ebook img

The Step to Rationality PDF

33 Pages·2008·5.3 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Step to Rationality

CognitiveScience32(2008)3–35 (cid:1) Copyright C 2008CognitiveScienceSociety,Inc.Allrightsreserved. ISSN:0364-0213print/1551-6709online DOI:10.1080/03640210701801917 The Step to Rationality: The Efficacy of Thought Experiments in Science, Ethics, and Free Will Roger N. Shepard DepartmentofPsychology,StanfordUniversity,andTheArizonaSeniorAcademy Abstract ExamplesfromArchimedes,Galileo,Newton,Einstein,andotherssuggestthatfundamentallawsof physicswere—or,atleast,couldhavebeen—discoveredbyexperimentsperformednotinthephysical worldbutonlyinthemind.Althoughproblematicforastrictempiricist,theevolutionaryemergence in humans of deeply internalized implicit knowledge of abstract principles of transformation and symmetry may have been crucial for humankind’s step to rationality—including the discovery of universalprinciplesofmathematics,physics,ethics,andanaccountoffreewillthatiscompatiblewith determinism. Keywords:Thoughtexperiments;Physicallaws;Imaginedtransformations;Mentalrotation;Symmetry; Rationality;Morallaws;TheGoldenRule;Determinism;Agency;Freewill 1. Theproblem Thoughtexperimentsarewidelyreportedtohaveplayedaprominentroleinthediscoveries of physical laws. I begin by describing some specific thought experiments, similar to those that were—or, at least, may have been—carried out by Archimedes, Galileo, Newton, and Einstein and that appear to be sufficient to establish fundamental laws of physics, without carrying out any of these experiments physically. How is this possible? Where does such knowledge originate if not, as supposed by strict empiricists, from each individual’s own directinteractionswiththephysicalworld? TheanswerIproposegrewoutofmyevolutionaryperspectivetogetherwithmycognitive psychological researches on mental transformations (Shepard & Cooper, 1982; Shepard & Metzler, 1971) and on generalization (Shepard, 1987; also see the related far-reaching de- velopmentssubsequentlyachievedbyTenenbaumandothers—e.g.,Chater&Vitanyi,2003; Feldman,2000;Tenenbaum&Griffiths,2001a,2001b).Here,however,Ifocusprimarilyon CorrespondenceshouldbeaddressedtoRogerN.Shepard,13805E.LangtryLane,Tucson,AZ85747.E-mail: [email protected] 4 R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) theroleofmentaltransformationsandanassociatedsymmetryprincipleofinvarianceunder transformation. Ithenventuretosuggesthowthesameapproachmaybeextendable,beyondthediscovery ofscientificlaws,toshedlightonthediscoveryofuniversalmoralprinciplesandtoaffordan account of free will that is compatible with determinism. I shall argue that the emergence in humans of the cognitive capabilities of discovering universal laws of science and principles ofethics,andofexercisingfreewillaremanifestationofaterrestriallyunprecedented(ifonly partially achieved) “step to rationality.” A crucial component of all three of these cognitive capabilities is the ability to disengage from immediate self-interest and to imagine and to evaluate alternative events or actions with respect to explicitly represented criteria. I invite thoseengagedincognitivemodelingtothinkabouthowthekindsofabstractrepresentational processes and symmetry principles I invoke here might be explicitly implemented in more concrete,detailedandevenneuro-physiologicallyplausibleways. 2. Empiricalscienceandmathematics Traditionally, a sharp distinction is maintained between the empirical sciences, on one hand,andmathematicsandlogic,ontheother.Observations,measurements,andexperiments onphysicalobjectsandphenomenaaregenerallyconsideredtobeessentialfortheadvance- ment of the empirical sciences. In contrast, mathematics is supposed to be concerned with what propositions are logically entailed by other propositions, regardless of whether these propositionscorrespondtoanythinginthephysicalworld. Also,inphysicswhataretakentobetheelementaryorprimitiveobjectsarealwaysprovi- sionalandsubjecttolaterreconceptualization—usuallyintermsofstillmoreelementalenti- ties.Thus,water,directlyexperiencedasacontinuousfluid,maybesuccessivelyreconceived ascomposedofmorefundamentalentities:discretemolecules,thenatoms,thenelectronsand protons,thenquarks,andthenperhapsmodesofvibrationinaconvolutedhigh-dimensional