ebook img

The Rhetoric of Powell's Bakke PDF

21 Pages·2017·1.26 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Rhetoric of Powell's Bakke

WWaasshhiinnggttoonn aanndd LLeeee LLaaww RReevviieeww Volume 38 Issue 1 Article 4 Winter 1-1-1981 TThhee RRhheettoorriicc ooff PPoowweellll''ss BBaakkkkee Lewis H. LaRue Washington and Lee University School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu/wlulr Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons RReeccoommmmeennddeedd CCiittaattiioonn Lewis H. LaRue, The Rhetoric of Powell's Bakke, 38 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 43 (1981). Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu/wlulr/vol38/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Washington and Lee Law Review at Washington and Lee University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington and Lee Law Review by an authorized editor of Washington and Lee University School of Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE RHETORIC OF POWELL'S BAKKE L. H. LARuE* By now, much has been written on the Bakke case,' and particularly on Justice Lewis Powell's opinion. Even so, much more needs to be writ- ten, for much is at stake. Consequently, we should turn away from legalisms and turn ourselves towards the different ways in which the opinion persuades or fails to persuade. Why study the opinion as an act of persuasion, as a piece of rhetoric? We are all familiar with the trivial commonplace that judicial opinions are not very good reports of how and why the judge reached a decision. Opinions do not report the order in which the judge learned things, nor the work done to solve the problems of the case. Instead, an opinion ex- plains and justifies in a different sort of way: we do not get very much of the biography of the decision; we generally get only an argument that the decision is correct. However, the fact that judicial opinions are, in part, attempts to per- suade does no more than make rhetorical analysis possible. The real question is whether such analysis is desirable. One can differ on this, but one very important question about an argument is: what sort of world does it assume that we live in?; or that we should live in? This question can be restated in a more personal and less abstract way by asking: what sort of people will we become if we are persuaded by this argument?; what sort of community will we have for our sharing? I. Part I of the opinion is the statement of facts, some of which are well known. The Medical School of the University of California at Davis had a "6special admissions program." The Medical School received about 3,000 applicants a year for admission; there were 100 places in each class. If applicants were to be selected for admission on the basis of indexing numbers such as Grade Point Average (GPA) or the Medical College Ad- missions Test (MCAT), then few or no blacks would be admitted. In order to avoid this result, the faculty voted to reserve sixteen places in each class for "disadvantaged" or "minority group" applicants, a category that included Negroes, Chicanos, Asians, and American Indians. Allan Bakke, a Caucasian, who had a strong record based on his GPA and MCAT, applied and was denied admission; he sued. A statement of facts can be put together in many different ways, and the persuasiveness of a judicial opinion can be increased or decreased * Professor of Law, Washington & Lee University; A.B. 1958, Washington & Lee University; LL.B. 1962, Harvard University. ' Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265 (1978). 44 WASHINGTON AND LEE LAW REVIEW [Vol. XXXVII markedly by the skill with which the statement of facts has been assembled. One of the ways in which this statement of facts can have an impact is by unsettling expectations. In the first place, most judicial observers knew, or thought they knew, the facts of Bakke; but Justice Powell's statement of facts takes approximately nine pages.2 This can persuade by disarming; one is met with facts as to which one was ig- norant, and this may have the effect of inducing some lessening of preconceptions. On another level, the length of the statement of facts might by association of ideas lead one to posit care in the author of the opinion and thus give rise to some presumption of credibility. Aside from this subliminal persuasion by length, are there any other parts of the statement of facts that might appeal to the reader? Several pages' of Powell's statement of facts are devoted to showing how qualified Bakke was. For example, when he first applied in 1973, his qualifications, judging by grades and test scores, were as good as most of those who were admitted, and in 1974, he was clearly better. However, he had complained about the special admissions program in 1974 and the Dean to whom he complained was his faculty interviewer. The Dean gave him a low rating and after he was rejected, the Dean did not exercise his discretion to put Bakke on the waiting list. When I read those facts, am I supposed to conclude that Bakke was unfairly treated? If so, what about the omission of any mention of these facts when the ra- tionale of the decision is explained? II. In the second part of the opinion, Justice Powell, in a lawyer-like fashion, takes up a statutory issue before he reaches the constitutional problem. As a performance, this enacts the values of caution and restraint, and so it might be expected to have some persuasive value by increasing our confidence