ebook img

The Social Philosophy of Adam Smith PDF

178 Pages·1973·11.14 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Social Philosophy of Adam Smith

THE SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY OF ADAM SMITH ARCHIVES INTERNA T10NALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDEES INTERNATIONAL ARCHIVES OF THE HIS TOR Y OF IDEAS Series minor 8 J. RALPH LINDGREN THE SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY OF ADAM SMITH Directors: P. Dibon (Paris) and R. Popkin (Univ. of California, La Jolla) Editorial board: J. Aubin (Paris); J. Collins (St. Louis Univ.); P. Costabel (paris); A. Crombie (Oxford); I. Dambska (Cracow); H. de laFontaine-Verwey (Amsterdam); H. Gadamer (Heidelberg); H. Gouhier (paris); T. Gregory (Rome); T. E. Jessop (Hull); P. O. Kristeller (Columbia Univ.); Elisabeth Labrousse (paris); S. Lindroth (Upsala); A. Lossky (Los Angeles); J.Orcibal (Paris); I. S. Revaht (Paris); J. Roger (Paris); H. Rowen (Rutgers Univ., N.J.); G. Sebba (Emory Univ., Atlanta); R. Shackleton (Oxford); J. Tans (Groningen); G. Tonelli (Binghamton, N.Y.). THE SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY OF ADAM SMITH by J. RALPH LINDGREN • MARTINUS NIJHOFF ! THE HAGUE / 1973 @ 1973 by Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherkmds Softcover reprint oft he hardcover 1st edition 1973 All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-1533-6 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-2440-2 DOl: 10.10071978-94-010-2440-2 For Shirley, Thomas, Michael, David, Timothy and Kathryn TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface IX Chronology xv Table of Abbreviations XVI I. INQUIRY II. MORAL JUDGMENT 20 III. PSYCHOLOGY 39 IV. GOVERNMENT 60 V. COMMERCE 84 VI. COMMERCIAL POLICY 110 VII. RELIGION 133 Works Cited 153 Index 159 PREFACE Adam Smith was one of the most important seminal social philosophers at of modern times. Although his great masterpiece - the Wealth Nations - is most frequently associated with the field of economics, it has exer cised a profound and abiding influence not only in that but in all areas of social theory and practice as well. In view of this it is not a little puzzling that after nearly two centuries there does not exist a single reliable account of the full range of his social philosophy. The "circumstances which have contributed to this void in the literature are easily identified. All who are at all familiar with Smith's life and writings recognize that he was a philosopher by profession and that all his writings were conceived and executed as works of philosophy. During his lifetime his work was viewed iIi that perspective. At about the time of his death in 1790, however, Smith's work was eclipsed in the field of philosophy by Hume and Reid in Great Britain and Kant on the conti nent. Thereafter the interpretation of his writings was taken up by those who were profoundly interested in only one aspect of his work, viz., his political economy. In the process of explicating that feature of his thought the social philosophy upon which his political economy was based and of which it was but one application was at first ignored and then represented as rather simplistic. His supposed advocacy of" 'bour geois economics,' that is the economics of those economists who look with favour on working and trading and investing for personal gain" (Cannan 1926, p. 129) is generally believed to have derived from a perspective which is strongly reminiscent of the one so eloquently ex pressed by Alexander Pope in his Essay on Man. Smith is said not only to have believed that "whatever in the long run is, is right" (Campbell at 1971, p. 53), but to have based his entire Wealth Nations on another of Pope's theses. Thus God and Nature linked the gen'ral frame, and bade Self-love and Social be the same. x PREFACE Over the past half-century these and other popular caricatures of Smith's views have been shown to be distortions of the historical record (see. for example. Viner 1927; Ginzberg 1934; Bittennann 1940). Recently Wil liam Grampp found existing commentaries to be so unreliable that he simply ignored them: "There is not space enough. nor have I the incli nation to contend with [Smith's] major critics. ... I do wish to make it clear that my objection to the commentaries is that they are mistaken" (1965. vol. II. p. 4). This was certainly an over-reaction. It has been largely due to the work of a few careful scholars that we now know how misleading the popular image of Smith's social philosophy is. Before proceeding it is essential to recognize if not understand how and why so much distortion has crept into this particular chapter of intel lectual history. Unless the repeated strategic mistakes of previous students of Smith are recognized they are apt to be repeated. Fortunately these can be identified without launching into an essay on the method ology of historical research in the field of philosophy. The principal obstacles to achieving a reliable understanding of Smith's social philoso phy have been clear for some time. On the one hand. his aims have typically been neglected. Adam Smith undoubtedly started with the purpose of giving to the world a com plete social philosophy. He accomplished the greater part of his design. and yet is seldom remembered except for his economical work and only for part of that. (Bonar 1893. p. 149) The tendency of Smith's commentators to ignore or at least neglect his overall objectives and instead to be satisfied with piecemeal interpre tations may be explained in a variety of ways. Certainly one explanation is the difficulty of the task. In this connection Alexander Gray was certainly right to observe that "Adam Smith is difficult to apprehend in his totality for the perverse reason that he is in parts so regrettably well known" (1931. pp. 123-4). This. however. does not explain why his aims are neglected even when interpreting those parts of his work which are well known to every schoolboy. On the other hand Smith's interpreters frequently proceed by accom modating his views to their interests. categories and paradigms. In this connection V. W. Bladen complained of "The self-centered expectation that other economists must be striving to answer the question we ask: When the answer fails to satisfy