved into an ongoing extracurricular Greek group, who, among viii preface and acknowledgments other things, have helped me review the translations of Aristotle and Parmenides presented in the appendices for elementary errors. (Any remaining errors are all substantive, and all mine.) Too many to name, it is the many doctoral students in philosophy I have met at Stony Brook from 1986 to the present that I want first to acknowl- edge, for their stimulation, collegiality, and probing attention. For the opportunity to work at Stony Brook, I thank Thomas J. J. Altizer and Robert C. Neville, and for the invitation to partici- pate in the graduate program in philosophy, Edward S. Casey. They are all very good at making books, and, together with their encour- agement, their example should have helped me get this one made more quickly. The welcome I have felt in the study of ancient Greek philoso- phy was extended to me first by the late Arthur Hilary Armstrong, F.B.A., M.A. in Classics (Cambridge), Gladstone Professor of Greek in the University of Liverpool, Visiting Professor of Classics at Dalhousie University, Halifax, whom I met there in the fall semester of 1975 as a post-doctoral fellow in classics, with support from the Killam Foundation of Canada, for which I would like to express my continuing gratitude. I had written a dissertation comparing Heidegger and Augustine on temporality (The Doctrine of the Trinity in Temporal Interpretation, Graduate Theological Union, 1972), and had decided to abandon the Heidegger discussion and look into the Greek back- ground of Augustine, specifically Plotinus. I wrote to Armstrong saying I needed an “antidote to Heidegger,” and he was delighted to assist. It was my privilege to grow into friendship and collaboration with Hilary Armstrong, starting with that semester in classics at Dalhousie in which I read Ennead III, 7 On Eternity and Time with him. Initially he resisted my Husserl-motivated interpretation, but finally warmed to it. At the time he was struggling to complete the translation of the Sixth Ennead for the Loeb, and we had much conversation about philosophical Greek. I owe to him whatever judgment I am able to exercise about how to balance philosophical and philological consid- erations when they come into conflict in the reading of ancient texts. I also learned a great deal from him about directness and clarity of voice,thoughthese are lessons I have found harder to put into practice. To all who have cared to see this work complete, my thanks. Peter Manchester Stony Brook University Thanksgiving, 2004 CHAPTER ONE TWO-DIMENSIONAL TIME IN HUSSERL AND IAMBLICHUS The Problem of the Flowing of Time Beginning with Aristotle, philosophers have regularly attempted to correct familiar ways of speaking that construe time itself as a motion— a passing, for example, or more canonically, a flowing. They have just as regularly failed. Because it is sustained by the ancient com- parison to a river, the notion that time flows is past rooting out. And yet it remains a difficult, even a doubtful observation. Time cannot itself be a motion, Aristotle explains, since motions are faster and slower, and faster and slower are discriminated with respect to time. Time is not motion, he concludes, but at best “some- thing about motion.”1 Plotinus rejects even an indirect connection to physical motion. To make time a feature of motion or something defined in relation to it (e.g. the measure of motion) turns time into a redundant accom- paniment, a motion running alongside of every motion.2 Still, a Platonist like Plotinus must confront the systematically deci- sive text in Timaeus according to which time is a “moving image of eternity.”3 But Iamblichus, the fourth century Neoplatonist for whose interpretation of Plotinus we are preparing in this chapter, stipulates that the “moving” of time is neither like, nor among, sensible motions, since it is motion with respect to eternity alone.4 Contemporary writing has belabored the point beyond tidy attri- bution. A recurring objection goes like this: If in some way it makes sense to say that time flows, then it ought to be possible to say which way it flows. Does it flow from the past, welling up into the present and spilling out into the future? Or from the future, looming nearer 1 Physics IV, 10: 218b10–11, 219a10. 2 Enneads III 7 (45), 7–10. 3 Plato, Timaeus 37D. 4 Commentary on Timaeus, Fragment 64 (Dillon). Iamblichi Chalcidensis in Platonis Dialogos Commentariorum Fragmenta, Ed. John M. Dillon (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1973).
Description: