ebook img

The rise of Christian theology and the end of ancient metaphysics : patristic philosophy from the Cappadocian Fathers to John of Damascus PDF

336 Pages·2020·1.657 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The rise of Christian theology and the end of ancient metaphysics : patristic philosophy from the Cappadocian Fathers to John of Damascus

OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi The Rise of Christian Theology and the End of Ancient Metaphysics OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi The Rise of Christian Theology and the End of Ancient Metaphysics Patristic Philosophy from the Cappadocian Fathers to John of Damascus JOHANNES ZACHHUBER 1 OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi 3 GreatClarendonStreet,Oxford,OX26DP, UnitedKingdom OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity’sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwide.Oxfordisaregisteredtrademarkof OxfordUniversityPressintheUKandincertainothercountries ©JohannesZachhuber2020 Themoralrightsoftheauthorhavebeenasserted FirstEditionpublishedin2020 Impression:1 Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced,storedin aretrievalsystem,ortransmitted,inanyformorbyanymeans,withoutthe priorpermissioninwritingofOxfordUniversityPress,orasexpresslypermitted bylaw,bylicenceorundertermsagreedwiththeappropriatereprographics rightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproductionoutsidethescopeofthe aboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment,OxfordUniversityPress,atthe addressabove Youmustnotcirculatethisworkinanyotherform andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer PublishedintheUnitedStatesofAmericabyOxfordUniversityPress 198MadisonAvenue,NewYork,NY10016,UnitedStatesofAmerica BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData Dataavailable LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2019954007 ISBN 978–0–19–885995–6 PrintedandboundinGreatBritainby ClaysLtd,ElcografS.p.A. LinkstothirdpartywebsitesareprovidedbyOxfordingoodfaithand forinformationonly.Oxforddisclaimsanyresponsibilityforthematerials containedinanythirdpartywebsitereferencedinthiswork. OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi 1 Introduction The Christian writers of late antiquity are famous for their foundational and decisive contribution to the formation of the Church’s teaching. Rarely has it been recognized, however, that they also pursued an ambitious and exciting philosophical project alongside their engagement in the doctrinal controversies oftheirage.Inthisbook,IwillforthefirsttimeofferafullanalysisofthisPatristic philosophy.Iwillshowhowittookitsdistinctiveshapeinthelatefourthcentury and give an account of its subsequent development until the time of John of Damascus. In this Introduction, I will outline the approach taken, explain the selection of authors that will be examined, and give a précis of my overall argument. 1.1 Patristic Thought as Christian Philosophy For a long time, early Christian thought has been connected with ancient phil- osophy mainly in order to explore its sources and to show how the Fathers depended on the insights of pagan thinkers from Plato and Aristotle in the classicalperiod,toPlotinusandProclusinlateantiquity.¹Scholarswhodisagreed with this assessment would do so by emphasizing the incompatibility between ChristianfaithandGreekphilosophywhetherwithaviewtocensureChristianity foritslackofrationalityortoinsistonitsgenuinelyreligiouscharacter.² Morerecently,scholarsofbothhistoricaltheologyandancientphilosophyhave rightly challenged the stark dichotomy of Patristic thought and ancient philoso- phy that underlay either of these traditional approaches. Instead, Christian authors have increasingly been treated as part of the late antique intellectual world and as philosophers in their own right. In this vein, Patristic accounts of creation, forexample,havesuccessfully beenreconstructed inthecontextoflate ancient philosophical cosmologies rather thanan entirely separate undertaking.³ ¹ Classical treatments along those lines include Chadwick (1966); Armstrong/Markus (1960); Ivanka(1964). ² FortheviewthatChristianitywasunduly‘hellenized’throughtheinfluenceofpaganphilosophy cf. Harnack (1976). The case for Christianity as an anti-intellectual force has most recently been restatedinNixey(2017). ³ E.g.Köckert(2009);Karamanolis(2014),ch.2. TheRiseofChristianTheologyandtheEndofAncientMetaphysics:PatristicPhilosophyfromtheCappadocianFathersto JohnofDamascus.JohannesZachhuber,OxfordUniversityPress(2020).©JohannesZachhuber. DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198859956.001.0001 OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi 2      Christian views of the soul, of time, or of the will have similarly been treated alongsidethoseheldbytheirnon-Christianphilosophicalpeers.