manifold—withnodefiniteendinsight. However, in mathematics the elementary or primitive objects are specified by the mathe- matician rather than by nature. Such objects as the integers of arithmetic or number theory or the points and lines of geometry are themselves completely transparent from the outset. Ordinarily,wedonotsupposethatapointoralineorthatanintegersuchas1,2,or3(setting asideFrege’sandRussell’sabstract,set-theoryofnaturalnumbers)willbefoundtobecom- posedofsomepreviouslyunsuspectedmoreelementalcomponents.Instead,theadvancesyet to be made in number theory or in geometry are expected to concern what relations among suchelementarynumbersorpointsandlineswillbefoundtobeentailedbywhateveraxioms wehaveformulatedfornumbertheoryorgeometry. Nevertheless, mathematics and physics are alike in that we aspire, in both cases, to a consistent theoretical system of basic assumptions and derivable implications. But whereas in physics such a system is valued to the extent that it provides the simplest explanation or prediction of the widest range of what we observe or measure in the physical world, in pure mathematicsthesystemmaybevaluedforitsownsimplicity,elegance,symmetry,orbeauty— independently of the extent to which it corresponds to what we observe or measure in the R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) 5 physicalworld.Nevertheless,resultsofpuremathematicsthatwereoriginallyvaluedfortheir intrinsic beauty are often later found to be most useful or even crucial for the development of physical theory. Notable examples include the non-Euclidean geometries of Minkowski andofRiemannforspecialandgeneralrelativity;thecomplexnumbers,matrixalgebra,and infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces for quantum theory; and the theory of groups for both relativityandquantummechanics. Moreover,theexplicitformalizationsofthelawsofphysicsandofmathematicsare,alike, creationsofthehumanmind.Absentacomprehendingmind,suchequationswouldnotexist and, even if by chance they did, they would exist only as meaningless configurations of physical matter. How do we humans come to formulate, to comprehend, and to evaluate the formalizations ofmathematical andphysicallaws? Whenwe try todothis forourselves,we mayfindthatthecognitiveprocessesinthecasesofphysicsandmathematicsareoftenmore similarthanthetraditionaldistinctionbetweenmathematicalandtheempiricalscienceswould suggest. To illustrate, I now present simple examples, first, from mathematics (specifically, geometry)and,then,fromphysics(primarily,mechanics). 3. Pythagoras’stheoremforrighttriangles ThePythagoreantheoremrelatesthelengthofthehypotenuse(c)ofarighttriangletothe lengthsofitstwoothersides(a&b)bytheequation(a2 +b2 =c2).Itissurelyatheoremof mathematics. It may not hold exactly in the physical world. Long before Einstein, it clearly didnotholdforlargetrianglesonthesphericalsurfaceoftheearth.(Theequilateralspherical triangle formed by traveling due south from the North Pole to the equator then due east one quarter of the way around the equator and then due north back to the North Pole is in clear violationthePythagoreantheorem.Eachpairofthethreeequallegsofthis“triangular”journey formsarightangle.)Now,accordingtoEinstein’sgeneraltheoryofrelativity,thePythagorean theoremdoesnotexactlyholdmoregenerallyfortrianglesinthree-dimensionalphysicalspace, moreorlesscurvedasthatspaceisinthevicinityofmassivebodies.Nevertheless,according to pure geometry, it does precisely hold for triangles in a flat plane. How can we convince ourselvesofthislatter,mathematicalfact? There have been numerous intuitive demonstrations of the validity of the Pythagorean theorem. Fig. 1 illustrates one attributed to Pythagoras himself. A right triangle (with its 2 sidesofarbitrarylengthsaandbandhypotenuseofcorrespondinglengthc,asshowninA)is imaginedtobereplicatedthreetimes,yieldingtheidenticalcopies(labeled“1,”“2,”and“3”) eachrigidlyrotatedand/orflippedtofitwithinasquarewithsidesoflengtha+b(asshownin B).Onecanimmediatelyseethatthetwoemptyportionsofthatsquare(displayedasshaded inC)arebothsquareandthatonenecessarilyhasareaa2andtheothernecessarilyhasareab2. Now the four identical triangles are imagined to be rigidly translated and rotated within the samesquaretofitintothefourcornersofthesquareasillustratedinD.Withthisrearrangement