we treat it as one more error on the part of our predecessors ..." (1960. p. 625). What Bladen does not seem to appreciate is that this tendency to interpret the expressed views of an ancestor by attempting to show how those views fit into our perspectives. answer our questions. further our objectives. has its roots in the habit PREFACE XI of what Thomas Kuhn calls "normal science" and not in some "self centered" eccentricity. Kuhn observed that those who are convinced that they have the right answers or at least are asking the right questions and are on the right track to those answers come to perceive the earlier classics in their field "as leading in a straight line to the discipline's present perspective" (1962, p. 166). This tendency is evident as early as Aristotle and as recently as Schumpeter. This, of course, does not vindi cate such practices as any less parochial than Bladen suggested. Still, such scientists oUght not to be faulted because they organized their scientific research in strict compliance with current canons of scientific practice. Their mistake lies in presuming that the canons currently ap propriate to the practice of scientific research are likewise the canons appropriate to the practice of historical research into earlier work in the same field. Wesley Mitchell recognized this and suggested that the history of economic theory "may fairly be said to be outside the field of economics, in the field of intellectual history" (1967, vol. I, p. 7). Be that as it may, it seems clear that the only reliable bases for interpreting the writings of any man, especially a philosopher, are his own interests, categories, and paradigms. My primary purpose in this volume is to present a more reliable and comprehensive account of the social philosophy of Adam Smith than is presently available. In pursuing this objective every effort is made to avoid the difficulties experienced by previous students of Smith by undertaking the interpretation of his thought from his own perspective. A sympathetic understanding of the views of a Scottish social philosopher whose active years spanned the third quarter of the eighteenth century, before western civilization had been transformed by the combined impact of the American, French, and Industrial revolutions, is not as easily attained as is commonly believed. In undertaking this project I have tried to preserve the balance and doctrinal dependencies which Smith espoused. Since the most reliable evidence of what Smith thought is what he said and especially what he wrote and published or permitted to be published under his own name, I have concentrated my efforts on his Essays on Philosophical Subjects, Theory of Moral Sentiments, "Considerations Concerning the First Formation of Languages" and Wealth of Nations. Lesser attention is given to his two sets of "lectures" and biographical data is used sparingly. Throughout I have tried to take full advantage of the sound contributions of previous students of Smith while at the same time avoiding those procedures which have proven to be sources of distortion. Finally, all speculation as to alleged influ ences on or by Smith as well as his rightful place in the history of phi- XII PREFACE losophy. economiCS. sociology. etc. is avoided. Insofar as my findings are valid these relationships appear to be in need of thorough reconsider ation. Throughout this volume I have insisted that we accommodate our interpretation of Smith·s work to his interests. methods and objectives. I know of no alternative seeing that our aim is to understand him. Still. this approach places severe strain upon the imagination of readers - especially those who are in the habit of regarding his work as an episode in the development of a currently fashionable scientific theory or politi cal attitude. Several stylistic devices have been employed in order to ease this burden. Hopefully these will also minimize the occasions of misunderstanding. to which this study is susceptible because its sympa thetic approach to Smith·s writings differs so sharply from the one we have grown accustomed to expect. First. I have treated what I take to be the essential core of any ade quate account of Smith·s social philosophy in six largely independent units each. with the exception of chapters five and six. in a sepa,rate chapter. In this way I hope to gradually introduce the reader who is acquainted with only one aspect of Smith·s work to the full range of his thought. The integrity of his total philosophical position as well as the final cogency of each of its aspects will become apparent by following out the cross-references within the text of each chapter. This is especially important in the case of chapters five and six which in many ways form the climax of this study. Second. I have. wherever considerations of accuracy permit. ap proached each unit within the context of the present state of the litera ture. In this way I have tried to maintain maximum continuity with the work of previous Smithian commentators. It was possible to follow this approach in every case except that of chapters five and six. There I preferred. for reasons already indicated. to approach the Wealth Q/ Nations from within the context of Smith·s own moral philosophy and according to his own method of inquiry. To have done otherwise would have resulted in devoting an unacceptably extended portion of those chapters to purely academic polemics. Those interested in my views on the major alternatives to my interpretation will not find them difficult to locate in the text and footnotes of those chapters. Third. I have suggested contemporary theorists whose work in certain respects parallel positions I attribute to Smith. In doing so I do not mean either to imply an "influence" or to defend the positions cited. but only to provide an additional vantage point from which readers who are acquainted with contemporary theorists might be better able to

Description:
Adam Smith was one of the most important seminal social philosophers of modern times. Although his great masterpiece - the Wealth at Nations - is most frequently associated with the field of economics, it has exer­ cised a profound and abiding influence not only in that but in all areas of social t
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.