⁴ TheaccountIwillgiveinthisstudyfollowsthistrajectoryyetextendsittothe very heart of Christian theology. The philosophy whose history will here be recounted is found directly in texts engaging with the central doctrines of the ChristianChurch,namely,theTrinityandChristology.Thisraiseswide-ranging and fundamental questions of terminology, method, and the disciplinary cast of thepresentstudy.Howcandoctrinalquestionsyieldphilosophicalinsightsgiven that they are based on authoritative decisions taken at the institutional level, usually by synods and councils? Conversely, if philosophical categories are used toanalysedoctrinaldebatesinlateantiquity,whatroomdoesthisleavefortheir claimthattheyreflectdivinerevelation? Partofmyanswertoquestionsofthiskindiscontainedintheverylanguageof Patristic or Christian philosophy which will be employed throughout this study. Itsmainpurposeistostemthedualistictendencyinherentintheconventionaluse of theology and philosophy as quasi-disciplinary designators. It is important to recall that this distinction has its origin in the medieval university with separate faculties of philosophy and theology.⁵ Since then, it has become seemingly self- evidentandis,therefore,appliedtohistoricalresearchonearlierperiodsaswell.It is,however,anillfitforthefirstmillennium.Whilepaganintellectualsoftendid notthinkhighlyofChristianity,theyfounditnaturaltoclassifyitasaphilosophy, albeit an inferior one, rather than as religion.⁶ The new faith was simply too different from traditional Greek or Roman cults. Christian writers, too, often referredtotheirownactivityasphilosophy,usuallyqualifiedastruephilosophy, truewisdom,ortrueknowledge.⁷ It is therefore arguable that the emerging intellectual culture of late ancient Christianitycanbeconceptualizedasakindofphilosophywithinthelateancient contextofapluralityofphilosophicalschools.⁸Itsrelationshiptothephilosophies ofPlatonismorStoicismwillthenappearanalogoustotheonethoseschoolshad amongsteachother.Dependenceandcritique,polemicalrejectionandtheaccept- ance of shared principles will no longer appear mutually exclusive or even contradictory.Moreimportantlyperhaps,noneofthoseobservationswillinitself feed ideological narratives of Christianity as an anti-philosophical force or, indeed,of‘hellenization’asabetrayalofthepurityofthegospel. ⁴ Cf.Karamanolis(2014).Seealsoesp.onthesoul:Ramelli(2007);ontime:Sorabji(1983);onthe will:Frede(2012). ⁵ Cf.Geyer(1964);Pannenberg(1973),11–12.Fortheuseoftheologiainantiquitycf.theoverview inMarkschies(2015),ch.1. ⁶ Cf.e.g.Galen,Plat.dial.comp.(150Kopf). ⁷ Fordetailedreferencessee:Bardy(1949).Forafullaccountofthetransformationoftheterm ‘philosophy’duringthisperiodcf.Malingrey(1961). ⁸ Zachhuber(2020a). OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi  3 ThisnotionofPatristictheologyasaphilosophicalschoolbecomesevenmore plausiblewhenthespecificcharacterofancientphilosophyistakenintoaccount: itsacceptanceofauthoritativetextsanditspracticeofcommentingonthem;⁹its institutionalization in schools whose heads derived their authority by direct descent (diadoche) from the school’s founder;¹⁰ its embeddedness in a specific formofethicalexistence,asinfluentiallyemphasizedbyPierreHadot.¹¹Inother words,whileitmayseemcounterintuitivetodaytoconsiderChristianthoughtasa philosophy,lateancientphilosophy,aspointedoutbyArthurDarbyNockmany yearsago,wouldstrikeamodernobserverasrathersimilartothekindofreligion thathasdominatedtheWestforthepast1500years.¹² In this sense, Patristic thought as a whole can be identified as Christian philosophy. In the present book, however, the term Christian or Patristic phil- osophywillgenerallybetakeninamorerestrictedsensesignifyingasetoflogical andontologicalconceptsunderlyingthearticulationofdoctrinalstatements.Such a philosophical system can be found in the Eastern Fathers from the end of the fourth century. These theories, then, are not themselves doctrinal; they can be appreciated or indeed critiqued independently of the affirmation of the doctrine they are meant to support. Thus far, they can be understood as properly philo- sophical. And yet, the argumentative purpose for which they were developed clearly influenced their shape. As philosophies, they were from the outset inscribed into the intellectual attempt to give a reasoned account of the Christianfaithas expressedthrough anumberof credaland doctrinal formulae. In this sense, these intellectual systems can be understood as Christian philoso- phies.As willbecome apparent, a considerable numberof Patristic authors took seriously the need to underpin their doctrinal standpoint by such a system of termsandconcepts.Itisthestoryoftheirworkthatwillbetoldinthisbook. Howcantheriseofthisphilosophybeexplainedandunderstood?Onemajor factor,undoubtedly,wasthedecisionoftheCouncilFathersofthefourthandfifth centuriestoadoptfortheformulationofthemostcentraldoctrinesofChristianity