of the four identical triangles within the same square, the remaining, empty portion of the square(againshaded,asshowninD)isimmediatelyseentobeatippedquadrilateralwhose sides are each of length c (the length of the hypotenuse of the original triangle). Because ◦ the whole configuration (in D) is obviously invariant under 90 rotations, all angles of the 6 R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) Fig.1. AproofofthePythagoreantheorem. tipped quadrilateral must be identical and, hence, this quadrilateral is a square. Because its sides are of length c, the area of this square is c2. Whatever area within the original larger squarecontainingthefourtrianglesisnotoccupiedbythosetrianglesmustbeinvariantunder non-overlapping rearrangements of those triangles within that larger square. Hence the sum oftheareasofthetwosquareshadedareasinC(i.e.,a2+b2)mustequaltheareaofthesingle shadedlargerrotatedsquareinD(i.e.,c2),Q.E.D. Fig. 2 illustrates another, quite different and in some ways simpler demonstration. (First broughttomyattentionbyDouglasHofstadter,personalcommunication.)Asindicatedinthe figure,thePythagoreantheorem(a2 +b2 =c2)isequivalenttothestatementthatthesumof theareasofthesquaresconstructedonthetwoshortersidesofthetriangleequalstheareaof thelarger,tiltedsquareconstructedonthehypotenuse. Again, the truth of the theorem can be confirmed by imagining a few simple operations. First,imagineastraightlineconstructedorthogonaltothehypotenuseandpassingthroughthe oppositevertex(asindicatedinthefigurebythedottedsegmentthatthusdividestheoriginal triangle into the two areas labeled “A” and “B”). Second, imagine each constructed square (of area a2, b2, or c2) and its adjacent triangle (of area A, B, or A + B) rigidly rotated (and also flipped in the case of the largest square-plus-triangle) as a rigid unit to yield the three house-shapedobjectslinedupacrossthebottomofthefigure.Third,fromaconsiderationof thecomplementaryanglesoftheoriginaltriangle,confirmthatthethreetrianglesatthetops ofthethreesquares(linedupbelowthat),ofareasA,B,andA+B,arenecessarilyidentical in shape. Finally, from this identity of shape, reach the conclusion for the proportional areas ofthesquaresthata2 +b2 =c2 (QED). I suggest that the operations imagined in these two proofs of the Pythagorean theorem are of essentially the kind that my students and I investigated in our studies of imagined R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) 7 Fig.2. AnalternativeproofofthePythagoreantheorem. transformations,including“mentalrotation”andapparentmotion(Shepard&Cooper,1982; Shepard&Metzler,1971).Alsocrucial,here,istherealizationthatshapeandsizeareinvari- ant under these rigid transformations of translation, rotation, and horizontal flipping (which is just a rotation in depth). I have suggested, too, that the visual salience of symmetries arisesfromtheimplicitrecognitionthatanobjectisinvariantunderthesetransformationsof reflection, translation, rotation, or, more generally, screw displacement in three-dimensional space (as in the 4 illustrative examples displayed in Fig. 3). Such invariance under trans- formation also applies to the case of the mere exchange or permutation of identical objects, whichwillfigureprominentlyinsomeoftheensuingexamples(bothfromphysicsandfrom meta-ethics). 4. Archimedes’slawofthelever UnlikethetheoremofPythagoras,whichbelongstopuremathematics,Archimedeslawof the lever appears to be a law of physics. It can be stated as follows: Physical objects placed alongabeamrestingonacentralfulcrumwillbalanceifandonlyifthesumoftheproducts of the weights and their distances from the fulcrum is equal for the objects on the left and fortheobjectsontherightofthefulcrum.Archimedesmayhaveverifiedthislawbyplacing actual physical objects on actual physical balance beams. But he need not have done so. He mayverywellhaveseenthatthislawmustholdbythoughtexperimentsandtheprincipleof symmetry,asIillustrateinAthroughEofFig.4. 