in Justice Powell. However, one suspects that most readers of the opinion had too much prior knowledge for Part II to work in this way. One knows that it is a constitutional case; one already knows from the newspapers that it was not disposed of on statutory grounds; and so the average reader probably thumbs through these pages rather quickly, not attending to any of the details of the language or of the argument. III. Most readers probably begin to pay close attention in Part III when they sense that the opinion is now settling into the key constitutional issue. The delay in getting this far perhaps has piqued interest, has in- 2 Id at 272-81. Id. at 276-77. Id at 288. ' 1981] RHETORIC OF POWELL'S BAKKE creased tension and suspense. In Part III, Powell begins by stating the issues, posing them by way of a report on the parties' disagreement. The issue, as stated, is whether or not there should be strict scrutiny of the racial classification used in the Davis plan. In the next two paragraphs, he turns aside from this issue to a separate one: he states that the par- ties disagree as to the "proper characterization of the special admissions program."' The school called it a goal, Bakke called it a quota. Powell's response is to say: "this semantic distinction is beside the point."5 He asserts that whatever you call it, it is a classification based on race. As a piece of rhetoric, this was a nice move. The semantic distinction conceals a larger issue. Quota has a nasty ring to it, whereas goal sounds more harmless. By finessing the point, and saying that it is a classifica- tion, Powell creates the impression that he is not a man to be bogged down in trivia or quibbles, but one who wishes to get to the larger issues of principle that are at stake. One nods in agreement, and, of course, it is always good strategy for a writer to start with statements with which the audience will agree. But before these larger issues of principle can be decided, some preliminary matters are relevant. Powell asserts: "The guarantees of the Fourteenth Amendment extend to all persons."8 However, even ac- cepting this conclusion, there is a subtle ambiguity: on the one hand, there is the question of the persons protected by the equal protection clause, that is, whether the entire population can claim rights under that clause; on the other hand, there is the question of the content of the rights created by the equal protection clause, that is, whether all members of the population have the same -sorts of rights protected by that clause. Powell addresses this issue by reporting it as an argument that is advanced by the lawyers; he reports that they argue that "white males, such as [Bakke], are not a 'discrete and insular minority' requiring extra- ordinary protection from the majoritarian political process."7 Powell's response is that the cases do not hold that minority status is a necessary prerequisite to strict scrutiny and that racial distinctions have been declared suspect without expressing any qualifications as to minority status.' If is, of course, true that the cases say what Powell says that they say, at least in the sense that the language that he quotes is indeed in the opinions from which he quotes them. However, it is also true that, on the facts, these cases did involve discriminations that were invidious and hostile and that fell with harsh force upon a group that could be fairly Id. at 289. 6Id. TI d at 290. Id. at 291; see, e.g., Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 216 (1944); Kirabayashi v. United States, 320 U.S. 81, 100 (1943). 46 WASHINGTON AND LEE LAW REVIEW [Vol. XXXVIII described as a discrete minority. In these cases, the judges have tended to avoid harsh characterizations. Brown v. Board of Education9 con- stitutes the very paradigm of this bland style. The judges who wrote these opinions wanted to lower tempers, not raise them, and so they adopted a rhetorical style that seemed appropriate to that end. Moreover, they perhaps saw their job as educating the public into higher aspirations, and so they stated the principles of decision in terms of abstract aspirations which could be future goals. The rhetorical strategy here has often seemed to be an attempt to change the facts for the future by moderating one's description of the facts of the past; the plea for the future being a plea for moderation, the facts as to the past have typically been described in moderate language. However, this strategy left an opening to Powell. He is able to claim that the generality of the language in these opinions constitutes the actual holding of the cases. In studying this rhetorical technique, the most important thing we should notice is that the technique of the argument corresponds with the desired result. The result is to be that racial distinctions are suspect without regard to historical context. It fits with this result to argue from the words of prior cases without using the context of those words. However, Lewis Powell understands that persuasion requires more than citation of authority, and so he asserts in Part III.B. of his opinion that his conclusion "is rooted in our nation's constitutional and demographic history."0" In support of this thesis, he offers approximately four pages of history. The history begins with a paragraph about the history of the four- teenth amendment as interpreted by the Supreme Court. He points out that the earliest cases interpreting the equal protection clause stated that