termsthatcouldnotbefoundintheBibleor,atleast,werenotusedinitinany technical sense. As soon as central tenets of the Christian faith were defined throughwordssuchasousia,physis,andhypostasis,theexposition,justification, and defence of these doctrines had to resort to definitions and arguments of an increasinglytechnicalnature. Importantthoughtheseinstitutionaldecisionswere,itisarguablethatanother factorwasequallyinfluentialinensuringtheemergenceofPatristicphilosophyas described above. Doctrines are often considered as static affirmations of certain ⁹ Betegh(2011),26–8;Sorabji(1990),1–30;Finamore/Johnston(2011). ¹⁰ Campenhausen(1963),esp.175. ¹¹ Hadot(1995).Cf.Hadot(2004),240forhisinterpretationofancientChristianityasphilosophyin thissense. ¹² Nock(1933).IamgratefultoProf.MarkEdwardswhomademeawareofNock’sbook. OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi 4      truths;traditionaltheologyconsideredthemasdivinelyrevealed,whereashistor- ianstendtothinkofthemasimposedbyinstitutionalauthority.Theverywords ‘doctrine’ or ‘dogma’ to us suggest rigidity and inflexibility. Such a perception overlooks,however,thatthedoctrinesoflateancientChristianitywerenotsimply promulgated and accepted but fiercely debated, rejected, and defended. A major space,therefore,inwhichphilosophicaldevelopmentoccurredwasinthedebates and controversies about doctrine that were such a central part of Christian literaturethroughouttheperiodcoveredinthisbook. In other words, Christian authors could not avoid embedding their doctrinal confessions about the Trinity and of the Person of Jesus Christ into a termino- logical and conceptual system whose validity did not directly depend on the acceptance of these doctrines, because they were faced by opponents unwilling to accept their own dogmatic formula. The trinitarian controversy of the fourth century was therefore the incubator for the first and most influential version of this Patristic philosophy. Subsequently, it was largely the debate about Christology,whichstubbornlycontinuedforcenturies,thatstimulatedconceptual clarificationsandmodificationsoftheoriginalfourth-centurytheory. Recognizing the importance of doctrinal polemics for the development of Patristicphilosophy inevitably highlights theextentto which itshistory wasone of unintended consequences. Wide-reaching philosophical decisions concern- ing, for example, the status of universals or the constitution of the individual being, were often caused by the need to find rationalizations for a doctrinal position an author simply had to defend. As we shall see, this was particularly thecaseforsixth-centuryChalcedonianswhostruggledtojustifytheunpopular formula of the Council of Chalcedon against a barrage of well-articulated criticisms and in doing so became rather innovative and inventive in their philosophicalideas. In line with the often-haphazard character of philosophical developments among Patristic authors is the observation of the plurality of forms it assumed. Those scholars who have treated Patristic thought as part of the history of philosophy have usually seen it as one or, at least, as converging towards one unified vision in line with the supposed unity of Christian doctrine emerging during this historical epoch. In reality, its plurality rapidly increased as the centurieswenton,andthereisnoindicationthatbythetimethepresentaccount comes toits close this tendencyhad come to a halt.The primary reason for this increasingpluralizationwasthefragmentationofEasternChristianityduringthis epoch, as the attempt to settle the Christological controversy through doctrinal formulae led to the permanent establishment of rival ecclesiastical communities across the Eastern Mediterranean. Yet even Chalcedonian attempts to develop a philosophicalvisioninlinewiththelanguagemandatedbytheCouncilof451did not result in unanimity but in several, rather different but equally fascinating philosophies. OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi  5 Despite this plurality, some major patterns will emerge from the analysis of these developments. There is a venerable tradition in philosophical historiog- raphy, most prominently represented by G. W. F. Hegel, that has assigned philosophical significance to the doctrinal development of late antiquity on the grounds that doctrine itself was philosophical.¹³ More recently, it has been the claim ofEasternOrthodoxthinkerssuch as Vladimir Lossky andJohnZizioulas thatPatristicthinkersbroughtaboutanontologicalrevolutionwhilearticulating thedoctrineoftheTrinityinparticular.