8 R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) Fig.3. Symmetryasinvarianceundertransformation. IfhehadimaginedthesituationshowninA,Archimedeswouldimmediatelyhaveseenby symmetrythatthefouridenticalweightsmustbalance.Becausetheweightsareidentical,any permutation of them must leave the situation unchanged, with no reason for one side or the othertotiltdown.Nowimaginethatwithoutalteringtheweightofanypartofthebeamitself, itismodifiedtohaveasecondaryfulcrumasshowninB.Ifthefouridenticalweightsarenow placed as illustrated in C, everything will still balance as it did in A. Moreover, this remains trueforanyplacementofthetwoweightsonthesecondaryBeam2thatissymmetricalaround that secondary fulcrum. For any such symmetrical placement, the combined weight of those twoobjectsiscommunicatedtotheprimarybeam,asbefore,atthelocationofthatsecondary fulcrum. Each of the cases exhibited (C, D, & E) thus satisfies Archimedes’s condition. As shown by the equation over each case, the negative sum of the products on the left of the fulcrumcancelsthepositivesumoftheproductsontheright. More generally, beginning with any distribution of any number of weights along a beam, we can use the same symmetry principle to confirm the following: First, we note (from the preceding)thatwhetherArchimedes’sconditionholdsornot(i.e.,whetherthebeambalances ornot),thefactofitsbalanceorimbalanceispreservedunderanytransformationofmoving anytwoweightstogetheratthemidpointbetweenthem.Second,asillustratedforaparticular, arbitrarydistributionofidenticalweightsinFig.5,iterationofsuchtransformationsconverges R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) 9 Fig.4. ThoughtexperimentleadingtoArchimedes’slawofthelever. towardthesituationinwhichalltheweightsarelocatedatArchimedes’scentroidoftheoriginal distribution. At every stage of this process, the centroid will be at the fulcrum if and only if Archimedes’s condition holds and, hence, the beam balances—as it surely will if at the end alltheweightsarestackeddirectlyoverthefulcrum(asatthebottomofthefigure). Thus, are we able to verify Archimedes law, without ever placing any actual weights on any actual beam. What appeared to be an empirical fact about the physical world turns out tobeentailedbyanabstract,mathematicalprincipleofinvarianceundertransformation—or, equivalently, of symmetry. We are able to verify the truth of this law of physics by thought 10 R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) Fig.5. ConfirmationofArchimedes’slawforanarbitrarydistributionofweights. alone,muchaswedidinthecaseofPythagoras’smathematicallawconcerningrighttriangles. Inbothcasesthelawsareuniversalundertheconditionsspecified.ThelawofPythagorasis universal,aswesaw,onlyforrighttrianglesinaflatplane.Likewise,thelawofArchimedes is universal only for weights distributed on a beam that is rigid and balanced on the fulcrum priortotheweightsbeingplaceduponit. R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) 11 After choosing the mathematical example of Pythagoras and the physical example of Archimedes, I noticed a striking connection between them: Imagine that you wish to verify that three long physical rods of the same uniform diameter and rigid material would form a righttriangle.But(a)thelongnarrowroominwhichyoumustdothisisnotwideenoughto accommodate the triangle itself and (b) no ruler or measuring tape is available. I leave it as anexerciseforthereadertouseArchimedes’slawtoverifythefollowingstatement:Ifalong (unmarked)beamandfulcrumareavailable,andthetwoshorterbarsarelaidside-by-sideon onesideofthebeamextendingfromthefulcrumandthelongestbarislaidontheotherside extending from the fulcrum (as illustrated in Fig. 6), then if a triangle were formed by the threebars,itwouldbearighttriangleifandonlyifthebarsonthebeamachieveabalance. 5. Galileo’slawoffallingbodies PerhapsthemostthoroughlyanalyzedthoughtexperimentofalltimeistheoneGalileoused torefutetheclaimattributedtoAristotlethatfallingbodiesdropwithspeedsproportionalto theirweights(seeGendler,1998).Presumably,Aristotledidnotreachanerroneousconclusion byperforminganactualexperiment.Ifhereacheditfromathoughtexperiment,itevidently was one to which he did not devote enough thought. Possibly by imagining the hefting of a lightobjectinonehandandaheavyobjectintheotherhandhewasledtothehastyconclusion that if the objects were released, the greater downward force he felt from the heavier object would manifest itself as a faster descent on the release of that object. But such a conclusion ignores inertia—something that Artistotle might have realized before Galileo if he had also