it was enacted for the protection of the newly freed slaves. He ad- mits that judges in fact failed to keep this promise of protection of the freedmen and instead turned away from the equal protection clause to the due process clause, which they used for the protection of business. He claims that only in modern times has the Court abandoned its use of the due process clause to impose substantive economic doctrines upon a legislature and begun to use the equal protection clause as an important source of restraint upon political action. A possible response to this story could be to assert that it was now time to revive the original and correct interpretation. However the next paragraph starts off with a rather different proposition. "By that time it was no longer possible to peg the guarantees of the Fourteenth Amend- ment to the struggle for equality of one racial minority."'1 Of course, one cannot turn back the clock; we can never make time or history run ' 347 U.S. 483 (1954). ,o4 38 U.S. at 291. " Id. at 292. 1981] RHETORIC OF POWELL'S BAKKE backwards. If indeed, history has made it impossible to revive the original understanding, then we should not do it. What counts for impossibility? There are two strands to Powell's argument. First, the original interpretation was itself not historically necessary, since the text permits a much broader interpretation. Second, the continued flow of immigration into the country has made our nation a nation of minorities. Logically, there are several ways of using this evidence. If immigration has indeed brought other minorities to our shores, then one can use the broad language of the equal protection clause as authorization to extend its substantive protections to them also. The question would be whether their case is fairly analogous. Thus, if some racial or ethnic group could show that it was suffering from in- vidious and hostile discrimination of the sort that the freed slaves suf- fered under, then a case would be made for extending the protections of the clause to them. In short, the historical events that are cited by Powell do nothing more than establish another historical problem. They do not establish that the historical context of racial distinctions should be irrelevant. Having argued from authority and from history, Powell next makes an argument based upon institutional limits. Starting from the assertion that our nation is multi-racial and multi-ethnic, he proceeds to the obser- vation that a person's status is not a permanent feature of the political landscape but one that can shift as we locate individuals in time and place, in history and geography. In this context, the Court has no prin- cipled way of judging to whom special solicitude may justly be given. His own words are: "The kind of variable sociological and political analysis necessary to produce such rankings simply does not lie within the judicial competence.... . 2 Does this mean that judges cannot understand history? Justice Powell's next step is to link this argument about institu- tional competence with grand theories about the constitution itself. He states: "By hitching the meaning of the Equal Protection Clause to these transitory considerations, we would be holding, as a constitutional prin- ciple, that judicial scrutiny of classifications touching on racial and ethnic background may vary with the ebb and flow of political forces."1 Powell offers the following as a reason for believing that such variability is bad: "Also, the mutability of constitutional principle, based upon shift- ing political and social judgments, undermines the chances for consistent application of the Constitution from one generation to the next, a critical feature of its coherent interpretation."'" And he cites Archibald Cox for the proposition that, "In expounding the Constitution, the Court's role is to discern principles sufficiently absolute to give them roots throughout Id. at 297. 12 13I d- at 298. Id. at 299. " 48 WASHINGTON AND LEE LAW REVIEW [Vol. XXXVIII the community and continuity over significant periods of time, and to lift them above the level of the pragmatic political judgments of a particular 15 time and place. The problem with discerning such principles is that we cannot see into the future and know what principles will have continuity in the generations to come. Indeed, predicting the future course of history would seem far more difficult than understanding the present historical context of racial discrimination. Even so, this rhetoric can persuade by appealing to that great American hope. that the law can be above politics. The Constitution is a symbol of the continuity of the nation, and judicial independence is the political technique for guaranteeing that this symbol of continuity is not dragged down into partisan politics. This symbolic need is so deep in the American imagination as to be above argument. Unfortunately, it does not fit well with the facts. The Burger Court has not maintained smooth historical continuity with the decisions of the Warren Court, but has made some abrupt departures. And of course, the Warren Court in its turn did what it could to bury the legacy of the Vinson Court and establish its own vision. Indeed, one could go back further, drawing other lines of division and break, seeing the Con- stitutional history of our country in terms of discontinuity and not con- tinuity. Should we wish to escape from these historical facts? In this connection, it is useful to recall some