¹⁴ Whiletheapproachinthisstudywillberatherdifferentfromthese,theoverall result will partly converge with such earlier assessments. I will show that by the end of the Patristic period philosophical ideas had been generated that were far away fromconsensusviewsthatprevailedamong mostpaganphilosophers.The term ‘ontological revolution’, thus far, is not far-fetched. Yet the revolutionary philosophyisnotthefourth-centurysystemestablishedbyBasilofCaesareaand GregoryofNyssa,asLosskyandZizioulasopined;rather,itwastheChristological controversythatledChristianthinkerstotheadoptionofincreasinglyinnovative intellectualassumptions. 1.2 From the Cappadocians to John of Damascus TheparticularapproachtoPatristicphilosophytakeninthisbookdeterminesits chronologicalscope.Thereisno doubtthatChristianwriters prior tothefourth centuries can legitimately be classed as philosophers; in fact, thinkers such as Justin Martyr and Origen who operated as independent teachers, may more plausibly be compared to contemporaneous philosophers than their later des- cendants in the fourth or sixth centuries.¹⁵ Histories of Patristic philosophy therefore rightly begin with these thinkers or, even earlier, with the Gnostic schools of the second century.¹⁶ Important works have even restricted their scopeofenquirytothefirstthreecenturiesonthegroundsthatChristianthought during this period was less impacted by external, political pressures than during theensuingageofstate–churchalliance.¹⁷ YethoweverphilosophicalearlierFathersmayhavebeen,itisarguablethatasa distinctiveandrecognizableentityChristianphilosophyonlyemergedintheEast at the end of the fourth century. As such, it owes its existence to the so-called ¹³ Cf.Hodgson(2005). ¹⁴ Lossky(1944),27;Zizioulas(2004),36:‘WhatdoesitmeantosaythatGodisFather,Sonand SpiritwithoutceasingtobeoneGod?Thehistoryofthedisputeswhichbrokeoutonthisgreattheme [...]includesaphilosophicallandmark,arevolutioninGreekphilosophy.Thisrevolutionisexpressed historicallythroughanidentification:theidentificationofthe“hypostasis”withthe“person”.’ ¹⁵ ForJustinasaphilosophercf.hisDial.1–9(90–101Goodspeed).ForOrigen,cf.Ep.adGreg.1 (40,10–41,6Koetschau). ¹⁶ NotablyMoreschini(2004). ¹⁷ Karamanolis(2014),27. OUPCORRECTEDAUTOPAGEPROOFS–FINAL,16/4/2020,SPi 6      Cappadocian theologians, Basil ofCaesarea,Gregory ofNazianzus, and Gregory ofNyssa.¹⁸Thesethree,andespeciallyBasilandGregoryofNyssa,integratedtheir proposedsettlementtothetrinitariancontroversy intoaninnovativeandclearly defined set of terms and concepts. On this basis, they spoke of the Trinity as a single substance or ousia in three consubstantial hypostases thus coining the formula that was to become recognized orthodoxy from the Council of Constantinople in 381 onwards. Moreover, Gregory of Nyssa applied the same conceptual language also to a range of other doctrinal topics including creation, salvation,andtheeschatologicalresurrectionandrestorationofhumankind.¹⁹In this way, Cappadocian philosophy permitted for the first time the systematic integration of many doctrinal topics into one systematic whole. Christology, however,wasnotoneofthem:afactthatwastohavegraveconsequences. Withinasurprisinglyshorttime,thisphilosophybecamewidelysharedacross the East. In this book, I will therefore refer to it as the ‘classical theory’. By this Imeanthatitsacceptancewasfromthebeginningnotasignofschoolaffiliation but became a sort of intellectual koine. From all the evidence we have, it seems clear that the Cappadocian heritage was never tied to a distinctive part of the EasternChurch.Cappadocianthoughtwasneitherconcentratedincertainareas, as Antiochene and Alexandrian theologies were, nor was it connected with particularintellectualmilieusaswasthecase withtheinheritanceofOrigenand EvagriusofPontus.Instead,Cappadocianpatternsofthoughtandargumenttook afoundationalplaceinthewritingofallmajortheologiansoftheEastonlyafew decades after Gregory of Nyssa codified this novel philosophy around the year380. The near-total absence of reliable texts from the decades following the Theodosian settlement of the 380s makes it impossible, for the time being, to trace this remarkable success-story in any detail, but it is a matter of historical recordthat,attheoutbreakoftheChristologicalcontroversyinthelate420s,all sidesalreadytookforgrantedtheuseofCappadocianphilosophytoarticulateand rationalizetheirvariousdoctrinalpositions.²⁰Whileneveragainlosingthisstatus, the Cappadocian theory subsequently came under strain when individuals employed it—or sought to employ it—to justify the particular positions they took in the increasingly entrenched debate about the doctrine of the Person of JesusChrist. Thistendencybecamepronouncedfromtheearlysixthcentury.Inmanyways, the main object of this book’s narrative is the dramatic intellectual realignment that ensued from this decision. Different groups emerging during this period soughttocapitalizeontheauthoritativestatustheCappadociantheoryhadgained by explaining their Christologies on its basis. This, however, was never possible ¹⁸ SeeChapter2. ¹⁹ Zachhuber(1999). ²⁰ SeeChapter3,section3.1.1.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.