thoughtaboutthegreaterforceneededtoaccelerateamoremassiveobjecttothesamespeed asalighterobject(e.g.,ifbothobjectswererestingontheslipperysurfaceofafrozenpond). Galileo’sthoughtexperimentwasconclusive.Ityieldedthecorrectconclusion:Thespeed of descent is independent of the weight of the object (to the extent that air resistance is negligible). This implies that the greater downward force that Aristotle imagined he would feelfromtheheavierobjectisinfactexactlytheforceneededtoacceleratethemoremassive object to the very same speed. I shall describe a thought experiment that is slightly different from the one actually offered by Galileo but that is, I believe, equally conclusive and more revealingoftherelevanceoftheprincipleofsymmetry. I imagine Galileo imagining himself at the top of the leaning tower at Pisa with three identical bricks. By the symmetry principle of invariance under permutation of identical objects, if the three bricks were dropped together, they should reach the ground at the same time. As in the case of Archimedes’s identical weights equally distant on each side of the Fig.6. AcorrespondencebetweenthelawsofArchimedesandPythagoras. 12 R.N.Shepard/CognitiveScience32(2008) fulcrum,thereisnoreasonforonetodescendmorethananother.Nowsupposetwoofthese three bricks are glued together to form a single, twice-as-heavy brick. Surely, the virtually weightlessfilmofglueusedtomakethetwobricksintoonewouldnotcausethatnowheavier bricktofalltwiceasrapidlyastheseparate,thirdbrick.Onceagain,thecorrectconclusionis reachedwithouthavingtoperformanactualexperiment. 6. Newton’slawofactionandreaction Newton’sinspirationforhisuniversallawofgravitationissometimesattributedtoathought experiment in which he imagined throwing an apple (according to legend, one that dropped on him from a tree under which he was sitting in an orchard). Newton would have realized that if he threw the apple with greater and greater force, the apple would fall to ground at a greater and greater distance from him. Knowing that the earth is a sphere, he would have concludedthatifhewereabletothrowtheapplewithsufficientforce,itwouldfallnottoearth butaroundtheearth.Hemightthenconjecturethatthemoonwashurlingwithsuchspeedas tobesimilarlyeverfallingaroundtheearth. I now consider, instead, a different thought experiment from which Newton might have arrived at his Third Law of Motion—the law that every action has an equal and opposite reaction.Ifocusonthislawfortworeasons:First,ofhisthreelawsofmotion,thisistheone thatwasmostoriginalwithNewton.Second,thisthoughtexperimentderivesinaparticularly simpleandtransparentwayfromtheprincipleofsymmetry. IimagineNewtonimagininghimselfarchedoverthewaterwithhisfeetonthegunwaleof hisboatandhishandsonthegunwaleofanotherboatofthesamesizethatheisendeavoringto pushawayfromhisboat.Fromtheobvioussymmetryofthesituation,Newtonwouldrealize thatthereisnowaythathecanpushtheotherboatawayfromhiswithoutequallypushinghis boatawayfromtheother.Hemightalsogoontorealizethatifhewerestrandedinthemiddle ofalakewithanoar-lessboatloaded,say,withapples,hecouldpropelhimselfbacktoward shorebyhurlingtheapples,onebyone,totherearwithgreatforce(justasspacevehiclesnow acceleratethroughemptyspacebyejectingmoleculesofthegaseousproductsofcombustion rearwardatextremelyhighvelocity). 7. Einstein’stheoryofrelativity Einstein,likeGalileo,wasamasterofthethoughtexperiment.Hearrivedatspecialrelativity throughthoughtexperimentsabouthowthe sameeventswouldbeexperiencedbyobservers indifferentstatesofmotion.Galileohadassertedthateventsonashipwouldappearthesame toshipboardobserverswhethertheshipwereatrestorunderfullsail.Ineithercase,hesaid, an iron ball dropped from the top of the mast would appearto drop straight down relative to the ship, and not (as some had supposed) further back on the deck if the ship were moving swiftlyforward. Einstein proposed that the same principle should continue to apply even if the velocity of thevesselweretoapproachthespeedoflight.Fig.7illustratesarelevantthoughtexperiment

Description:
Examples from Archimedes, Galileo, Newton, Einstein, and others suggest that .. Thought experiment leading to Archimedes's law of the lever. greed, hatred, or revenge) that may have contributed to the reproduction and
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.