words of John Marshall. In Marbury v. Madison,16 he asserted: "It is a proposition too plain to be contested, that the constitution controls any legislative act repugnant to it; or, that the legislature may alter the constitution by an ordinary act. Between these alternatives there is no middle ground. The constitution is either a superior, paramount law, unchangeable by ordinary means, or it is on a level with ordinary legislative acts, and, like other acts, is alterable when the legislature shall please to alter it."'7 Powell's contrast of the permanent versus the transitory finds its roots in John Marshall's rhetoric about change. Despite the fact that both arguments are equally nonsensical, they are both equally per- suasive. My own experience of teaching Marbury v. Madison is that this is the single most persuasive part of Marshall's opinion to the average student. When I teach the case, I often ask students what arguments they can offer in defense of judicial review. There are numerous arguments that are offered, many of which are different from, and perhaps better than, those offered by Marshall. However, once I limit the students and get them to distinguish between the arguments that they have offered and those that Marshall offers, then they choose more often than not Marshall's remarks about the unchangeable Constitution. However, the practical issue is who is to have the final say as to the ,Id. (quoting A. Cox, THE ROLE OF THE SUPREME COURT IN AMERICAN GOVERNMENT 114 (1976)). , 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803). " Id- at 177. 1981] RHETORIC OF POWELL'S BAKKE constitutionality of a piece of legislation: the legislature or the court. It is true, as John Marshall said, that if the legislature has the final say, then the legislature can change the Constitution, for all practical pur- poses, by the ordinary act of passing a statute. What John Marshall failed to point out is that if the Supreme Court has the final say, then it can change the Constitution by the ordinary act of deciding a case. Further- more, one can see that they have done it. As a practical matter, the issue is not whether the Constitution will change. The only practical issue is to whom we should trust the power of changing the Constitution: the Con- gress, or the Supreme Court. Alternatively, we might sometimes trust one, sometimes the other. A question like this one can not be decided by logic. The political question of whether the Supreme Court or the Congress should be able to change the Constitution must have a political answer and not a logical one. It also seems to be true that-political questions get tangled with rhetorical questions: I do not mean that rhetoric will shape politics or vice versa, but that it is hard to distinguish the two. If we give judges the responsibility for changing the Constitution, we shall have to argue about changes with a different sort of rhetoric. This seems to entail that our basic political questions include a question of how we should talk. In Part III.C., Powell returns to case analysis. Lawyers for the university had cited precedents in which preferential classifications,"5 were approved without being subjected to strict scrutiny.19 Powell dealt with these cases by distinguishing each of them. Of course, the cases cited were in fact distinguishable; cases generally are." Powell is surely correct when he says that the problems involved in those cases were altogether different from the problem involved in the case at bar. Even so, the performance is rather shabby; earlier he picked out language from cases without reference to their facts, and he then used the language as authority for the proposition that a classification alone, without regard to its hostility or invidiousness, should trigger strict scrutiny. In this section, he refuses to generalize in this way, but instead he demands that cases be read in light of their facts and understood in light of the particular context. This schizophrenia in technique seems to presuppose amnesia in the reader. IV. Having established to his own satisfaction that strict scrutiny is ap- propriate, Powell next states what this entails: "We have held that in " "Preferential classifications" are classifications that operate to the advantage of a minority group, rather than to its detriment. " See, e.g., Califano v. Webster, 430 U.S. 316 (1977) (gender based classifications); Franks v. Bowman Transp., Co., 424 U.S. 747 (1976) (racial classifications as remedy for employment discrimination); Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Educ., 402 U.S. 1 (1971) (racial classifications in school desegregation). 438 U.S. at 300-05. 50 WASHINGTON AND LEE LAW REVIEW [Vol. XXXVIII 'order to justify the use of a suspect classification, a State must show that its purpose or interest is both constitutionally permissible and substantial, and that its use of the classification is 'necessary ... to the accomplishment' of its purpose or the safeguarding of its interest."'21 This is the orthodox two-prong test: examine the end; test the fitness of means to end. This sort of rhetoric does not persuade everyone. First, there are reasons for doubting the whole enterprise. It is a curious anthropomor- phism to imagine that a 'law' or a 'state' is the sort of thing that can have a purpose. Of course, the people who enact laws can and do have pur- poses. To establish what purposes different people had when they engaged in lawmaking and the degree to which those different persons had common or disparate purposes requires that one engage in a difficult historical inquiry. One can doubt whether the court is searching for something that is existent, and even if it is existent, one can criticize the skill with which the search is conducted. Despite these criticisms, there are numerous rhetorical appeals in an argument such as this. One appeal arises from its analogy to scientific and technological talk, which is, of course, an important part of our civilization. In technology, this sort of argument is called means-end ra- tionality, and there are those who are tempted to identify rationality solely with this way of proceeding. By association, an argument cast in this form can seem rigorous. Since dispassionate logical rigor is one of the forms that judicial independence can take, this form of argument perhaps has some resonance with many people's image of the ap- propriate judicial role. A second source of persuasiveness can be the analogues which this argument has in ordinary life. We are often met with the quandry of what to do when someone proposes to do something with which we are uneasy, and yet we do not wish to give an outright No as an answer. We often try to avoid giving either a Yes or No, but instead attempt to reshape the proposal; we quite often open our persuasion by asking ques- tions such as: What are you trying to do?; Is this really the most impor- tant thing to you? Such rhetorical moves are often quite effective: it may force a redescription; it may open avenues for negotiation. As a result of such questions, we are often able to say such things as: you can do the same thing in another way, and done in this other way, you will not be doing those things that are offensive to us; or, why don't you leave out some of these things that are not really centrally important to you, especially since these less important things are what make your pro- posal offensive to us. The appeal is to moderate behavior, to reasonable- ness. This is a powerful appeal as it works in ordinary life, and a judicial opinion that embodies it will strike us most likely as persuasive. "1I d. at 305 (quoting In re Griffiths, 413 U.S. 717, 721-22 (1973)). 19811 RHETORIC OF POWELL'S BAKKE For my purposes, the test is less important than the way it is used. First, I must emphasize that the purposes that Powell discusses have not been established by evidence as matters of historical fact. They exist only in the world of litigation. Perhaps a more realistic way of viewing them would be to use the word 'excuses' instead of the word 'purposes.' Viewed in this way, Powell's way of proceeding can be seen to overlap with ordinary life. When we are challenged for doing what we have done, we often try to justify it by offering excuses. These excuses do not constitute the biography of our action. The reason for this is sim- ple enough: we often do not know exactly why we have done the things that we have done. The real reasons for action perhaps can never be known, but we can ask whether there are good reasons, whether' we are justified in doing what we have done. There are dangers in doing this. Hypocrisy can be encouraged; one can be led into talking about one's life as though it were an abstract intellectual problem, as opposed to something one must live. But at times we know of no other way to pro- ceed. Here too, we might be persuaded that Powell is proceeding cor- rectly. He does not know, and perhaps there is no way to find out, exactly why the medical faculty of Davis did what it did. So he can consider various hypothetical reasons why they might have done what they did, and then he can judge the action in this hypothetical mode. Of course, we must still have some expectation that the hypotheses are not altogether removed from reality. Four purposes ('excuses'?) are stated, the first being "'reducing the historic deficit of traditionally disfavored minorities in medical schools and in the medical profession.'""2 However within one page it is restated as follows: "If petitioner's purpose is to assure within its student body some specified percentage of a particular group merely because of its race or ethnic origin, such a preferential purpose must be regarded not as insubstantial but as facially invalid. Preferring members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic origin is discrimination for its own sake."" This appears to change rather substantially the state- ment of purpose as originally hypothesized. As restated, Powell makes it appear as though the first purpose is including blacks because of a mere preference for blacks as such. However, the purpose as originally stated was related to a particular historical problem. We see here in microcosm one of the problems of translating the or- dinary means-end rationality of technology into the classification- purpose rhetoric of constitutional law. When one states a purpose, it is hard to get it to stand still. Technological ends can be clearly stated. Purposes are hard to state, and we see here how their vagueness of statement can lead to subtle shifts of language that seem to make a dif- 438 U.S. at 306 (quoting Brief for Petitioner, Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265 (1978)). 438 U.S. at 307.

Description:
tial difference since the issue of history is raised in the next subpart of the opinion. cept of injury that may be ageless in its reach into the past. 126.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.